Добавил:
Upload Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:
david_Introduction_to_behavioral_economics.pdf
Скачиваний:
50
Добавлен:
26.03.2016
Размер:
12.18 Mб
Скачать

 

 

 

 

Rational Explanations for Flat-Rate Bias

 

33

 

Rational Explanations for Flat-Rate Bias

Two primary rational explanations have been given for the at-rate bias. The rst supposes that consumers might not actually know the amount of use they are projected to have. Given this uncertainty about use, they might opt for the xed-price plan to avoid the uncertain cost of consumption. For example, it may be that one occasionally uses a cell phone extensively, whereas in a normal month one might only use a few minutes. Expected utility theory suggests that a consumer may be willing to reduce the average payout of a gamble in return for eliminating the uncertainty. The at-rate bias could be explained by the same phenomenon where consumers are willing to pay a larger amount on average to ensure that they are certain of the eventual total cost. In this case, although future use is a decision variable rather than an externally determined random variable, the value of the calls may be random. Thus, one might buy the xed-price option because of the value of the option to place more calls without facing a penalty. Kridel, Lehman, and Weisman nd that this appears to be a good explanation for many of the apparent mistakes in pricing choices.

Eugenio Miravete claims that there is little evidence of incorrect choices to begin with. He uses a survey of telephone customersanticipated and actual use of services in Kentucky to determine the extent of such errors. In fact, he nds that customersanticipated use was consistent with the pricing scheme they chose. Further, he nds evidence that customers respond to charges in a way that suggests they are trying to minimize their bill given their level of use. Thus, those who incorrectly predicted their use usually shifted to the correct service plan after discovering the error. He nds that less than 6% of customers commit the error of subscribing to a at-rate service when they would have beneted by using another system. His explanation for the observed errors is that consumers are in transition and still discovering which is the best plan for them. He concludes that the rational model of pricing choice is the best model to describe behavior. Miravete nds that among those who choose the at rate pricing, a majority overestimate their eventual use of the phone service. However, even if the phone-use data contain no direct or incontrovertible evidence of the anomaly, the data are consistent with the underlying behavioral tendencies that could lead to the anomalous behavior. Even if the anomalous behavior is not evident, a behavioral economist would nd the consumers formation of use forecasts important in discerning the motivations for behavior.

History and Notes

Although there was ample evidence and discussion before his observation, Kenneth Train is credited with coining the term flat-rate bias in discussing telephone pricing plans in 1994. In coining this term he cited evidence from his own work from the 1980s. This bias has been noted in Internet subscriptions, software licensing, electricity use, and gym memberships. Not only is there evidence of the flat-rate bias, but there is also evidence that those subscribing through a flat rate are much less likely to abandon service. Thus, the service provider not only gets more money for the level of service, but it is also more likely to retain the customer. Thus there is substantial incentive for service providers to offer a flat-rate option for premium levels of use.

 

 

 

 

 

34

 

TRANSACTION UTILITY AND CONSUMER PRICING

Transaction Utility and Consumer

Preferences in Reference

Often our perception of how good a deal we have achieved depends not only on the amount we are able to consume and the quality of the good itself but also on the context within which we make our purchase. In some contexts, items are expected to be more expensive than in other contexts. This leads consumers to display very different demand behavior depending upon the purchase context. Someone might refuse to purchase a good in one venue because it is too expensive, but the same person might purchase the good at an identical price when in a context where the price seems justied. Consumers might use cues from the environment or memory of previous transactions in similar contexts to form an idea of what is a fair price. A comparison used to aid in making a decision is called a reference point. For example, your reference point may be the price you have paid in the past at a particular establishment. If a hamburger has always cost $5 at a particular restaurant, that hamburger might feel like a particularly good deal if you could purchase it for $3. It might feel like a terrible deal if the price rose to $6. Thus the reference point can play an important role in determining the consumers transaction utility. The reference point may be inuenced by the context. An identical hamburger at another restaurant might always be priced at $2. Here it might feel like you have been ripped off if they were to suddenly increase the price to $3.

EXAMPLE 2.6 Beverage Demand and References

Richard Thaler surveyed consumers about their intended behavior under a couple of different hypothetical scenarios. Each respondent saw only one scenario. The first asks you to consider that you are at the beach on a hot day and want to buy a bottle of your favorite beer. A companion offers to get you one from a run-down grocery store. Your friend asks how much you are willing to pay for the beer, saying she will buy it if the price is less than or equal to your stated willingness to pay. The second scenario is identical except that instead of a run-down grocery store, your friend is going to a fancy resort hotel. Note that both scenarios suggest that the respondent will receive their favorite beer, and thus the item itself is identical in both choices. Respondents were willing to pay much more for the beer from the resort than from the grocery store (median value of $2.65 versus $1.50). Moreover, because both scenarios involve consuming the beer on the beach with the friend after she returns, there is no chance that environmental factors could influence the utility the consumer derives from the beer. Thus, the willingness to pay for the experience was influenced by the context in which the purchase takes place.

 

 

 

 

Theory and Reference-Dependent Preferences

 

35

 

EXAMPLE 2.7 Internet Auctions

Internet auctions often offer either a minimum bid or a price at which the potential buyer could forgo the auction altogether and buy the item outright—sometimes called a buy now price. Anna Dodonova and Yuri Khoroshilov examined how the listed buy now price affected bids on a jewelry auction website. They found several mass-marketed items that come up for auction regularly on the site that could offer valid comparisons of behavior. This allowed them to compare items that are identical in design and content and thus in market value. However, the buy now price varied among the auctions. When items were posted with higher buy now prices, bidders placed higher bids, signaling that they valued the item more highly than when they saw the identical item with a low buy now price. Somehow, the buy now price had influenced the bidders’ valuations, perhaps by creating a reference point.

Theory and Reference-Dependent Preferences

The response of consumers to context in forming consumption decisions tells us a lot about how transaction utility works. To use the notion of transaction utility in predicting behavior, we need to know the potential reference points that drive the decision behavior. Thus, a behavioral theory of reference points might suppose that the consumer considering the purchase of a good will be inuenced by her transaction utility for the purchase given the context of the purchase, zx, pξ, where ξ represents the reference point in the given context. The consumer will also be inuenced by the utility of consumption, as in equation 2.8. This particular theory contains very little predictive power because it does not tell us how the reference point was created or how we could determine it.

We could create a procedural rational model of reference point selection. For example, the reference price may be the average price the consumer had previously observed in a particular context (e.g., a resort hotel). This would tell us that the consumer considered previous observed prices in determining if the price was reasonable or not. If the price was higher than at previous resorts, the consumer would think it was a bad deal and have a lower transaction utility. If the price was lower than at previous resorts, the consumer would feel she had gotten a good deal. There is substantial evidence of the use of reference points in decision making. This concept is examined in several of the chapters in this book.

A pervasive problem with using reference-based behavioral theories is that we seldom have a theory describing why a consumer selects a particular reference point. One of the reasons for a lack of clarity in theory is that it can be difcult to test for differences in reference points empirically. In purchasing behavior, the formation of reference points may be particularly difcult to isolate. What is it that quintessentially separates a resort hotel from a run-down grocery store? How can we classify different purchasing locations or experiences into different categories? Does the presence of luxury items nearby signal that higher prices are to be expected?

 

 

 

 

 

36

 

TRANSACTION UTILITY AND CONSUMER PRICING

Alternatively, some have found success in manipulating reference points. For example, the buy now price creates a very simple reference point. In this case, the bidder will purchase or not purchase the item but will judge the transaction utility of a potential purchase based on what price she pays relative to the buy now price. In this case, transaction utility may be written as zppbn, where pbn is the buy now price and where transaction utility is decreasing in p and increasing in pbn. By raising the buy now price, the consumer is more likely to be willing to purchase at a higher price because she will receive a greater transaction utility in addition to the same level of consumption utility.

For the manager trying to set prices within her store, the implication is that one can manipulate the reference point of the consumer and potentially receive higher prices and greater prot. Stores can list comparison prices for items that they are selling in order to induce customers to feel they are obtaining a good deal. We often hear of stores that perpetually mark items as on sale in order to induce this type of feeling. For example, consumers are more likely to buy an item marked On sale for $2 regularly $4than they are to buy the same item marked simply $2. The item may be the same price, but consumers feel they are getting a better deal in comparison to the regular price. Stores often manipulate regular and sale prices to take advantage of this behavior. Some stores that offer everyday low prices instead advertise their own price in relation to their competitorsregular price to the same effect.

From a normative standpoint, transaction utility can lead consumers to make two types of mistakes. First, consumers might purchase items that they otherwise would not want, simply because they think they are getting a good deal. Second, consumers might fail to purchase things that would make them better off because the context suggests a lower reference price to them. In this case, a consumer might not purchase the $3 hamburger at a relatively cheap restaurant even though she would be willing to pay $5 for the same sandwich at a relatively more expensive restaurant. Normatively, consumers would receive higher consumption utility if they did not consider the transaction utility and made purchase decisions based on price irrespective of context. The difculty in offering our consumers prescriptive advice is that we do not know which context represents true consumption preferences. Nevertheless, we are often given advice designed to combat such context-dependent preferences. For example, one should never use the snacks provided in your room at a high-end hotel: The markup is enormous.

Rational Explanations for Context-

Dependent Preferences

Two primary alternative explanations exist for reference-dependent preferences. First, it may be that the context itself conveys information. For example, bidders might not have substantial knowledge about the prices of jewelry and might look to the buy now price to learn something regarding the overall value of the item. Although this might not be the best way to research the price of a good, other ways may be prohibitively costly in terms of effort or time. In this case, it might not be the reference point that was manipulated but simply the bidders expectation of prices she may be able to obtain if she looked

 

 

 

 

Rational Explanations for Context-Dependent Preferences

 

37

 

elsewhere for a similar item. In this case, shifting bids may be perfectly rational given the costs of alternative forms of learning.

Alternatively, it could be that some contexts truly add value to goods. Whereas the beach example is carefully constructed to try to avoid this issue, in practice it may be hard to isolate the reference-point effect from the effect of context on value in a moregeneral consumption setting. I may be willing to pay more for a hot dog at a Chicago Cubs baseball game because I have fond memories of consuming a hot dog at another game in the past. Or I may be willing to pay more for a beverage at a resort because I like the atmosphere in the resort more than that of a run-down grocery store. If the atmosphere is a complement for consumption of a particular good, then willingness to pay for that good should increase in context.

Biographical Note

© Benschop/Hollandse Hoogte/Redux

Richard H. Thaler (1945)

B.A., Case Western Reserve University, 1967; M.S.,

University of Rochester, 1970; PhD, University of

Rochester, 1974; held faculty positions at the

University of Rochester, Cornell University, and the

University of Chicago

Though all his degrees were in economics, Thaler is famous for incorporating concepts from cognitive psychology into models of economic decision making. Many consider him to be the founder of behavioral economics. From his early work on, he has asserted

that consumers suffer from biases in perception as well as emotions that inuence decisions. Much of his work has been in the development of the eld of behavioral nance, focusing on how behavioral biases can inuence nancial markets. He laid the foundation for nearly every behavioral economics contribution to date. From 1987 to 1991 (and occasionally thereafter) he produced a series of review articles for the Journal of Economic Perspectives entitled Anomalies.In it he wrote of phenomena that appeared to defy rational economic modeling. For many academic economists, this was their rst serious exposure to the eld of behavioral economics and helped to codify and dene the eld. His ngerprints can be found throughout the eld of behavioral economics. More recently, he has become an advocate for the notion of using behavioral economics to create policies that do not restrict choice but that have a tendency to lead the consumer to a desired decision. The case for such policies is made in his book Nudge with Cass Sunstein. Daniel Kahneman praised Thaler for his direct contributions in incorporating psychology and economics and for the contributions of the many students who have ocked to work with him.

 

 

 

 

 

38

 

TRANSACTION UTILITY AND CONSUMER PRICING

T H O U G H T Q U E S T I O N S

1.This chapter has presented some evidence that consumers derive utility from getting a good deal. Have you observed evidence that people purchase goods when it is not necessarily in their best interest just so they can get a good deal?

2.If retailers and manufacturers are aware that consumers derive utility from getting a good deal,they may be able to take advantage of this to increase their own prots. Can you nd evidence that retailers take steps to manipulate the perception of the deals they offer?

3.Policy makers concerned with the increasing number of overweight consumers have long complained about the pricing of sodas at fast food restaurants. In most cases, a small soda (usually around 16 ounces) sells for a couple dollars. For just a few cents more, one could purchase a drink that was double that size and obtain a much better deal. Why would fast food chains offer such steep discounts on larger sodas? In one extreme case, a major fast food chain has offered all sizes of drinks for the same price. How could this be protable? Policymakers have suggested requiring linear pricing (eliminating discounts for larger amounts) to ght obesity. New York also attempted to ban the sale of large soft drinks. Are these policies likely to be effective?

4.Suppose a telephone company had two kinds of cus-

tomers. One had a utility function that could be repre-

sented as u1x= 5x − x2 − kx, where x is the total amount of time spent on the phone and k is the total cost

to the customer for service. This results in a marginal

utility curve

u1

x

x = 5 2x − k

x.

The

other

type of consumer possesses a utility function

that

can be

written

as

u2

x = 5x − x2 − k x

− x

k x ,

resulting

in

a marginal

utility curve

u2

x

x =

5 2x − k

x −

k x

− x

k x

 

. Suppose

that

each

faces

x

 

 

2

 

 

 

 

k x

 

 

 

 

 

 

R E F E R E N C E S

Arkes, H.R., and C. Blumer. The Psychology of Sunk Cost.

Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes

35(1985): 124140.

Della Vigna, S., and U. Malmendier. Paying Not to Go to the Gym.

American Economic Review 96(2006):694719.

Dodonova, A., and Y. Khoroshilov. Anchoring and the Transaction Utility: Evidence from On-Line Auctions.” Applied Economics Letters 11(2004): 307310.

no budget constraint (so that they will purchase until marginal utility declines to zero). Suppose the rm charges a linear price so that kx= px, and marginal cost is given by kxx = p. What is the demand curve for each customer type? (Hint: Simply solve each case for the amount of line use, x, that results in zero marginal utility). Are these demand curves downward sloping? Alternatively, suppose that the rm charges a at fee, so that kx = p, and kxx = 0. What is the demand curve for each consumer type given this pricing structure? Are these demand curves downward sloping? Which consumer displays a desire for transaction utility? How does this inuence demand under each pricing scheme? What does demand look like if consumers face a two-part tariff so that kx= p0 + p1x, so that

k x x = p1? (Do not solve for the demand curve, but give some intuition as to how it will behave.)

5.Further, suppose that the cost function for providing

minutes on the phone is given by cx= x2. The prot function is given by π = kx*− Cx*, where x* is the optimal consumption given the pricing scheme solved

in the previous exercise. What are the optimal price choices for the rm under linear or at-fee pricing if all customers were of type 1? Write down the prot function for each pricing scheme. Use a spreadsheet application (like Microsoft Excel) to solve for the price that maximizes the prot by trying various prices until you nd the price yielding the highest prots. Which pricing scheme provides greater prots? Now try the same exercise assuming all customers are of type 2. Which pricing scheme now provides the greatest prots? How do you think the answer would change if the phone company believed they would have customers of both types?

Just, D.R., and B. Wansink. The Flat-Rate Pricing Paradox: Con-

icting Effects of All-You-Can-Eat Buffet Pricing.” Review of Economics and Statistics 93(2011): 193200.

Kridel, D.J., D.E. Lehman, and D.L. Weisman. Option Value, Telecommunications Demand, and Policy.” Information Economics and Policy 5(1993): 125144.

Miravete, E.J. Choosing the Wrong Calling Plan? Ignorance and Learning.” American Economic Review 93(2003): 297310.

 

 

 

 

References

 

39

 

Prelec, D., and G.F. Loewenstein. The Red and the Black: Mental Accounting of Savings and Debt.” Marketing Science 17(1998): 428.

Samuelson, P.A., and W.D. Nordhaus. Economics. New York:

McGraw-Hill, 1948.

Sandmo, A. On the Theory of the Competitive Firm under Price Uncertainty.” American Economic Review 61(1971): 6573.

Thaler, R. Toward a Positive Theory of Consumer Choice.” Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 1(1980): 3960.

Thaler, R. Mental Accounting and Consumer Choice.” Marketing Science 4(1985): 199214.

Train, K.E. Optimal Regulation. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1994.

Advanced Concept

Fixed Costs and Rational Choice

More explicitly, we can consider the LaGrangian associated with equations 2.1 and 2.2:

 

L = U x1, x2 + λ y − p0 − p1x1 − p2x2

2 A

with rst-order conditions for an internal solution given by

 

 

 

 

 

L

=

 

U x1*, x2* − λ*p1 = 0

2 B

 

 

 

 

x1

 

 

 

 

 

 

x1

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

L

=

 

U x1*, x2*

− λ*p2 = 0

2 C

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

x1

x2

 

 

 

 

 

 

y − p0 − p1x1 − p2x2 = 0

2 D

As in Chapter 1, equations 2.B and 2.C imply that

 

 

1

 

 

 

U x1*, x2* =

1

 

 

 

U x1*, x2* .

2 E

 

p2

 

 

 

 

 

x2

 

 

p1

x1

 

We can solve the budget constraint for x2 and substitute into equation 2.E to nd

p1

 

 

U

x1*,

y − p0 − p1x1*

 

 

=

x1

p2

,

2 F

p2

 

U

x1*,

y − p0 − p1x1*

 

 

 

 

 

x2

p2

 

 

 

 

 

 

which implicitly denes the demand function for good 1. Altering p0 in this equation will almost certainly alter the consumption of good 1. To see this, note that as p0 increases, if x1* were to remain the same, x2* must increase through the budget constraint. If there is diminishing marginal utility of consuming good 2, the denominator of the right side must decline, requiring a proportional decline in

 

 

 

 

 

40

 

TRANSACTION UTILITY AND CONSUMER PRICING

the numeratorthe marginal utility of good 1. This is an unlikely occurrence if we are holding x1* constant. Alternatively, good 1 may remain the same if the two goods are independent and if good 2 displays constant marginal utility.

Were we to assume p1 = 0, then equation 2.B is replaced by

L

= U x1*, x2* = 0,

2 G

 

x1 x1

 

or, after substituting the budget constraint

 

U x1*,

y − p0

= 0,

2 H

 

 

x1

p2

 

which implicitly denes the demand function. Totally differentiating equation 2.H with respect to x1* and p0 yields the relationship between xed costs and demand for good 1

2

 

 

 

 

y − p0

 

 

1

 

2

 

 

 

y − p0

dp0 = 0,

 

 

 

 

U x1*,

 

dx1

 

 

U x1

*,

2 I

 

x12

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

p2

 

 

 

 

p2 x2 x1

 

 

 

 

p2

 

or,

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

dx1

 

 

1

 

 

 

 

2

U x1*,

y

− p0

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

=

 

p2

 

x2

x1

 

p2

 

.

 

2 J

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

dp0

2

U x1*,

y − p0

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

p2

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

x2

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

1

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

The two

goods

 

are independent

(neither

compliments or substitutes) if

2U x1, x2

x2

x1 = 0, in which case the derivative in equation 2.J is equal to

zero, implying that consumption of good 1 will not change with a marginal change in the xed price of consumption.

Mental Accounting

3

Suppose you had a coupon for a free ice cream cone from a local ice cream parlor. While walking by the store on a particularly hot day, you decide to redeem your coupon. Leaving the store, you stroll down the street and accidently drop the cone on the ground, rendering the ice cream inedible. You are disappointed at rst, but you achieve some comfort by reminding yourself that it was free to begin with. You reason that if you didnt have to pay for it, it was no real loss.

Alternatively, suppose you had been wanting to buy a new video game system. You had contemplated saving for the system, but knew you really needed to save your money for a new pair of eyeglasses. Your prescription had changed substantially and it was beginning to be difcult to do everyday things. One afternoon you check your mail and nd that your grandmother has written you a check. It is just enough to purchase either the game system or the new glasses. After thinking about it for a minute or two you decide to purchase the video game system. What kind of a gift would glasses make, anyway?

Consumers must deal with new income from varied sources and new expenses on a variety of items on a regular basis. Additionally, people face changes in the state of the world (often referred to as shocks) that can render prior investments useless or make them even more valuable. The sheer volume of decisions one must make can lead people to use simple rules of thumb to make decisions rather than to optimize in the way that economic theory suggests. In particular, people can use a system called mental accounting to make decisions as well as to rationalize previous decisions. Mental accounting is a procedure of keeping accounts of income and expenses, similar to that used by corporations, except in this case, each person is his or her own bookkeeper and the books are kept in the ledgers of ones mind.

In the previous chapter, we detailed how people can be motivated by transaction utilitythe desire to get a good deal on an item. In a sense, when a sunk cost is incurred, it is entered into the mental ledger as an expense in a particular account. To balance the books, the person then seeks a gain of equal or greater value that allows him to close the mental account. Thus, for example, you might open a mental account when you enter an all-you-can-eat restaurant and pay the admission fee. This account could only be closed by consuming enough food for you to feel you have received a value that exceeds the cost of entry. In this case, you would choose to consume more when the price is higher. Decision making based on mental accounting can lead directly to the transaction utilitybased behavior described in the previous chapter, though many other anomalous types of behavior are implicated.

41

Соседние файлы в предмете [НЕСОРТИРОВАННОЕ]