Добавил:
Upload Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:
david_Introduction_to_behavioral_economics.pdf
Скачиваний:
50
Добавлен:
26.03.2016
Размер:
12.18 Mб
Скачать
n
i = 1 pizi,

 

 

 

 

Rational Bidding under Dutch and First-Price Auctions

 

101

 

Rational Bidding under Dutch and First-Price Auctions

Some auction mechanisms do not present the bidder with a clear dominant strategy. One such auction is a rst-price sealed-bid auction. In this case, the bidder with the highest bid wins the auction and must pay the amount he bid. Further, because it is a sealed-bid auction, bidders cannot observe the bids of other players before determining their own bid. If bidders are not allowed to observe the bids of others before placing their bids, there is not one single bid that clearly yields a higher payout no matter what all other bidders choose to do.

Bidders who bid their value are guaranteed a zero return in all cases. If their bid is not the highest, then they neither pay nor receive any payoff. If their bid is the high bid, they would pay exactly their valuation and receive the value from the object of the auction exactly offsetting the amount paid. The only way to receive a positive return from this auction is to bid something below the valuation of the object. Suppose bidder i places a bid of xi = vi − k, where k is a positive constant. In this case, if some other bidder bids xj = vi − k2 and wins the auction, player i receives a payoff of zero, neither receiving the object of the auction or paying any money. Player i could clearly have done better. By bidding something above xj and something below vi, player i could have won the auction and made a positive gain upon paying that bid. Thus, players face a tradeoff in placing bids. By increasing the bid up to the level of their valuation, players increase their probability of winning the auction and obtaining some positive value. However, as players increase their bid, they also reduce the eventual payoff for having won by increasing their eventual price paid. To discuss the optimal strategy for bidding, we need to use the tools of elementary probability and some discussion of decision under uncertainty.

Consider a random variable z that can take on real number values. We call the set of values the variable can take on the support of z. Thus, if z were the roll of a single sixsided game die, the support is given by {1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6}. Let us suppose that the random variable displays predictable properties that allow us to discuss how likely some outcomes are relative to others. For example, when a fair, evenly weighted die is rolled hundreds of times, each number is rolled in approximately 1/6 of the rolls. The probability of an outcome is the proportion of times that outcome would occur if the random variable could be drawn a large number of times (approaching innity). Thus, probability is a number between 0 and 1 representing the likelihood of a particular outcome. Further, the probability of a draw of the random variable being contained in the support of that random variable (obtained by adding the probability of each individual outcome in the support) must be 1. Thus the probability of rolling some integer between and including 1 to 6 is 1. The probability of any outcome outside of the support must be zerothe probability of rolling a 7 is 0.

The expectation, or mean, of a random variable can be dened as Ez =

where pi is the probability of outcome zi, and E is the expectation operator. The expectation is simply a sum of all outcomes weighted by their relative frequency in a large sample, thus representing the average or mean outcome of a draw from the distribution. When an individual decision will result in a randomly distributed payoff, we

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

102

 

THE WINNER’S CURSE AND AUCTION BEHAVIOR

 

 

 

 

 

refer to this as a decision under uncertainty. Often, economists suppose that when

 

 

facing

uncertainty, people

seek to maximize the expectation

of their

payout,

 

 

maxxE π x

. Thus, in the rst-price sealed-bid auction, the bidder tries to solve

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

max E πi

,

 

5 3

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

x

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

where

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

πi = v xi

if xi = p

 

5 4

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

0

if

xi < p.

 

 

 

 

 

Here, the uncertainty arises because the price depends on the bidding strategies of all

 

 

others in the auction. In particular, if everyone formulates their bid as a function of their

 

 

own valuation, vi, then the underlying uncertainty arises from the distribution of prob-

 

 

ability over valuations in the bidding pool. Thus, bidders face uncertainty because they

 

 

do not know how much other people value the good being auctioned. If one could

 

 

somehow observe the individual valuation of each person participating in the auction,

 

 

one could easily bid the valuation of the bidder directly below ones valuation, producing

 

 

the familiar rational prediction from the Vickrey auction. In the absence of this, the

 

 

bidder must form a bid based upon his own valuation, the number of bidders partici-

 

 

pating in the auction, and his belief as to what othersvaluations may be.

 

 

 

 

 

Suppose that valuations are independent observations from a random variable with

 

 

the probability of any single outcome given by p v . Then suppose that all bidders will

 

 

choose a bid as a particular function of their own valuation, x vj , with presumably

 

 

higher bids resulting from higher valuations, so that each bidder employs the same bid

 

 

function. Then these bids become random variables with a distribution such that the

 

 

probability of a bid x v

is p v . The probability that bidder i will win by bidding x vi

is

 

 

equal to the probability that n − 1 draws of the valuation will yield a bid lower than x vi

,

 

 

where n is the number of bidders. Suppose we relabeled the valuations in order, such that

 

 

vi > vj

whenever i > j. Then the probability that bidder j produces a bid that is lower than

 

 

x vi

is just

 

i

. If individual valuations are independent draws from this same

 

 

 

j = 1 p vj

 

 

distribution, then the probability of all n − 1 bidders having a lower bid than x vi

can be

 

 

found

by multiplying

the probability of

each

individual having a

lower value, or,

 

 

 

i

 

 

n − 1

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

. Thus, the expected payout for bidding amount x vi

can be written as

 

 

 

j = 1 p vj

 

 

 

 

 

= vi − xi

i

 

n − 1

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

E πi

 

, the probability that all other bidders submit lower

 

 

j = 1 p vj

bids multiplied by the value obtained if all other bids are lower. Maximizing the expected payout involves increasing xi until the marginal expected payout becomes zero. Bidding less than this means that bidders could increase the expected benet of their bid, and bidding more than this would mean that they could receive a higher benet by lowering their bid.

Finding the Nash equilibrium for such a game is difcult. As an example, let us suppose that valuations are drawn from a uniform distribution over all integers 0 to 100. The uniform distribution assigns the same probability to every individual outcome. Thus the probability that any particular bidder has a valuation of 10 is equal to 0.01, and the

 

 

 

 

Rational Bidding under Dutch and First-Price Auctions

 

103

 

probability that any particular bidder has a valuation of 100 is also equal to 0.01. Let us rst examine the possibility that everyone bids their own valuation. If player i believes

that

everyone will

bid their own

valuation, then

the payout for a bid xi

is vi − xi

if xi

> xj

for all j

i. The probability of this occurring when player i bids his own

value is

xi = vi, is

i

n − 1

=

n − 1

. Thus, the expected

payout is

 

j = 1 p vj

 

0.01vi

E πi

= vi − x 0.01vi n − 1. If one bids exactly ones value, then x = vi, meaning the

expected payout is 0. If instead the bidder bids slightly more than his value but not enough to surpass the next highest valuation, the probability of winning remains the same. So long as the probability of winning remains positive, the expected payout is negative if his bid exceeds his valuation. Thus, given that othersbid their value, it is not in the interest of any bidders to bid above their value. Alternatively, if the a player bids slightly below his value, then vi − x > 0, and so long as the probability of winning remains positive, the expected payout is positive. Thus, if all others bid their value, an individual bidder has an incentive to bid below his value, making him better off. Thus it cannot be a Nash equilibrium for everyone to bid their value because any individual player could be better off trying a different strategy given that others bid their value. So the rst-price sealed-bid auction should result in a different outcome than either the English or Vickrey auctions.

Suppose instead that all other players bid a fraction α of their valuation. Thus, if my valuation were 50 and α = 0.5, I would bid 25. Then, if player i bids αvi, the probability

of winning x is

i

n − 1

=

n − 1

, the probability that player i’s drawn

 

j = 1 p vj

 

0.01vi

 

value

is above

all others.

The expected

payoff from winning in this case is

E πi

= vi − αvi

0.01vi n − 1 = 1 − α vin 0.01 n − 1. Given that others are bidding α times

their value, and the next highest value is vi + 1, increasing their bid by less than α will not increase the probability of winning. Thus, bidding less than α above αvi decreases the expected payoff by decreasing the payoff in the event of a win, and the probability of winning remains the same. Increasing the bid by α results in a payoff of

E πi = vi − αvi − α

0.01 vi + 1 n − 1, with the probability increased by raising the bid

above those with a

valuation just 1 unit higher. Alternatively, decreasing the bid

immediately decreases the probability by 0.01vin − 1 vi 1n − 10.01 because

the bid will potentially fall below others with value vi who are bidding αvi. But once bidders have lowered their bid, they do not further reduce the probability of winning until the bid has been lowered by α, and they continue to increase the payoff for winning. The Nash equilibrium occurs where α is such that bidding an amount either α less or α more would result in a lower expected value, or

E πi x = αvi + α = vi − αvi − α

0.01 vi + 1

n − 1 < 1 − α vin 0.01 n − 1,

5 5

and

 

 

 

 

E πi x = αvi − α = vi − αvi + α

0.01 vi 1

n − 1 < 1 − α vin 0.01 n − 1.

5 6

Solving equation 5.5 for α yields

 

 

 

 

α >

vi vi + 1 n − 1

− vin

 

5 7

vi + 1 n − vin

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

104

 

THE WINNER’S CURSE AND AUCTION BEHAVIOR

and equation 5.6 yields

α <

vi vi 1

n 1 − vin

.

5 8

vi 1

n − vin

 

 

 

With any number of players, and for any value vi, these two conditions will always be met where α = n − 1n. In a more-general rst-price auction, if values are drawn from a uniform distribution over all real numbers between 0, v, the Nash equilibrium bid is

xi* = vi n − 1 n.

5 9

Thus, the appropriate strategy depends on the number of players in the game, with the bid increasing toward the valuation as n gets large. The interested reader can nd the derivation of this more general case in the Advanced Concept box at the end of this chapter.

Another common form of auction is the Dutch auction. In this auction, the auctioneer begins by calling out a very high price. The auctioneer then lowers the price by small increments until a bidder indicates he or she is willing to pay the price. This form of auction is common in the sale of large batches of owers, as well as corporate and public bonds. Because the auction stops when the rst bidder indicates his willingness to buy, no bidder has any information on othersvaluations or intended bids before the auction concludes. Thus, despite the difference in mechanism, the Dutch auction acts exactly like a rst-price sealed-bid auction. The highest bidder wins and pays his own bid price, but this bid must be determined before any observed actions by others.

EXAMPLE 5.4 Dutch Auctions

James C. Cox, Bruce Roberson, and Vernon L. Smith conducted early experimental comparisons of Dutch and first-price sealed-bid auctions. The rational economic model of bidding suggests that both auction mechanisms should yield the same bids and that these bids should be somewhat below the individual valuation of the object. They found that the Dutch auction bids are regularly below the bids of those in identical first-price auctions. The bidder assigned the highest valuation wins the auction approximately 88 percent of the time in the first-price auction, compared to only 80 percent in the Dutch auction. Thus, lower-valuation bidders have a greater tendency to outbid the top-value bidder in the Dutch auction. Further, they found that both the first-price and Dutch auction bids are above the bids in the second-price auctions. The anchoring and adjustment model might suggest that bidders in a Dutch auction should overbid, as appears to be the case, by anchoring on the opening amount called and failing to adjust down sufficiently. The Dutch auction starts with the highest possible price, providing a high anchor, which should lead to higher overall bids. The first-price sealed-bid auction provides no clear anchor but the induced value of the bidder: The amount the bidder will receive should he win the auction. Hence, the anchoring and adjustment model suggests lower overall bids for the first-price than the Dutch auction, a prediction that is not borne out in laboratory experiments. In fact, both appear to be higher than the bids predicted by theory by a substantial amount.

Соседние файлы в предмете [НЕСОРТИРОВАННОЕ]