Добавил:
Upload Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:
david_Introduction_to_behavioral_economics.pdf
Скачиваний:
50
Добавлен:
26.03.2016
Размер:
12.18 Mб
Скачать

 

 

 

 

 

116

 

THE WINNER’S CURSE AND AUCTION BEHAVIOR

between the laboratory outcomes and the real-world outcomes. In essence, they found three real reasons why the winner’s curse is rare in construction bidding.

First, contractors monitor the difference between their bid and the bids of others on any particular project. They monitor closely enough that they have a good feel for the average difference between the top and second bid for various types of jobs. When the differences between the lowest (winning) and the next lowest bid were greater than about 7 percent, they often inquired of other bidders to determine the reason for the difference, a clear sign that they were aware of and worried about the winner’s curse. Contractors also clearly understand the need to mark up bids in anticipation of random costs that might occur unforeseen in the construction process.

The second mechanism that allows a contractor to avoid the winner’s curse is the ability to withdraw an apparent winning bid once all bids have been announced if there has been any arithmetic error in calculating the bid. In this case, winning the bid with a significant distance between the top and second bid might lead a contractor to reevaluate the bid and search for reasons for the difference. If the difference is due to an error, he may withdraw the bid.

Finally, the contractor has the ability to adjust costs. For example, in the course of construction some of the plans might change, allowing the bidder to renegotiate for higher pay in midstream. The lesson from this study appears to be that the winner’s curse is a real threat, but industries with experience in bidding might find heuristics and other mechanisms to reduce or eliminate the threat.

History and Notes

The term winner’s curse was first coined by Capen, Clapp, and Campbell in their description of the oil lease contracts of the 1950s and 1960s. The early study of the winner’s curse was driven first by field data from various industries. The notion has become quite popular in describing many different phenomena where parallels can be drawn. The winner’s curse has inspired research-based books by Richard Thaler and by John Kagel and Dan Levin and a score of popular books by various authors. For participants in bidding, the implication is clear. One must scrutinize one’s bid with the goal that the bid should likely be below the lowest possible value one would consider for the good. This is especially important when there are large numbers of bidders or when the person formulating the bid is inexperienced. Although this might result in losing the auction even when it might have been profitable, this is a much better outcome than winning the auction when it is unprofitable. From the point of view of sellers, it may be better to employ auctions with large numbers of inexperienced bidders, because this is the most likely way to generate bids well in excess of the true value of the object being auctioned.

 

 

 

 

Rational Explanations for the Winner’s Curse

 

117

 

Rational Explanations for the Winners Curse

Most of the rational explanations for the winners curse deal with identifying imperfections in the eld data used to demonstrate the effect. Unfortunately, it is not generally possible to observe individual information about the value of an object in a eld setting. As well, it is impossible to determine the expected prot for an object or endeavor with any degree of accuracy.

For example, in studying the oil lease contracts, it is necessary to assume specic discount factors for future consumption in order to determine if the net present value of returns is negative or positive. Assuming less discounting for the future provides a larger return. Further, there were tremendous increases in the price of oil over the period generally studied that are unlikely to have been anticipated. Similarly, estimating the overpayment of baseball players relies heavily on the underlying assumptions of that players value. Certainly there may be factors other than slugging, strikeouts, and walks. Finally, risk aversion alters the optimal bid and generally leads to higher bids. Thus, if winning bidders are risk averse, we would expect them to display prots that are below the expected payoutmaximizing amount on average, though these prots should not be negative on average.

All of these factors make it difcult to say with certainty that the winners curse has been observed in the wild. Thus, many have suggested that the winners curse is simply an illusion. However, this phenomenon appears to have had tremendous impacts on the way several industries respond to unknown values. The simple presence of mechanisms such as those found in the construction industry is tangible evidence that people develop heuristics to deal with the problem of the winners curse, while not fully understanding the mathematics behind the problem itself. These heuristics develop out of systematic experience, providing a key point of evidence that the curse exists in some contexts and is strong enough to lead to long-term changes in institutions.

Biographical Note

© KENDRA LUCK/San Francisco Chronicle/Corbis

Matthew Rabin (1963–)

B.A., University of Wisconsin at Madison, 1984; Ph.D., Massachusetts Institute of Technology, 1989; held faculty positions at the University of California at Berkeley

Matthew Rabin conducted his undergraduate study in economics and mathematics. His training has led to an approach that is behavioral, yet based on rigorous mathematical modeling of the underlying phenomena. Much of this work employs behavioral concepts in a game-theory setting. His earliest work

posits that people consider the motivations of others when deciding how to behave. For example, one might wish to help someone who has been nice to one in the past

 

 

 

 

 

118

 

THE WINNER’S CURSE AND AUCTION BEHAVIOR

and might wish to harm those who have harmed one in the past. His works have contributed to behavioral theory of auctions, risk and uncertainty, the impacts of cheap talk (nonbinding talks) in games, the discounting and anticipation of future events, probability judgment bias, and welfare analysis. His colleagues describe him as a voracious reader, approaching new research by rst pulling all related literature from any discipline that may be connected to it. In 2001, he won the John Bates Clark Medal, which is generally awarded to the economist younger than 40 years who has contributed the most to the eld. He has won the MacArthur fellowship (often called the Geniusfellowship). Personally, Matthew Rabin is known as an engaging teacher and presenter, endowed with more than his fair share of humor. As an example of the humor inherent in his personality, his personal résumé lists his rst professional honor as being voted Most Likely to Express His Opinion,by the Springbrook High School class of 1981.

T H O U G H T Q U E S T I O N S

1.Consider that you are preparing to sell some antique items at auction. How might you design the auction so as to receive the highest possible sale price? What sorts of behavioral anomalies will be important to consider? What role will the number and experience of the bidders play in the auction?

2.Consider now that you are preparing to purchase an item at auction for your personal use. What factors should you consider in forming your bid? What behavioral tendencies should you try to avoid? What if you were purchasing the item for resale at a later date instead?

3.Building contractors bidding on a building project often calculate their anticipated costs, add some percentage for prot, and then double this number and submit it as a bid. Similar rules of thumb have been reported in other auction arenas. Why do you think such rules of thumb developed? What purpose do they serve? In what ways might the contractors be worse off for using this rule of thumb?

4.Suppose that two people are engaged in a Vickrey auction for a good with two possible values: $10 or $20. Further, suppose each bidder receives a signal of the value, xn, where xn is equal to the true value with probability 0.8, and equal to the other possible value with probability 0.2. No information other than this signal is available. Each player must select a bid based on his own signal. What bidding strategy would be

suggested by the fully cursed equilibrium (e.g., what should you bid if you receive a signal of $10 and what should you bid if you receive a signal of $20)? Suppose that players can only bid integer amounts, and follow the example given in the text. Thus, if player 1 draws x1 = 10, the mean value of winning the auction is μ = 0.8 × 10 + 0.2 × 20 = 12, the probability of signals that player 2 might receive is (similar to equation 5.14)

p x2

= 0.8 × 0.8 + 0.2 × 0.2 = 0.68

if

x2 = 10

 

0.8 × 0.2 + 0.2 × 0.8 = 0.32

if

x2 = 20.

If player 1 draws x1 = 20, the expected value of winning the auction is μ = 0.8 × 20 + 0.2 × 10 = 18, and the probability distribution of signals that player 2 might receive is

p x2

= 0.8 × 0.8 + 0.2 × 0.2 = 0.68

if

x2 = 20

 

0.8 × 0.2 + 0.2 × 0.8 = 0.32

if

x2 = 10

Suppose that in the event of a tie, both players receive the value of the object. First try the strategy in which each player bids the expected value of the gamble given the signal each has received. Show that this constitutes a cursed equilibrium. What is the expected prot in this case (the actual, not perceived)? Do these strategies constitute a Bayesian Nash equilibrium? If not, can you nd the Bayesian Nash equilibrium?

 

 

 

 

References

 

119

 

R E F E R E N C E S

Ariely, D., A. Ockenfels, and A.E. Roth. An Experimental Analysis of Ending Rules in Internet Auctions.” RAND Journal of Economics 36(2005): 890907.

Baraji, P., and A. Hortaçsu. The Winners Curse, Reserve Prices and Endogenous Entry: Empirical Insights from eBay Auctions.

RAND Journal of Economics 34(2003): 329355.

Capen, E.C., R.V. Clapp, and W.M. Campbell. Competitive Bidding in High-Risk Situations.” Journal of Petroleum Technology

23(1971): 641653.

Cassing, J., and R.W. Douglas. Implications of the Auction Mechanism in Baseballs Free Agent Draft.” Southern Economic Journal 47(1980): 110121.

Cox, J.C., B. Roberson, and V.L. Smith. Theory and Behavior of Single Object Auctions.” Research in Experimental Economics

2(1982): 143.

Dyer, D., and J.H. Kagel. Bidding in Common Value Auctions: How the Commercial Construction Industry Corrects for the Winners Curse.” Management Science 42(1996): 14371475.

Eyster, E., and M. Rabin. Cursed Equilibrium.” Econometrica

73(2005): 16231672.

Kagel, J.H., R.M. Harstad, and D. Levin. Information Impact and Allocation Rules in Auctions with Afliated Private Values: A Laboratory Study.” Econometrica 55(1987): 12751304.

Kagel, J.H., and D. Levin. The Winners Curse and Public Information in Common Value Auctions.” American Economic Review

76(1986): 894920.

Kagel, J.H., and J.-F. Richard. Super-Experienced Bidders in FirstPrice Common Value Auctions: Rules of Thumb, Nash Equilibrium Bidding, and the Winners Curse.” Review of Economics and Statistics 83(2001): 408419.

Lucking-Reiley, D. Using Field Experiments to Test Equivalence between Auction Formats: Magic on the Internet.” American Economic Review 89(1999): 10631080.

Mead, W.J., A. Moseidjord, and P.E. Sorensen. The Rate of Return Earned by Lessees under Cash Bonus Bidding of OCS Oil and Gas Leases.” Energy Journal 4(1983): 3752.

Roth, A.E., and A. Ockenfels. Last-Minute Bidding and the Rules for Ending Second Price Auctions: Evidence from eBay and Amazon Auctions on the Internet.” American Economic Review

92(2002): 10931103.

Samuelson, W.F., and M.H. Bazerman. The Winners Curse in Bilateral Negotiations.” Research in Experimental Economics

3(1985): 105137.

Stahl, D.O., and P.W. Wilson. On PlayersModels of Other Players: Theory and Experimental Evidence.” Games and Economic Behavior 10(1995): 218254.

Wilson, R. A Bidding Model of Perfect Competition.” Review of Economic Studies 44(1977): 511518.

Advanced Concept

Bayesian Nash Equilibrium and Bidding under Uncertainty

When dealing with a continuum of possible valuations, we use a probability density function to represent the likelihood of any particular draw falling in any particular range of values. Let z be a random variable with support given by

z,

z

. Then, the probability density function is a function f

z such that the

probability of z falling in any interval z1, z2 is given by

z2 f z dz. Thus,

 

 

 

z1

z f z dz = 1, and if the probability density is continuous, the probability of any

z

 

 

 

single outcome is given by

z1 f z dz = 0. We now dene the expectation function

 

 

z1

 

as E z =

z zf z dz. Let F z =

z f z dz. Thus, F z is the probability of any

 

z

 

z

particular draw from the distribution falling below z. In this context, given a probability density gv of valuations, if the bidder believes others will bid

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

120

 

THE WINNER’S CURSE AND AUCTION BEHAVIOR

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

according to the bid function xj = b vj , his expected payoff for bidding x is given

 

 

 

by E πi = vi − x G b 1 x

n − 1. Here, b 1

x is the valuation that will result

 

 

 

in a bid of x. Hence, G b 1

x is the probability of a single draw from the

 

 

 

distribution of valuations falling below the valuation that would bid x. To nd the

 

 

 

probability that all other players bid less than x, we need only multiply this

 

 

 

probability together n − 1, times, or

G b 1 x

 

n − 1. This is thus the probability

 

 

 

of wining the auction given a bid of x. If we differentiate the expected payout with

 

 

 

respect to vi, we obtain

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

d

E πi = G b 1 x

n − 1 − vi − x n − 1 G b 1 x

n − 2

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

dvi

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

×

d

G b 1 x

d

b 1 x

dx

 

vi

5 A

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

dv

 

 

dx

dv

 

 

 

 

 

 

= G b 1 x

n − 1 +

d

E πi

 

d

b x .

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

dx

 

dvi

 

 

 

 

When evaluated at the optimal bid, dE πi dx = 0 so that the second term of

 

 

 

equation 5.A is zero. Thus,

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

dE πi

= G b 1 x

 

 

n − 1,

5 B

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

dvi

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

in Nash equilibrium. Further, note that no bidder should ever bid lower than the lowest possible valuation. Each bidder knows that all other bidders have a minimum valuation of v, and that bidding below this value will ensure losing the auction. Further, no one will ever bid above their valuation. Thus, we know that whatever the optimal rule, the bidder who has drawn the lowest possible valuation must bid his own valuation, bv = v. We can then solve for the optimal bidding strategy by solving the differential equation given by equation 5.B and the condition that bv = v. Solving equation 5.B obtains

vi

G b 1 x v n − 1dv = k +

vi

 

E πi = k +

G v n − 1dv,

5 C

v

 

v

 

where k is an arbitrary constant and the second equality holds by assuming that xv = bv; in other words, all bidders with the same value make the same bid. The denition of the expected payout function (assuming again that all bidders with the same valuation submit the same bid) is given by

E πi = vi − x G vi n − 1,

5 D

or substituting equation 5.C we nd

 

vi

 

k +

G v n − 1dv = vi − x* G vi n − 1.

5 E

v

 

 

 

 

References

 

121

 

Solving equation 5.E for the optimal bid yields

 

k +

vi

G v

n − 1

dv

 

 

x* = vi

v

 

 

 

.

5 F

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

G vi

n −

1

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

The condition requiring the lowest valuation to result in b v

= v allows us to

solve for the constant, k = 0. Hence, the optimal bid is given by

 

 

vi

G v

n − 1

dv

 

 

x* = vi

v

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

.

 

5 G

 

G vi

n −

1

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

In the special case when the distribution of v is uniformly distributed on support

0,

 

, the probability density is given by g v

= 1 v over the support and zero

v

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

=

v

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

vi

 

n − 1

 

elsewhere.

Thus,

 

G v

1

vdv = v v.

 

Also,

G v

dv =

 

0

 

0

 

0vi v

 

n −

1dv = vin

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

n − 1n . Thus,

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

v

v

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

n − 1vin

 

 

 

vi

 

 

n − 1

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

x* = vi

 

 

v

 

 

= vi

= vi

,

 

 

5 H

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

n − 1vn − 1

n

 

n

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

nv

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

i

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

which is the result reported in equation 5.9. When we employ a Nash equilibrium in a game of uncertainty such as this we refer to it as a Bayesian Nash equilibrium. This is in reference to the requirement that each player must have beliefs regarding the strategies and payoffs of all other players that is consistent with their strategies in the equilibrium. Thus, in this game we require that each player has the same prior beliefs regarding the distribution of valuations and that each anticipates the correct strategy of others given their valuation.

INFORMATION AND UNCERTAINTY

PART2

Many decisions involve outcomes that are unknown at the time of making a decision. For example, homebuyers may opt to purchase ood or earthquake insurance but must decide to do so before it becomes obvious whether or not a ood or earthquake will inict damage on their home. Investment, education, family planning, production, and other decisions all require decision makers to leap before they can look. Economics has proposed a welldeveloped and intuitively satisfying theory for how people make decisions when facing uncertainty; this theory is built on the work of John von Neumann and Oscar Morgenstern in proposing a rational decision framework.

However, there has been evidence from early on of behavioral anomalies in decision under risk. Such decisions are particularly prone to behavioral anomalies because of the random nature of the outcomes. For example, consider the case where a homebuyer insures her house against ooding when it would be in her best interest not to. Perhaps she overestimated the relative frequency of oods. In other words, given her tolerance for risk, she would be better off not purchasing insurance and facing the risk of catastrophic loss from a ood given the relative rarity of ooding near her home. Given that ooding is relatively rare, she might not particularly notice or revise her beliefs regarding the frequency of oods over the course of many years without an observed ood.

With any event that happens with relative rarity, people can have a very hard time distinguishing between events with vastly different relative frequency. Behavioral economists have noted several behavioral anomalies that are relatively predictable, and they have proposed alternative theories as to why these anomalies occur. This section of the book presents many of these theories, which can be divided into three general categories: theories of learning, theories of decision under uncertainty, and choice bracketing. I begin with choice bracketing because it makes a relatively easy transition from consumer theories to the theory of decision under risk.

123

Bracketing Decisions

6

Consider your friend who has a nal paper due in a relatively important class. The paper will be worth about half of his grade in the class. It is Friday at 7:00 P.M., and he must complete the paper by Monday morning at 9:00 A.M. He believes that the paper will take about six hours of hard work to complete. However, he is in the middle of a role-playing video game and is really itching to play the game for at least another 20 minutes before diving into his paper. Upon considering his options, he believes the 20 minutes will not set him back too far because it is such a small amount of time. Further, the 20 minutes would not allow him to make very much progress at all on his paper relative to the amount of progress he might be able to make on the game. Thus, he decides to play. About 20 minutes later, he faces the same decision. But 20 minutes still seems like such a short period compared to the amount of time he has left to nish the paper. So, he continues to play. At about 3:00 A.M., after playing for eight hours, he decides to go to bed and work on the paper the next day. He regrets the amount of time he spent playing video games, and realizes that he could have made signicant progress on the paper and could perhaps have completed it by then. He laments, How could I have played video games for eight hours instead of working on my paper?

Consider, alternatively, a company headed by two people: a CEO and a president of operations. The CEO has ultimate responsibility for the company, and the president directly oversees the eight team leaders who make up the senior management. Each of the team leaders has some autonomy and can decide on the particular projects that they will undertake. The CEO is worried that although the company is protable, prots are smaller than she would like. Wondering the root cause of the problem, she calls on the president to consider the problem. The president meets one by one with each team leader, asking for detailed accounts of their decision-making process. He nds that each has engaged in relatively safe projects. As well, each has turned down some risky projects. For example, a typical risky project would return $20 million with about 50 percent probability and lose $10 million with 50 percent probability. Considering the overall budget of this individual team is only around $20 million, the president considers the decision to scuttle such risky projects sound. He compiles his report detailing the similar decision processes and abandoned opportunities from each of the eight teams to the CEO. The CEO, upon reading about the potential for eight projects, each returning about $20 million with 50 percent probability, and losing $10 million with 50 percent probability, calculates the expected value to be $40 million, with less than a 15 percent chance of losing any money. She immediately res the president of the company.

125

Соседние файлы в предмете [НЕСОРТИРОВАННОЕ]