Добавил:
Upload Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:
david_Introduction_to_behavioral_economics.pdf
Скачиваний:
50
Добавлен:
26.03.2016
Размер:
12.18 Mб
Скачать

 

 

 

 

 

234

 

DECISION UNDER RISK AND UNCERTAINTY

FIGURE 9.4

The Common Ratio

Effect in the

Marschak–Machina

Triangle

p(4,000) = 1

 

 

 

 

 

B

 

Probability of $4,000

 

 

 

 

 

 

D

p(4,000) = 0

A

 

C

p(0) = 0

Probability of $0

p(0) = 1

As with the common outcome effect, the common ratio effect is a violation of the independence axiom. This can be seen in Figure 9.4. The gambles A and B in the triangle form a line segment with the same slope as the line segment connecting C and D. Thus any indifference curve that places A to the northwest and B to the southeast would imply indifference curves that place C to the northwest and D to the southeast. Instead, the observed choice suggests that indifference curves are steeper in the western portion of the triangle than they are in the southeastern corner. As with the common outcome effect, probability weighting and regret provide two competing explanations for the violation of expected utility.

Allowing Violations of Independence

Both the common ratio and common consequence effects suggest that indifference curves are steeper in the western portion of the MarschakMachina triangle than in the southeast portion. This led some to suppose that instead of parallel indifference curves, indifference curves fan out across the MarschakMachina triangle. One way to salvage the axioms, or behavioral rules, that serve as the foundations for expected utility is to replace the independence axiom with the betweenness axiom.

Betweenness Axiom

If A B, and C is a compound gamble that yields A with probability p and B with probability 1 − p, then betweenness is satised if A C B.

 

 

 

 

Allowing Violations of Independence

 

235

 

p(100) = 1 Eu(x) = u(100)

Probability of $100

Eu(x) = u(50)

p(100) = 0

 

Eu(x) = u(0)

FIGURE 9.5

 

 

 

p(0) = 0

Probability of $0

p(0) = 1

Indifference Curves under Betweenness

The betweenness axiom allows indifference curves to have different slopes, but it still requires indifference curves to be straight lines. Thus, the indifference curves may be like those displayed in Figure 9.5. To see that indifference curves must be straight lines, consider the gambles A and B that lie on a single indifference curve. Any gamble located directly between points A and B represents a gamble that is a combination of A and B (called C in the denition). Thus, betweenness requires that the gambler be indifferent between A, B, and C, and thus C must also lie on the indifference curve.

One of the rst proposed theories to employ betweenness is called weighted expected utility theory. Let p1, .. , pn be the probabilities associated with outcomes x1, , xn. Then weighted expected utility preferences suppose that people act to maximize their weighted utility, which is given by

 

n

 

 

U =

i = 1 piu xi

.

9 31

n

 

i = 1 piv xi

 

 

Here, ux is a standard utility of wealth function, and vx constitutes some function used to weight the probabilities associated with particular outcomes. To derive indifference curves, consider all points p1, p2 such that

p1u x1 + p2u x2 + 1 − p1 − p2 u x3

= k,

9 32

 

p1v x1 + p2v x2 + 1 − p1 − p2 v x3

 

where the left side of equation 9.32 corresponds to the denition of weighted utility from equation 9.31, and the right side is just a constant. Rearranging obtains

p1 u x1 − u x3 − k v x1 − v x3 + p2 u x2 − u x3 − k v x2 − v x3

933

+ u x3 − kv x3 = 0,

 

 

 

 

 

236

 

DECISION UNDER RISK AND UNCERTAINTY

which, because outcomes and the functions u and v are xed, yields an equation of the standard linear format p1c1 + p2c2 + c3 = 0. To see that the slopes of the indifference curves may be different, note that k is a parameter of the constants c1, c2 and c3. Thus, the slope depends upon the level of utility indicated by the indifference curve.

Several have noted that the weighted utility model does t the data in the triangle signicantly better than the expected utility model. However, others have noted that there is signicant evidence that betweenness is violated. Colin Camerer and Tek-Hua Ho nd that in laboratory settings, people show clear evidence of nonlinear indifference curves. Interestingly, however, the shape of the indifference curves depends substantially on the types of gambles presented. In particular, gambles that involve losses generate a very different pattern of indifference curves from those generated by gambles involving gains.

The Shape of Indifference Curves

By repeatedly asking people to choose between pairs of gambles representing different points in the MarschakMachina triangle, experimental economists have discovered many regularities in the shapes of these indifference curves. Figure 9.6 provides an example of the general shapes of indifference curves found in laboratory experiments for gambles involving gains. In general, the curves are steeper than the 45-degree line in the northwest portion of the triangle, and they are atter than the 45-degree line in the southeast portion of the triangle. The curves display signicant fanning out around both the vertical and horizontal axes. However, the curves are close to parallel in the center of the triangle. There is some weak evidence that curves actually fan in around the hypotenuse of the triangle. Thus, the places where violations of expected utility are most likely to occur are near the edges of the triangle, where very large and very small probabilities are involved. Interestingly, when gambles with losses are examined, the indifference curves appear to be

 

Probability of highest value

FIGURE 9.6

 

Indifference Curves in

 

the Triangle for Gam-

 

bles Involving Gains

Probability of lowest value

 

 

 

 

Evidence on the Shape of Probability Weights

 

237

 

Probability of highest value

 

 

FIGURE 9.7

Probability of lowest value

 

Indifference Curves in the Triangle for Gambles

 

 

Involving Losses

reected around the 45-degree line (see Figure 9.7). This reection results in many of the same properties but some distinct differences. In particular, people appear to be more risk loving (more shallow curves) in the center of the triangle.

Evidence on the Shape of Probability Weights

Malcolm G. Preston and Philip Baratta were the rst to experiment with using probability weights to describe deviations from expected utility theory. They conducted several experiments in which they auctioned off various simple gambles (with some probability of winning an outcome and remaining probability of winning nothing). They discovered that willingness to pay for gambles was approximately linear in the amount of the reward but highly nonlinear in the probability associated with the outcome. This led them to suppose that people were misperceiving the probabilities in very systematic ways. In particular, people appeared to overweight small probabilities and underweight large probabilities. Similar work has conrmed their early ndings with respect to the general shape of these perceived probabilities. Such systematic misperceptions would explain some of the violations of expected utility such as the common ratio and common consequence effects.

One prominent theory of decision under risk supposes that people seek to maximize their perceived expected utility, where their perception is described by probability weights (discussed earlier in examples 9.3 and 9.4). Probability weights are given by a function πp, which maps probabilities onto the unit interval. Generally πp is thought to be an increasing function of the true probability, with πp > p for all p < p and πp < p for p > p. Moreover, experimental evidence suggests that π is a concave function when p < p, and a convex function when p > p. A typical probability weighting function is depicted in Figure 9.8. Generally, the xed point (the point p such that

 

 

 

 

 

238

 

DECISION UNDER RISK AND UNCERTAINTY

1

Probability weight

FIGURE 9.8

0

 

 

A Typical Probability

 

1

Weighting Function

0

Probability p

 

 

p = πp) is believed to be smaller than 0.5. One commonly used functional form for a probability weighting function is given by

π p =

pγ

 

pγ + 1 − p γ 1γ .

9 34

This function has the same inverted s-shape as the function presented in Figure 9.8. Probability weights imply subadditivity under the right circumstances (for example, if all probabilities are larger than p) and could thus explain the certainty effect. Alternatively, probability weighting would imply superadditivity (probabilities sum to greater than 1) if all outcomes had probability below p, suggesting uncertain outcomes would be unduly preferred to certain outcomes in some cases.

Finally, probability weighting functions make preferences a nonlinear function of the probabilities. For example, using the probability weighting function above, the value of a gamble would be given by

V =

n

 

piγ

 

U xi .

9 35

i = 1

γ

 

1

 

1 − pi

γ

 

 

 

pi +

γ

 

 

 

 

 

 

Given the highly nonlinear nature of the function with respect to the probabilities, the indifference curves are also necessarily very nonlinear, potentially allowing the possibility of explaining some of the fanning out or fanning in of the indifference curves. In particular, if the slope of the probability weighting function only changes substantially for very high probabilities or very low probabilities, that might explain why the indifference curves in the triangle only display changes in slope near the edges of the triangle (or where some probability is necessarily low and another is necessarily high).

Соседние файлы в предмете [НЕСОРТИРОВАННОЕ]