Добавил:
Upload Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:

aswath_damodaran-investment_philosophies_2012

.pdf
Скачиваний:
302
Добавлен:
10.06.2015
Размер:
8.32 Mб
Скачать

170

INVESTMENT PHILOSOPHIES

is transparent and can be copied by other investors. To illustrate this point, assume that stocks are consistently found to earn excess returns in the month following a stock split. Since firms announce stock splits publicly and any investor can buy stocks right after these splits, it would be surprising if this inefficiency persisted over time. This can be contrasted with the excess returns made by some funds in index arbitrage, where index futures are bought (or sold), and stocks in the index are sold short (or bought). This strategy requires that investors be able to obtain information on index and spot prices instantaneously, have the capacity (in terms of margin requirements and resources) to buy and sell index futures and to sell short on stocks, and to have the resources to take and hold very large positions until the arbitrage unwinds. Consequently, inefficiencies in index futures pricing are likely to persist at least for the most efficient arbitrageurs with the lowest execution costs and the speediest execution times.

I N E F F I C I E N C Y O R A N O M A L Y : A S I M P L E T E S T

When you do find an investment strategy that seems to beat the market, it is always an open question as to whether you have found a market mistake that can be exploited for excess returns or just a phenomenon that occurs in financial markets that you are unable to explain because the models you use are incorrect or the data you use are incomplete or erroneous. You would categorize the first as an inefficiency and the second as an anomaly. The pragmatic difference is that you should try to make money off the first but not off the second.

One way to tell the difference is to observe what happens to the excess returns once a strategy has been uncovered and publicized. If it has uncovered an inefficiency, you should see the excess returns rapidly disappear after the strategy is made public. If it is an anomaly, you will see the excess returns continue unabated even after it is publicized.

B E H A V I O R A L F I N A N C E : T H E C H A L L E N G E T O

E F F I C I E N T M A R K E T S

Underlying the notion of efficient markets is the belief that investors are for the most part rational and even when not so, that irrationalities cancel out in the aggregate. Starting in the mid-1970s, a challenge was mounted by a subset of economists, with backing from psychologists, that the belief

Too Good to Be True? Testing Investment Strategies

171

in rational investors was misplaced. They pointed to the patterns that are observable in stock prices (that we will talk about in more depth in the next section), the recurrence of price bubbles in different asset markets, and the reaction to news announcements in markets as backing for their argument. In this section, we begin by considering some of the evidence accumulated by psychologists on human behavior. We will argue that almost all investment philosophies try to exploit one investor irrationality or another and that, ironically, investor failures in applying these philosophies can be traced back to other irrationalities. Put succinctly, you are your biggest enemy when it comes to investment success.

P s y c h o l o g i c a l S t u d i e s

At the risk of stating the obvious, investors are human and it is not surprising that financial markets reflect human frailties. In an extraordinary book (at least for an academic economist), Robert Shiller presented some of the evidence accumulated of human behavior by psychologists that may help us understand financial market behavior.5 He categorizes these findings into several areas, and we consider each one.

T h e N e e d f o r A n c h o r s When confronted with decisions, it is human nature to begin with the familiar and use it to make judgments. Kahneman and Tversky, whose research has helped illuminate much of what is called behavioral finance, ran an experiment where they used a wheel of fortune with numbers from 1 to 100 to illustrate this point.6 With a group of subjects, they spun the wheel to get a number and then asked the subjects numerical questions about obscure percentages—the percentage of the ancient Egyptians who ate meat, for instance. The subjects would have to guess whether the right answer was higher or lower than the number on the wheel and then provide an estimate of the actual number. They found that the answer given by subjects was consistently influenced by the outcome of the wheel spin. Thus, if the number on the wheel was 10, the answer was more likely to be 15 or 20 percent, whereas if the number on the wheel was 60 percent, it was more likely to be 45 or 50 percent. Shiller argues that market prices provide a similar anchor with publicly traded assets. Thus, an investor asked

5R. J. Shiller, Irrational Exuberance (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2005).

6A. Tversky and D. Kahneman, “Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases,” Science 185 (1974): 1124–1131.

172

INVESTMENT PHILOSOPHIES

to estimate the value of a share is likely to be influenced by the market price, with the estimated value increasing as the market price rises.

T h e P o w e r o f t h e S t o r y For better or worse, human actions tend to be based not on quantitative factors but on storytelling. People tend to look for simple reasons for their decisions, and will often base their decision on whether these reasons exist. In a study of this phenomenon, Shafir, Simonson, and Tversky gave subjects a choice on which parent they would choose for sole custody of a child.7 One parent was described as average in every aspect of behavior and standing whereas the other was described more completely with both positive characteristics (very close relationship with child, above-average income) and negative characteristics (health problems, travels a lot). Of the subjects studied, 64 percent picked the second. Another group of subjects was given the same choice but asked which one they would deny custody to. That group also picked the second parent. These results seem inconsistent (the first group chose the second parent as the custodian and the second group rejected the same parent, given the same facts) but suggest that investors are more comfortable with investment decisions that can be justified with a strong story than one without.

O v e r c o n f i d e n c e a n d I n t u i t i v e T h i n k i n g As you have undoubtedly become aware from your interactions with friends, relatives, and even strangers over time, human beings tend to be opinionated about things they are not well informed on and to make decisions based on these opinions. In an illustrative study, Fischhoff, Slovic, and Lichtenstein asked people factual questions, and found that people gave an answer and consistently overestimated the probability that they were right. In fact, they were right only about 80 percent of the time that they thought they were.8 What are the sources of this overconfidence? One might just be evolutionary. The confidence, often in the face of poor odds, may have been what allowed us to survive and dominate as a species. The other may be more psychological. Human beings seem to have a propensity to hindsight bias; that is, they observe what happens and act as it they knew it was coming all the time. Thus, you have investors who claim to have seen the dot com crash, the housing bubble and the banking

7E. Shafir, I. Simonson, and A. Tversky, “Money Illusion,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 112 (1997): 341–374.

8B. Fischhoff, P. Slovic, and S. Lichtenstein, “Knowing with Uncertainty: The Appropriateness of Extreme Confidence,” Journal of Experimental Psychology 3 (1977): 522–564.

Too Good to Be True? Testing Investment Strategies

173

crisis coming during earlier years, though nothing in their behavior suggests that they did.

H e r d B e h a v i o r The tendency of human beings to be swayed by crowds has been long documented and used by tyrants over time to impose their will on us. In a fascinating experiment, Asch illustrated this by having a subject ask a group of people a question to which the answer was obvious; however, the other people in the group had been induced to provide the wrong answer deliberately.9 Asch noted that the subject changed his own answer one-third of the time to reflect the incorrect answer given in the group. Whereas Asch attributed this to peer pressure, subsequent studies found the same phenomenon even when the subject could not see or interact with others in the group. This would suggest that the desire to be part of the crowd or share their beliefs is due to more than peer pressure.

While there is a tendency to describe herd behavior as irrational, it is worth noting that you can have the same phenomenon occur in perfectly rational markets through a process called information cascade. Shiller provides an example of two restaurants. Assume that one person picks the first restaurant at random. The second person observes the first person eating in that restaurant and is more likely to pick the same restaurant. As the number of subjects entering the market increases, you are likely to see the crowd at the first restaurant pick up, while business at the second restaurant will be minimal. Thus, a random choice by the first customer in the market creates enough momentum to make it the dominant restaurant. In investing, all too often investors at early stages in the process (initial public offering) pile into specific initial public offerings and push their prices up. Other initial public offerings are ignored and languish at low prices. It is entirely possible that the first group of stocks will be overvalued whereas the latter are undervalued. Since herd behavior is made worse by the spreading of rumors, you could argue that the coming together of the available data and media sites such as CNBC and Bloomberg has increased herd behavior.

U n w i l l i n g n e s s t o A d m i t M i s t a k e s It may be human to err, but it is also human to claim not to err. In other words, we are much more willing to claim our successes than we are willing to face up to our failures. Kahneman and Tversky, in their experiments on human behavior, noticed that subjects when presented with choices relative to the status quo often made choices

9S. E. Asch, “Effects of Group Pressure upon the Modification and Distortion of Judgment,” in H. Guertzkow, ed., Groups, Leadership, and Men (Pittsburgh, PA: Carnegie Press, 1951).

174

INVESTMENT PHILOSOPHIES

based on unrealistic expectations. They noted that a person who has not made peace with his losses is likely to accept gambles that would otherwise be unacceptable to him. Anyone who has visited a casino will attest to this finding.

In investing, Shefrin and Statman call this the disposition effect, i.e., the tendency to hold on to losers too long and to sell winners too soon.10 They argue that it is widespread and can cause systematic mispricing of some stocks. Terrance Odean used the trading records of over 10,000 customers at a discount brokerage house to examine whether there is evidence of this behavior among investors.11 He noted that investors realized only 9.8 percent of their losses each year, whereas they realized 14.8 percent of their gains.12 He also finds that investors seem to hold on to losers too long and to sell winners too soon. Overall, he argues that there is evidence of the disposition effect among investors.

T h e E v i d e n c e

While it is evident that human beings do not always behave rationally, it does not necessarily follow that markets will also be irrational. In fact, you could argue (as some believers in market efficiency do) that markets can be efficient even with irrational investors for several reasons. First, it is possible that there is a selection process that occurs in markets where irrational investors lose consistently to rational investors and eventually get pushed out of the market. Second, it is also possible that irrationalities cut in both directions—some leading investors to buy when they should not and others leading them to sell when they should not; if these actions offset each other, you could still have a market price that is unaffected by irrational investors. The only way to resolve this debate is to look at the evidence on the presence or absence of irrationality in market behavior.

One of the problems that we face when we test for irrationality in financial markets is the number of variables that cannot be controlled for. Investors enter and leave markets, new information arrives constantly, and the macroeconomic environment changes frequently, making it impossible to construct a controlled experiment. A few researchers have attempted to get around this problem by constructing experimental studies, similar

10H. Shefrin and M. Statman, “The Disposition to Sell Winners Too Early and Ride Losers Too Long: Theory and Evidence,” Journal of Finance 40 (1985): 777–790.

11T. Odean, “Are Investors Reluctant to Realize Their Losses?” Journal of Finance

53(1998): 1775–1798.

12The only month in which more losses are realized than gains is December.

Too Good to Be True? Testing Investment Strategies

175

to those used by psychologists and sociologists in the previous section, to examine how investors behave in financial markets.

The most interesting evidence from experiments is what we learn about quirks in human behavior, even in the simplest of settings. In fact, Kahneman and Tversky’s challenge to conventional economic utility theory was based on their awareness of the experimental research in psychology. In this section, we cover some of the more important of these findings.

Framing. Kahneman and Tversky noted that describing a decision problem differently, even when the underlying choices remain the same, can lead to different decisions and measures of risk aversion. In their classic example, they asked subjects to choose between two responses to a disease threat: the first response, they said, would save 200 people out of a population of 600, but in the second, they noted that “there is a one-third probability that everyone will be saved and a two-thirds probability that no one will be saved.” While the net effect of both responses is exactly the same mathematically—400 die and 200 are saved— 72 percent of the respondents picked the first option. Kahneman and Tversky termed this phenomenon “framing” and argued that both utility models and experimenters have to deal with the consequences.13

Loss aversion. Loss aversion refers to the tendency of individuals to prefer avoiding losses to making gains. In an experiment, Kahneman and Tversky offer an example of loss aversion. The first offered subjects a choice between the following:

Option A: A guaranteed payout of $250.

Option B: A 25 percent chance to gain $1,000 and a 75 percent chance of getting nothing.

Of the respondents, 84 percent chose the sure option A over option B (with the same expected payout but much greater risk), which was not surprising, given risk aversion. They then reframed the question and offered the same subjects the following choices:

Option C: A sure loss of $750.

Option D: A 75 percent chance of losing $1,000 and a 25 percent chance to lose nothing.

13A. Tversky and D. Kahneman, “The Framing of Decisions and the Psychology of Choice,” Science 211 (1981): 453–458.

176

INVESTMENT PHILOSOPHIES

Now, 73 percent of respondents preferred the gamble (option D, with an expected loss of $750) over the certain loss (option C). Kahneman and Tversky noted that stating the question in terms of a gain resulted in different choices than framing it in terms of a loss.14 Loss aversion implies that individuals will prefer an uncertain gamble to a certain loss as long as the gamble has the possibility of no loss, even though the expected value of the uncertain loss may be higher than the certain loss.

Benartzi and Thaler combined loss aversion with the frequency with which individuals checked their accounts (what they called “mental accounting”) to create the composite concept of myopic loss aversion.15 Haigh and List provided an experimental test that illustrates the proposition where they ran a sequence of nine lotteries with subjects, but varied how they provided information on the outcomes.16 To one group, they provided feedback after each round, allowing them to thus react to success or failure on that round. To the other group, they withheld feedback until three rounds were completed and provided feedback on the combined outcome over the three rounds. They found that people were willing to bet far less in the frequent feedback group than in the pooled feedback group, suggesting that loss aversion becomes more acute if individuals have shorter time horizons and assess success or failure at the end of these horizons.

House money effect. Generically, the house money effect refers to the phenomenon that individuals are more willing to take risks (and are thus less risk averse) with found money (obtained easily) than with earned money. Consider the experiment where 10 subjects were each given $30 at the start of the game and offered the choice of either doing nothing or flipping a coin to win or lose $9; seven chose the coin flip. Another set of 10 subjects were offered no initial funds but offered a choice of either taking $30 with certainty or flipping a coin and winning $39 if it came up heads or $21 if it came up tails. Only 43 percent chose the coin flip, even though the final consequences (ending up with $21 or $39) are the same in both experiments. Thaler and Johnson illustrate the house money effect with an experiment in which subjects were offered a

14A. Tversky and D. Kahneman, “Loss Aversion in Riskless Choice: A ReferenceDependent Model,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 106 (1991): 1038–1061.

15Shlomo Benartzi and Richard Thaler, “Myopic Loss Aversion and the Equity Premium Puzzle,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 110 (1995): 73–92.

16M. S. Haigh and J. A. List, “Do Professional Traders Exhibit Myopic Loss Aver-

sion? An Experimental Analysis,” Journal of Finance 45 (2005): 523–534.

Too Good to Be True? Testing Investment Strategies

177

sequence of lotteries. In the first lottery, subjects were given a chance to win $15 and were offered a subsequent lottery where they had a 50–50 chance of winning or losing $4.50. While many of these same subjects would have rejected the second lottery if it had been offered as an initial choice, 77 percent of those who won the first lottery (and made $15) took the second lottery.17

Break-even effect. The break-even effect is the flip side of the house money effect and refers to the attempts of those who have lost money to make it back. In particular, subjects in experiments who have lost money seem willing to gamble on lotteries (that standing alone would be viewed as unattractive) that offer them a chance to break even. The study by Thaler and Johnson that uncovered the house money effect also found the break-even effect. In a study of sequenced lotteries, researchers found that subjects who lost money on the first lottery generally became more risk averse in the second lottery except when the second lottery offered them a chance to make up their first-round losses and break even.18

In summary, the findings from experimental studies offer grist for the behavioral finance mill. Whether or not we buy into all of the implications, it is clear that there are systematic quirks in human behavior that cannot be easily dismissed as irrational or aberrant since they are so widespread and long-standing.

As a side note, many of these experimental studies have been run using inexperienced subjects (usually undergraduate students) and professionals (traders in financial markets, experienced businesspeople) to see if age and experience play a role in making people more rational. The findings are not promising for the rational human school, since the consensus view across these studies is that experience and age do not seem to confer rationality in subjects and that some of the anomalies noted in this section are attenuated with experience. Professional traders exhibit more myopic loss aversion than undergraduate students do, for instance. The behavioral patterns indicated

17R. H. Thaler and E. J. Johnson, “Gambling with the House Money and Trying to Break Even: The Effects of Prior Outcomes on Risky Choice,” Management Science

36(1990): 643–660. They also document a house-loss effect, where those who lose in the initial lottery become more risk averse at the second stage, but the evidence from other experimental studies on this count is mixed.

18R. C. Battalio, J. H. Kagel, and K. Jiranyakul, “Testing between Alternative Models of Choice under Uncertainty: Some Initial Results,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty

3(1990): 25–50.

178

INVESTMENT PHILOSOPHIES

in this section are also replicated in experiments using business settings (projects with revenues, profits, and losses) and experienced managers.19 Finally, we should resist the temptation to label these behaviors as irrational. Much of what we observe in human behavior seems to be hardwired into our systems and cannot be easily eliminated (if at all). In fact, a study in the journal Psychological Science examined the decisions made by 15 people with normal IQs and reasoning skills but with damage to the portions of the brain that control emotions.20 They confronted this group and a control group of normal individuals with 20 rounds of a lottery in which they could win $2.50 or lose a dollar, and found that the inability to feel emotions such as fear and anxiety made the brain-damaged individuals more willing to take risks with high payoffs and less likely to react emotionally to previous wins and losses. Overall, the brain-impaired participants finished with about 13 percent higher winnings than normal people who were offered the same gambles.

T e s t i n g M a r k e t E f f i c i e n c y

Tests of market efficiency look at whether specific investment strategies or portfolio managers beat the market. But what does beating the market involve? Does it just imply that someone earns a return greater than what the market (say, the S&P 500) earns in a specific year? We begin by looking at what beating the market requires and define what we mean be excess returns. We will then follow up by looking at three standard ways of testing market efficiency and when and why we may choose one over the other.

B e a t i n g t h e M a r k e t The fundamental question that we often attempt to answer when we test an investment strategy is whether the return we earn from the strategy is above or below a benchmark return on an alternative strategy of equivalent risk. But what should that benchmark return be? As we will see, it is almost impossible to measure the success or failure of an investment strategy without taking a point of view on how risk should be measured.

19K. Sullivan, “Corporate Managers’ Risky Behavior: Risk Taking or Avoiding,”

Journal of Financial and Strategic Decisions 10 (1997): 63–74.

20S. Baba, G. Lowenstein, A. Bechara, H. Damasio, and A. Damasio, “Investment Behavior and the Negative Side of Emotion,” Psychological Science 16 (2005): 435–

439.The damage to the individuals was created by strokes or disease and prevented them from feeling emotions.

Too Good to Be True? Testing Investment Strategies

179

Performance Benchmarks If you can estimate the returns that you could have made by adopting an investment strategy in the past or observed the returns made by a portfolio manager or investor over a period, you can evaluate those returns. To make the evaluation, you have to choose an appropriate benchmark. In this section, we consider two alternatives that are available to us in making this choice.

1.Comparison to indexes. When you have estimated the returns on a strategy, the simplest comparison you can make is to the returns you would have made by investing in an index. Many portfolio managers and investors still compare the returns they make on their portfolios to the returns on the S&P 500 index. While this comparison may be simple, it can also be dangerous when you have a strategy that does not have the same risk as investing in the index, and the bias can cut both ways. If you have a strategy that is riskier than investing in the index—investing in small, high-growth stocks, say—you are biasing yourself toward concluding that the strategy works (i.e., it beats the market). If you have a strategy that is much safer than investing in the index, such as buying shares of high-dividend-paying, mature companies, you are biasing yourself toward concluding that the strategy does not work.

There are slightly more sophisticated versions of this approach that are less susceptible to this problem. For instance, some services that judge mutual funds do so by comparing them to an index of funds that have the same style as the fund being judged. Thus, a fund that invests in large market capitalization companies with low price-to-book ratios will be compared to other large-cap value funds. The peril remains, though, since categorizing investors into neat boxes is easier said than done. A fund manager may begin the year calling herself a largecap value investor and during the course of the year shift to being an investor in high-growth, risky companies.

2.Risk and return models. In Chapter 2, we considered the basics of risk and put forth several risk and return models. All of these models tried to measure the risk in an investment, though they differed on how best to measure it, and related the expected return on the investment to the risk measure. You could use these models to measure the risk in an investment strategy, and then examine the returns relative to this risk measure. We will consider some of these risk-adjusted measures of performance in this section.

Mean-Variance Measures The simplest measures of risk-adjusted performance have their roots in the mean-variance framework developed by Harry