Добавил:
Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:

coons_c_weber_m_eds_paternalism_theory_and_practice

.pdf
Скачиваний:
1
Добавлен:
29.10.2019
Размер:
3.32 Mб
Скачать

Introduction: Paternalism – Issues and trends

21

we choose the less healthy items in the cafeteria despite being nudged towards the healthy ones or we indeed choose the more healthy ones. If we resist and choose the less-healthy items then the nudge has been unsuccessful. As such, this would not constitute an instance of morally acceptable paternalism; it is only attempted paternalism. If instead we do in fact choose the more healthy options, it is unclear whether this counts as paternalism either. For now it seems more like the cafeteria patron has been simply reminded by the sign to think (explicitly) about eating more healthily. What leads him to the healthy choice is that he has been reminded of the importance of eating healthily, and not because of the psychological mechanisms nudges target. In other words, transparent choice architecture appears to be more akin to providing information, giving advice, or engaging in rational persuasion. And as Hausman and Welch pointed out, this is not paternalism at all.

All that being said, it is hard to avoid thinking that many of the nudges Thaler and Sunstein recommend are rather benign. Do we really need to get all up in arms about setting defaults that enroll people in retirement programs? Perhaps not. But there are things to be worried about here. First, there remains the problem of non-standard actors: Someone with a very short life expectancy could well be harmed by being enrolled in a standard retirement plan if it involves contributing a portion of his income, as he will never enjoy the benets in his retirement. Similarly for someone set to inherit a large sum upon retirement (at age sixty-ve). And again, although every choice architecture will have its victims,when a nudge is intended the unfortunate have special grounds for complaint: The state tried to push them towards the disastrous option, knowing that for some this push will be successful and disastrous. And though one might reply that pushis too strong a word because individual nudges(by stipulation) are easy to resist this reply is little comfort given that Thaler and Sunstein never address the concern that nudges might be stackedwithin and across choice architectures, e.g., the food could be ordered a particular way, presented a particular way, listed on menus in most attractive fonts, etc. This possibility clearly illustrates that there can be more or less nudgingin an environment, and again raises the question whether trying to reduce or avoid these inuences is the best option, even if some inuence is inevitable.

Thaler and Sunstein would presumably object to stackingnudges because collectively they might constitute a shove.Thus proper use of the power to nudge will require choice architects, and those who monitor them, to be self-conscious and careful about the manner and degree to

22 christian coons and michael weber

which they inuence our preferences. Put plainly and unatteringly, they need to adopt their role as a manipulator of preference and be vigilant about not misusing it. But this leads us to our nal worry about the libertarian paternalist program. Specically, theres something unsettling, maybe even something somewhat incoherent, about viewing oneself as one who manipulates preference because it is less objectionable than coercion. Indeed, though many of their proposed nudges seem innocuous, libertarian paternalism, when considered at an abstract distance, can seem even more sinister than its coercive or option-removing cousin. To get a sense of our worry, rst notice that debates about paternalism can be fundamentally framed in terms of conicts between an individuals choices and her well-being. We will not always choose whats best for ourselves, or even what is best by our own lights. When we wont the paternalist nds it sometimes justied to act to prevent these imprudent or subjectively suboptimalchoices. Traditional paternalism typically pushes us away from these choices by dramatically changing the cost of making such decisions. State paternalism often imposes nes or penal sanctions for making such choices. Less controversially, the state can attach incentives to choices deemed best for its citizens, thereby making putative suboptimal choices costlyin terms of benets foregone. These measures rarely involve actual physical force; instead they make choosing in a way deemed imprudentcostly costly relative to the targets own evaluative perspective. The traditional paternalist thus takes e orts to articially ensure it is irrational (by the subjects own lights) to make choices deemed imprudent, but he does not alter the targets fundamental evaluations. Rather he changes the external environment in a way that makes those fundamental evaluations now favor the prudentoptions. This is clearly in some sense disrespectful to the person and his perspective about what is to be done, because he might have otherwise wanted to choose something else. In rigging the external cost structure for his sakethe paternalist e ectively disregards his ability to make prudent decisions, and disregards his own, would-be view about what choice to make.

Libertarian paternalism might initially be thought of as operating in exactly the same way, the only di erence being that the external costs imposed are somewhat smaller. If that is so, then we have a di erence in degree and not kind: The traditional anti-paternalist will view the program as unjust but presumably better than more traditional forms of paternalism. However, that is probably the wrong way to view many nudges. The biases of our automatic systems do not reect the weightings of options relative to our evaluative perspective we do not judge that we have more

Introduction: Paternalism – Issues and trends

23

reason to choose items that we are o ered rst, or that we have more reason to choose a default. We do, however, judge ourselves as having reason to seek nancial incentives and avoid nes. In this way, the traditional paternalist at least treats us as rational by appealing to what we value, and what we ourselves take ourselves as having reason to do (even if only like the gunman who says your money or your life).

The libertarian paternalist, as manifested in at least some of Thaler and Sunsteins proposed nudges, takes measures to make us act on features we do not take to be reason-giving. E ectively, these nudges change our (relative) evaluation of options without appealing to our current evaluations or view about what provides reasons. Seen this way, libertarian paternalism involves a much deeper disrespect of its target. The traditional paternalist may be accused of ignoring the targets own view of what is to be done, or worse, turning that own view against her by changing the external environment so that the favored optionnow becomes rational relative to her own point of view. The libertarian paternalist, on the other hand, does not ignore the targets point of view, or use it against her; rather he sees her perspective itself as something to be fashioned or altered. But if we think of the agent as partly constituted by her evaluative perspective, libertarian paternalism is apparently a threat to the agent herself, and not just the unimpeded expression of her evaluative outlook. Our targets are no longer beings whose choices, but not evaluations, are to be guided. Rather, were engaged in a project that more directly shapes the targets preferences and evaluations themselves. If traditional and libertarian paternalism really are distinct in this way, libertarian paternalism though noncoercive may seem worse and less justiable than more traditional forms. It may seem worse because the targets view of what is to be done is no longer merely ignored or thwarted, but is rather viewed as something one may attempt to extinguish, supplant, or manage.There may be a deep tension in thinking our viewpoints are subject to management, but our actions should not be. One might alternatively put our preliminary worry this way: If traditional paternalism is somehow guilty of violatingour rights to autonomy or self-sovereignty, libertarian paternalism treats us as beings that could not even be owed such rights.32

32Many of the points being made here are consistent with Hausman and Welchs criticism, and could plausibly be seen as explicating and expanding upon the worry they only begin to develop in their review article. They suggest that choice architects shaping peoples evaluation and choice is incompatible with autonomy. This seems right. However, no explanation of the incompatibility is provided. The comments here, though themselves not fully worked out or conclusive, might plausibly be seen as a beginning of providing just such an explanation.

24 christian coons and michael weber

Ultimately, it remains unclear what precisely, if anything, is wrong with paternalism. And answering this question has become even more di cult as weve become more aware of the fact that it neednt be accompanied with the dubious features typically associated with it: coercion, removal of choice, and the imposition of values on its targets. Though this suggests that paternalism is benign in the absence of these features, as weve just seen, it may be possible to argue that some paternalism without these features may be worse. Of course, not much rides on whether paternalism always has a bad-making feature or not. Our trouble in identifying such a feature simply reveals the complexity of the issue. There are no easy answers. It appears unreasonable to reject paternalistic policies because they are paternalistic; but equally unreasonable to welcome paternalism when it lacks the evils typically associated with it. Further investigation is needed, but its promise neednt merely be a clearer view about if, when, and how to paternalize. It promises to further illuminate more general moral issues about the relationship between persons, the state, and its citizens, and the substantive content of central rights and values. We view all the works in this volume as valuable contributions to this investigation.

chapter 1

Defining paternalism

Gerald Dworkin

There are three concepts all of them vague. Imagine 3 solid pieces of stone. You pick them up, t them together and now nd they make a ball. What youve now got tells you something about the 3 shapes. Now consider you have 3 balls of, or lumps of soft mud or putty formless. Now you put them together and mold out of them a ball.

Wittgenstein, from Bouwsma, Wittgenstein: Conversations, 1949–1951

The merit of any denition . . . depends upon the soundness of the theory that results; by itself, a denition cannot settle any fundamental question.

Rawls, A Theory of Justice

Any denition of a concept is subject to various criteria for a good denition in the context at hand. Unless we are simply stipulating how we shall be using the word and even then questions will arise about why we picked that word to use for this stipulation there will be some, usually implicit, ideas of what makes for a good denition. In addition to trivial ones such as consistency there will be a set of problems that the denition will be used to clarify or, if possible, resolve. There will be a set of constraints weak or strong on how the word is currently being used. There will be a context perhaps one of personal ethics or perhaps one of current law in which the concept nds a place. There will be some conceptual or normative issues that will be used to assess the usefulness or correctness of the denition.

There may be stipulated criteria, e.g., that the concept should not settle some particular normative matter, thereby avoiding what Hart has called the denitional stop.For example, if one denes terrorism as the morally illegitimate use of violence on innocent persons then the question of whether terrorism is ever morally legitimate has been settled by the denition. Sometimes, this is not an objection to a denition. If we dene murderas the wrongful taking of human life then although we cannot raise the question of whether murder is ever right, we can raise the

25

26

gerald dworkin

question of whether some killing of a human being is murder. I am going to begin by canvassing a wide variety of denitions of paternalism which may have been developed in quite di erent contexts for quite di erent purposes. It is helpful both to see how wide the variety is and to see the various dimensions along which the denitions vary.

The rst crucial dimension is what the term is predicated of. People can be paternalistic. Reasons can be reasons of paternalism. Motivations can be paternalistic. Institutions can be paternalistic. Acts can be paternalistic. Policies can be paternalistic. It may be that acts are primary in some denitions with the other elements being dened in terms of acts, or the order might be the reverse. But I shall be concerned primarily with the notion of a paternalistic act or the notion of a paternalistic policy.

dimensions

Outcomes vs. motives

A paternalistic act may be dened in terms of the outcomes it produces. If a state enacts legislation requiring boaters to wear life jackets, and if wearing life jackets is benecial to the interests of boaters, then this is an act of paternalism. The alternative view is that whether an act is paternalistic or not cannot be determined without reference to the reasons for which the state acts. Two acts may have the same outcome, an improvement of B, yet only one counts as paternalistic.

Actual vs. hypothetical motives

An act may be dened as paternalistic in terms of the reason for which A acts. If she has more than one reason there is an issue of how to specify the relation between her various reasons and the characterization of the act. If we are considering a piece of legislation which is passed by many voters, with di ering reasons, the issue is even more complex. But in both cases it is the actual reasons which must be considered.

The alternative view is that the reasons which count in determining whether an act is paternalistic are the hypothetical reasons which could motivate or justify the act. So a doctors lying to a patient about his terminal condition is paternalistic because considerations of the patients welfare would have led to his lying (even if his current act was motivated by a desire to avoid a long discussion after a tiring day).

Defining paternalism

27

Motives vs. reasons

As opposed to what explains the act, the motives for which the agent acts, the important question may be whether there are reasons which are su cient to justify the policy which are of the appropriate kind. The agent may have acted, say, to promote the interests of third-parties; but if there are reasons which refer to Bs welfare, and such reasons are su cient to justify the act, then the act is paternalistic.

normative constraints

A’s act must violate B’s autonomy vs. A’s act need not be a violation of B’s autonomy

Consider the case where a husband hides his sleeping pills because he fears that his wife may nd them and use them to commit suicide. A denition of paternalism might classify the husbands act as nonpaternalistic on the grounds that what A does is not a violation of a sphere of autonomy of his wife. She has no right that he keep his sleeping pills in clear view. Or, one might consider the act as paternalistic even while conceding this point. In some sense he substitutes his judgment for hers in the belief that his judgment is better than hers. Obviously, interference with autonomy is not a su cient condition for an acts being paternalistic. I interfere with your autonomy when I steal your bicycle but that is not a case of paternalism. The issue is whether it is a necessary condition. Can I act paternalistically towards B even if I do not in any way violate his autonomy? I speak of autonomyrather than, say, libertybecause paradigm cases of acting paternalistically, such as a doctor lying to his patient, might not be considered infringements of liberty.

Acts vs. omissions

Is paternalism dened only over the range of actions, or can it include failures to act as well? If I push you out of the way of a car to avoid injury, this could be thought to be paternalistic.

Suppose I do not push you out of the way (when I could), envisaging minor bruises and scrapes, so that you will miss a business meeting where I believe you will make a seriously mistaken deal. Is that paternalistic?

28

gerald dworkin

Against your consent vs. failing to consider whether you consent or not

If I act knowing that you do not (or would not) consent to what I am doing, I act against your consent. If I act not knowing whether you consent (or would consent) or not, I act without your consent. A related question is whether the test is objective or subjective, i.e., whether the issue is whether you have consented (whether or not I know this) or whether I believe you have consented (whether or not you have).

Interests at stake

The most common denitions of paternalism make reference to the welfare/interest of the person whose autonomy is being limited. The broadest denition I have encountered is that of Seana Shi rin who denes paternalism in such a way that the beneciary of the action may be, and may be intended to be, someone other than the person towards whom we are acting paternalistically.1 I will return to this denition later.

Physical welfare vs. moral

The issue here is whether the harm to be avoided is psychological or physical, such as death or torment, or is moral such as being corrupted or degraded. Moral paternalism is to be distinguished from legal moralism. In the latter case the grounds for acting are that the conduct in question is wrong or evil but not that it harms the agent who acts in these ways. It is a distinct, substantive question of whether, for example, if your character is made worse by what you do, you are worse o , i.e., whether your wellbeing is diminished. Some philosophers such as Plato have asserted the truth of this view. Some philosophers such as Feinberg have denied it.

definitions

Given the number of these dimensions, and the possibility of combining the dimensions in various ways, there are obviously a large number of denitions that are possible. Obviously not all possibilities have been seriously put forward for acceptance. But the variety is larger than might be thought and I will set out a number of proposed denitions to give the reader an idea of what such a variety might look like.

1 Shi rin, Paternalism, Unconscionability Doctrine, and Accommodation.

4 Ibid., 177.

Defining paternalism

29

Definition A

X acts paternalistically towards Y by doing (or omitting) Z if and only if:

(1) Z (or its omission) interferes with the liberty or autonomy of Y (2) X does so without the consent of Y

(3) X does so just because doing Z will improve the welfare of Y (where this includes preventing his welfare from diminishing), or in some way promote the interests, values, or good of Y.2

Definition B

The second denition is from an economics paper by Sunstein and Thaler.3 If an employer is attempting to steer employeeschoices in directions that will promote employeeswelfare,he is acting paternalistically.4 Thus, if an employer automatically enrolls an employee in the companys 401k plan (with the option to withdraw at any time) this counts for them as paternalistic. Elsewhere, Sunstein claims that the anti-paternalist position is incoherent, simply because there is no way to avoid e ects on behavior and choices.5 This denition does not require any interference with liberty, or coercion, or infringement upon autonomy. If an action has e ects on choices, and one intends those e ects because they will enhance the welfare of the person being a ected, then on their denition the action is paternalistic.

2 See Dworkin, Paternalism.Condition one is the trickiest to capture. Clear cases include threatening, bodily compulsion, lying, withholding information that the person has a right to have, and imposing requirements or conditions. But what about the following case? A father, skeptical about the nancial acumen of a child, instead of bequeathing the money directly, gives it to another child with instructions to use it in the best interests of the rst child. The rst child has no legal claim on the inheritance. There does not seem to be interference with the childs liberty; nor on most conceptions the childs autonomy.

Or consider the case of a wife who hides her sleeping pills so that her potentially suicidal husband cannot use them. Her act may satisfy the second and third conditions but what about the rst? Does her action limit the liberty or autonomy of her husband?

The second condition is supposed to be read as distinct from acting against the consent of an agent. The agent may neither consent nor not consent. He may, for example, be unaware of what is being done to him. There is also the distinct issue of whether one acts not knowing about the consent of the person in question. Suppose the person in fact consents but this is not known to the paternalizer.

3 Thaler and Sunstein, Libertarian Paternalism.

5 Sunstein, The Laws of Fear, 195.

30

gerald dworkin

Definition C

X acts paternalistically towards Y by doing (or omitting) Z if and only if:

(1) X aims to close an option that would otherwise be open to Y or X chooses for Y in the event that Y is unable to choose for himself

(2) X does so, to some extent, in order to promote Ys good.6

Definition D

X acts paternalistically in regard to Y to the extent that X, in order to secure Ys good, as an end, imposes upon Y.7

Definition E

X acts (hard) paternalistically with regard to Y if:

(1) X restricts Ys liberty

(2) X does so primarily out of benevolence towards Y (3) X must disregard Ys contemporaneous preferences

(4) X must either disregard whether Y engages in the restricted conduct voluntarily or deliberately limits Ys voluntary conduct.8

Definition F

Essentially the preceding with (4) replaced by: Xs action must be a violation of a moral rule or X recognizes (or should) that his action towards Y needs moral justication.9

Definition G

A policy is paternalistic if it limits a persons liberty for her own good, or for the reason that it benets her or improves her situation in some way. To limit a persons liberty for her own goodis to limit her liberty for a certain kind of reason: that this policy will promote her welfare or improve her situation in some way.

6 Clarke, A Denition of Paternalism.

7 Kleinig, Paternalism.

8Pope, Counting the Dragons Teeth and Claws.

9Gert and Culver, The Justication of Paternalism.