Добавил:
Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:

coons_c_weber_m_eds_paternalism_theory_and_practice

.pdf
Скачиваний:
0
Добавлен:
29.10.2019
Размер:
3.32 Mб
Скачать

Choice Architecture: Preserving liberty?

191

eating healthily emerged from her roommates actions. As Dworkin notes of the classic gunman example where a gunman threatens to shoot a victim if he does not hand over his money, People resent acting merely in order to retain a status quo against the interference of another agent (threats).33 Jane likely resents acting for her roommates deceptive and manipulative actions. I do not mean to suggest that all cases of manipulation, or of choice architecture, necessarily impair autonomy (or that the ones that do, do so to the same extent), but they certainly raise red ags that are worth investigation.34

One way to combat choice architecture hindering the exercise of autonomy is to make it transparent to those who encounter it. In fact, Thaler and Sunstein do toy with the idea of transparency. In order to express the transparency requirement they draw on Rawls’ “publicity principle,which would ban interventions that choice architects would not be able or willing to defend publicly.35 The problem with this requirement is that it is only hypothetical. Certainly, considering whether one would hypothetically be able or willing to defend a choice environment design offers some normative guidance for the choice architect, but it is not sufcient to preserve freedom of choice and action. In order to preserve freedom of choice and action, the transparency would need to be actual not merely hypothetical. How this transparency requirement would be fullled would vary from case to case. In some cases, the choice architecture and its intention will be readily transparent and nothing would need to be disclosed, in other cases a verbal disclosure would be best, and in some cases a posted written disclosure would be best.

But of course, disclosure and transparency is not enough to preserve liberty since manipulation (which at least poses a threat to a persons ability to govern themselves) occurs not just when a person is inuenced without knowing it, but when they are inuenced via exploitation of the non-rational elements of their psychological makeup. Return to the

33Dworkin, The Theory and Practice of Autonomy, 155.

34Hausman and Welch do think that all cases of nudgingthat involve taking advantage of peoples psychological foiblesimpair autonomy. See Hausman and Welch, Debate,128, 133. Although, from this they extrapolate that the use of decisional psychology techniques to shape peoples decisions should be avoided and that rational persuasion (the use of data and valid arguments) is the only defensible alternative. Yet, they repeatedly acknowledge the difculty and potential impossibility of the use of rational persuasion (data and valid arguments) alone, acknowledging that what may be doing the persuasive work is the accompanying soft smile, aura of authority, order in which the data is presented, etc. Thus, I nd their position untenable since it merely turns a blind eye to the facts and promotes denial instead of responsible reection on and management of the factors that shape peoples choices.

35Thaler and Sunstein, Nudge, 244.

192

j. s. blumenthal-barby

example of Janes roommate who places unattering mirrors around the apartment. Even if the roommate transparently tells Jane what she is trying to do, by using the mirrors in her choice environment she is exploiting her desire to feel attractive, her guilt, etc. Part of what is threatening to Janes liberty here, as is true with many cases of manipulation via exploitation of emotion, is that Janes roommate is making it very hard for Jane to go her own wayand eat the junk food.

The problem of blocking or burdening choices

The notion that we must avoid making it hard for a person to discern her options and act according to her preferences is essential for the preservation of liberty. In order to fully preserve liberty choice architecture must not block off or signicantly burden other choices. Of course, developing criteria for when choice architecture is easilyovercome or avoided is tricky, but I will attempt to make a few guiding remarks here. In an attempt to deal with this challenge, Thaler and Sunstein write, We do not have a clear denition of easily avoided,. . . It would be arbitrary and a bit ridiculous to offer an inexible rule to specify when costs are high enough to disqualify a policy as libertarian, but the precise question of degree is not really important. Let us simply say that we want those costs to be small.36

It is true that it would be arbitrary to offer such an inexible rule, simply because liberty, freedom, and autonomy are concepts best conceptualized as degree concepts that lie on a spectrum. There are, however, a couple of points to make. First, the costsof avoiding or overcoming an instance of inuence via choice architecture can take many different forms. For example, a person may have to give up time, take on an annoyance, walk a little further, pay a little more money, or forfeit some money or material goods, execute willpower, feel bad about himself (self-scorn), undergo social scorn, or have to think a little harder. The second point is that the cost of willpower is particularly important since it threatens a persons ability to govern themselves the way that they want to govern themselves; it threatens their autonomy and as such their freedom of choice and action.

Consider an example of a woman, Susan, who wants her colleague David to become romantically involved with her; but David does not want to become involved with her, so Susan exploits his weakness for the scent of lavender and designs a choice environment that involves a lot of

36Ibid., 251. Interestingly, while here the adjective that they use for the costs is small,at other times they use close to zero.

Choice Architecture: Preserving liberty?

193

lavender. Susan is not blocking off any options for David, and it is not as if David has to pay a substantial amount of money or forfeit a lot of his time in order to overcome Susans architecture, but it does require a lot of willpower. The fact that extensive willpower is necessary makes it difcult for him to govern himself the way that he wants to. Davids autonomy is threatened despite the fact that Susans attempts are transparent, and it is threatened because the architecture requires that David muster a lot of willpower making it difcult for him to go his own way.

To sum up then, in order for an instance of choice architecture to be liberty-preserving in a meaningful way, choice architects must ensure that (1) other choices are not blocked off, (2) avoiding or overcoming the inuence attempt is easy and can be done with low material, physical, temporal, mental, and willpower costs, and (3) inuence attempts are transparent and/or that the person inuenced would not mind acting for reasons of the choice architecture. It truly must be easy for a person to go her own way, to govern herself.37

What would a true libertarian do?

Some might object that a true libertarianwould not engage in choice architecture at all. Instead, they would favor ways to help people make better decisions that do not involve architecting their decisions for them. One way that is often mentioned is to use mandated choice,whereby instead of inuencing people towards a particular choice, we force them to make their own choice. The second way is to debiaspeople instead of rebiasingthem. In other words, one might recognize that human decision-making is full of biases and errors that result in less than optimal and sometimes harmful decisions, but hold that the response should be to strip people of these harmful biases instead of rebiasing them towards better decisions. I will take each point in turn. Regarding the option of mandated choice, I have two responses. One is that often people do not want to choose. Choosing requires a lot of time, energy, and psychological burden not to mention that the person must enhance their expertise in the area that they are making a choice about. For example, policy-makers

37An interesting side issue about liberty that I will raise, though not address in this paper, is the issue about the freedom of institutions/companies to choose not to engage in choice architecture to promote peoples well-being and the overarching regulatory issues that might be raised by institutions/companies that choose not to engage in choice architecture for the good of their consumers or clients (e.g., the supermarket manager who refuses to put the fruits and vegetables near the front of the store and the unhealthy goods in the back).

194

j. s. blumenthal-barby

could force me to make a choice about which retirement plan I join, but I would be none too happy about the time and energy that I would have to spend investigating all of the options. As Thaler and Sunstein note, Given that people would often choose not to choose, it is hard to see why freedom lovers should compel choice even though people (freely and voluntarily) resist it.38 And of course, those who do want to investigate the options and make the choice themselves can certainly do so. The second point that I want to make regarding mandated choice is that it does not avoid inuencing peoples choices. Imagine that someone is describing retirement plans to me and instead of setting a default such that I am enrolled in the plan that suits me best, they force me to make a choice. The person still has to describe the options to me; and my choice will be unavoidably inuenced by the order and manner in which they present the options. So for the libertarian, mandated choice is not a realistic or better alternative to choice architecture.

What about the approach of identifying the biases that are resulting in bad decisions and trying to remove them? Why not encourage people to use their reective systems more in decision-making instead of setting up things so that their continued use of their automatic systems will result in better outcomes? Why not just inform people and educate them? Mitchell is an advocate of this debiasing approachand cites several studies showing that asking experimental subjects to consider alternative or opposing options or arguments ameliorated the effects of several biases.39 I have two responses to this approach. One is that even if you work to rid someone of one of their biases and do so successfully, other biases are still present and new ones have likely been introduced in the process. It is simply impossible to completely debias someone and make them into a rational, robotic, calculating decision-maker. It is impossible to avoid inuencing peoples choices. It is impossible to be neutral no matter how scrupulously designers try to achieve that goal.40 This is the key lesson from behavioral psychology, behavioral economics, and decision science. Second, even if one could debias people via the presentation of (neutral) information, education, and engagement of the reective system, this approach is simply not practical and as such is not desirable. Much of decision-making simply does not have the opportunity for this sort of extensive intervention. We make dozens of decisions every day: how fast to drive, whether to stop at that yellow light, whether to buckle our

38

Thaler and Sunstein, Nudge, 243.

39 Mitchell, Libertarian Paternalism Is an Oxymoron,14.

40

Thaler and Sunstein, Nudge, 243.

 

Choice Architecture: Preserving liberty?

195

seatbelts, whether to work or check Facebook, whether to eat pizza or salad, whether to take the stairs or the elevator, whether to work out or turn on the TV, whether to go out or eat in, what to buy at the grocery store, and whether to leave the water running while we brush our teeth. If we want to improve peoples decisions in these areas then we must interact with their automatic systems. There is not time to ask them to consider all of the options and the arguments on the other side. Someone might urge that for the more important, less mundane, less day-to-day decisions, the debias/engage the reective systemrather than the rebias/architect the automatic systemapproach be implemented. This is a fair point, but we must remind ourselves that the effort to debias will never be fully successful and moreover that it may not be as effective as fashioning the automatic system to encourage people to make choices that make them better off. To see this latter point, imagine a person deciding whether to undergo a surgery. They are very much inuenced by what is automatically available in their mind, which is the image of their grandmother who underwent a similar surgery and died. A choice architect could encourage the person to really consider the statistics, which point very favorably towards undergoing surgery, and to engage in constructing arguments on the opposite side; but this is not going to be as moving as placing a vivid example in their mind that will be automatically available of someone who died without the surgery. In other words, rebiasing through crafting the automatic system will often be the most effective means towards our end of helping people make better choices.

Before concluding there is one nal issue that I would like to take up and that is the claim that choice architecture and its effects cannot be avoided, that inuencing choices is impossible to avoid. One might grant this point but maintain that there is important commission/omission distinction that a true libertarianwould uphold, and that is that there is a difference between being inuenced by a random environmental otherand another person intentionally designing the inuential environment. The former is a case of inuence by omission (we do not do anything except for allow the environment, broadly construed, to inuence people) and the latter is a case of inuence by commission (we actively do something to the environment so that it inuences people in a particular way). For those concerned about freedom, it might seem like there is something particularly objectionable about designed environmental inuence by another person. Dworkin raises this point, although does not esh it out, when he notes the difference between a natural

196

j. s. blumenthal-barby

world/culture and a planned one (such as the world in Walden Two).41 Frankfurt, on the other hand, views the difference to be irrelevant. He writes, We are inevitably fashioned and sustained, after all, by circumstances over which we have no control . . . It is irrelevant whether those causes are operating by virtue of the natural forces that shape our environment or whether they operate through the deliberatively manipulative design of other agents.42 The crucial question is whether I am in control and whether I have liberty. If I do not, whether because of a gun to my head or a mental illness or an instance of choice architecture then I do not. The question of whether an agent is in control and at liberty is best answered by asking questions about ease and cost of going ones own way, transparency, and whether one minds acting for the reasons that one did.

I will end the paper with a quote from Thaler and Sunstein, along with a caveat and a point of emphasis. Thaler and Sunstein write, Choice architecture and its effects cannot be avoided, so the . . . answer is an obvious one, call it the golden rule . . . offer nudges that are most likely to help and least likely to inict harm.43 As caveat to that I would add, and least likely to disrespect autonomy.The point of emphasis is that judgments about what is most likely to helpor make people better off should be based on data about satisfaction and happiness levels across various outcomes and not simply on intuition. Choice architecture can indeed be a mechanism to improve peoples choices while preserving their liberty, although as this paper shows, there are many stipulations, nuances, and clarications involved in establishing the soundness of that claim.

41

Dworkin, The Theory and Practice of Autonomy, 152.

 

42

Frankfurt, Reply to John Martin Fischer,28.

43 Thaler and Sunstein, Nudge, 72.

chapter 10

A psychological defense of paternalism

Jeremy A. Blumenthal

introduction

Visceral objections often exist to policies seen as paternalistic.Terms like Big Brotherand the nanny stateinvoke the dire specter of government intrusion into individualsthoughts, feelings, and behavior.1 Indeed, paternalismitself is often a term of opprobrium, used to disparage or reject policies without necessarily addressing their merits or demerits.2 Economists are traditionally hostile to paternalism;3 public policy-makers and legal academics tend to be as well. Even those recognizing the implications of social science research indicating that individuals tend to make non-optimal decisions and to be vulnerable to a host of cognitive and emotional biases, hesitate in acknowledging the paternalistic implications of their results.4 Public opinion, too, is seen to oppose paternalistic policies; citizens are presumed to object to any government infringement on their rights or autonomy. Opposition tends to focus on such autonomy objections emphasizing a libertarian ideal that each person prefers, and should be free, to make his own decisions, even if those decisions result in negative outcomes for the individual. If they do, the argument runs, then they will learn from those mistakes. Taking such objections into account, some scholars, as something of a compromise, have developed alternatives to traditional paternalism e.g., light,” “libertarian,or asymmetricpaternalism that they argue accrue benets to non-optimal decisionmakers but retain autonomy of choice as much as possible.5

Thanks to Danny Hayes for feedback on an early draft of the paper, to Kristen Stewart and Chelsea Rogen for research assistance, and to participants in the Bowling Green State University Freedom, Paternalism, and Moralityworkshop for probing and helpful questions and comments.

1 Blumenthal and Huang, Positive Parentalism.2 Gold, Paternalistic or Protective?,35.

3Calcott, Paternalism and Public Choice.

4Loewenstein and Schkade, Wouldnt It Be Nice?; Kahneman, Wakker, and Sarin, Back to Bentham?.

5Sunstein and Thaler, Libertarian Paternalism Is Not an Oxymoron; Camerer et al., Regulation for Conservatives.

197

198

jeremy a. blumenthal

Here I call into question some of these assumptions and objections, suggesting that upon closer inspection, they are awed. First, most broadly, objections to paternalism based on the importance of autonomy and choice are challenged by empirical data showing that in fact people prefer not to make choices, make better decisions when faced with fewer choices, and are more satised with their decision outcomes when those decisions are based on fewer choices. I connect such preferences with literature on stealth democracy,6 and suggest that ndings in both contexts connect well with an under-explored area in political science, that of agency decision-making. I suggest that certain models of agency decision-making may well reect both stealth-democracy preferences and, similarly, citizenspreferences not to choose. Second, critics of paternalism assert that little or no deference should be paid to experts,especially government experts (e.g., agency decisionmakers), because, inter alia, (a) experts cannot know citizens as well as citizens know themselves; and (b) expertsare themselves vulnerable to the same cognitive, a ective, and motivational biases as are the citizens whose awed judgment they are supposed to protect against. As discussed below, however, empirical evidence belies those assertions.7 Third, although recent criticisms of light paternalism miss the mark or are simply awed, nevertheless, light paternalism may in fact not preserve choice in the way its proponents believe, and alternatives to both traditional and light paternalism may be viable and perhaps preferable. Fourth, data from public opinion surveys suggest that citizens may not be as averse to paternalistic policies as is traditionally presumed.

Accordingly, paternalistic intervention of some sort may be appropriate in some circumstances depending on the costs and benets of a particular intervention.8 Moreover, certain policies or framing of policies might be more or less appropriate, and might be more or less palatable to the public. At bottom, I suggest that empirical data make a prima facie case for third-party intervention that anti-paternalists have not yet overcome.

autonomy objections

Part of the objection to paternalistic interventions, at least in theory, stems from traditional assumptions about the evils of paternalistic intervention per se.9 As alluded to above, even invoking the word can be seen as closing

6

Hibbing and Theiss-Morse, Stealth Democracy.

7 See also Blumenthal, Expert Paternalism.

8

Blumenthal, Emotional Paternalism.

9 I draw here on my discussion in ibid.

A psychological defense of paternalism

199

a discussion; paternalismand paternalisticare derogatory terms of abuse.10 But seen in light of more contemporary empirical research, the traditional assumptions, and the basis for public opinion antagonistic to such interventions, are on less solid ground than is typically presumed.

For instance, the strongest traditional assumption is the libertarian perspective that individuals know their own preferences and are better than any third party at choosing among alternatives to obtain the appropriate outcome.11 Similarly, even if such choices are non-optimal, the assumption is that individualsautonomy, the freedom to make even non-optimal choices, should be valued and respected, kept safe from infringement.12 In related fashion, even the preference for autonomy the preference for the ability to make ones own decisions should be valued.13

But both in theory and in practice, these objections to paternalistic intervention are undercut. First, substantial empirical evidence shows that people are surprisingly unable to accurately predict their reactions to future emotional events.14 In particular, people tend to overestimate the duration and intensity of emotional experiences, not taking into account their tendency to adapt or events that will help them cope with negative events or reduce the enjoyment of positive ones.15 To the extent that people are unable to accurately predict how happy or unhappy an event will make them, then not only can we not be sure how to maximize happiness,16 but it is also clear that individuals may not accurately know their own preferences. If so, then a fundamental anti-paternalist objection is challenged.

Relatedly, of course, simple observation makes clear that citizens constantly make non-optimal or harmful choices for themselves, ranging from nance to health and safety decisions about retirement portfolios and stock purchases are made in relative ignorance or under irrational exuberance; people overeat, engage in unsafe sex, smoke, and drink to excess; and drivers still neglect to wear seatbelts or motorcycle helmets. Again, such tendencies challenge the traditional assumption that people know what is good for them and can be trusted to make decisions accordingly. Showing any of these aws, of course, whether in predicting emotions or in failing to act in

10Burrows, Patronising Paternalism,542; Glaeser, Paternalism and Psychology,133; Shapiro, Courts, Legislatures, and Paternalism,519.

11See, e.g., Mitchell, Libertarian Paternalism Is an Oxymoron.

12See Sunstein and Thaler, Libertarian Paternalism Is Not an Oxymoron.

13See, e.g., Zamir, The E ciency of Paternalism,240.

14Blumenthal, Law and the Emotions; Gilbert, Stumbling on Happiness.

15See, e.g., Blumenthal, Law and the Emotions; Gilbert, Stumbling on Happiness; Wilson and Gilbert, A ective Forecasting.

16Blumenthal, Emotional Paternalism.

200

jeremy a. blumenthal

ones own welfare interest, need not mandate paternalistic intervention. Nevertheless, such empirical evidence at least calls into question some of the traditional objections, indicating that critics may need to provide stronger arguments than they previously have.

Data call into question the autonomy objection more directly, as well. Taking the second objection rst, it is not apparent that peoples putative preference for choosing should be respected. People generally prefer to keep doors open,that is, to retain exibility in their decision-making options, even when that exibility comes at the expense of decision quality.17 Further, people generally prefer their decisions to be reversible” – we want to retain the option of changing our minds despite research showing that when we are more committed to a decision, we tend to derive more utility from the relevant choice.18 Moreover, an increasing amount of empirical evidence shows that having a number of options from which to choose actually leads to lower quality decisions as well as decreased satisfaction with the choices made.19 Thus, the simple assumption that individuals necessarily value making decisions is likely incomplete, if not awed outright. Even when people do value decisions, they are often mistaken in the choices they make the ability to choose can lead to decreased, not increased, utility.20 Again, to the extent that this is so, the standard objections must meet higher hurdles than have heretofore been set in order to be fully persuasive.21

Even more directly addressing the rst objection citizens in fact often prefer not to make decisions,22 undercutting the presumed importance of making autonomous decisions. We are likely to procrastinate;23 we often try to transfer decision-making authority to others;24 and, especially in the marketplace, we prefer to minimize the e ort or costs of making decisions.25

17

Shin and Ariely, Keeping Doors Open.

18 Gilbert and Ebert, Decisions and Revisions.

19

Iyengar and Lepper, When Choice Is Demotivating; and Choice and Its Consequences;

 

Schwartz et al., Maximizing Versus Satiscing.

20Iyengar and Lepper, When Choice Is Demotivating.

21Blumenthal, Emotional Paternalism,14.

22See, e.g., Beattie et al., Psychological Determinants of Decision Attitude; Blumenthal, Emotional Paternalism; Korobkin, Bounded Rationality, Standard Form Contracts, and Unconscionability; Monahan, Addressing the Problem of Impatients, Impulsive and Other Imperfect Actors; Schwartz et al., Maximizing Versus Satiscing; Sunstein and UllmannMargalit, Second-Order Decisions.

23See, e.g., Ariely and Wertenbroch, Procrastination, Deadlines, and Performance; Monahan, Addressing the Problem of Impatients, Impulsive and Other Imperfect Actors.

24See, e.g., Sunstein and Ullmann-Margalit, Second-Order Decisions.

25Korobkin, Bounded Rationality.