Добавил:
Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:

coons_c_weber_m_eds_paternalism_theory_and_practice

.pdf
Скачиваний:
0
Добавлен:
29.10.2019
Размер:
3.32 Mб
Скачать

Paternalism in economics

161

a powerful hold on public policy discussions and it is important to understand exactly where it goes wrong. So here our target is the sort of CBA that eschews all values except as they appear in preferences and takes preferences to be fully revealed by choices. Let us call this Minimalist CBA or MCBA. Here we are concerned with one problem that, as far as we can tell, has been overlooked by the critics of MCBA. It can override values and commitments that people hold dear, purportedly with the aim of furthering their interests or other goals a patently paternalistic implication.

But before we justify this claim, we will take a brief foray into denitions of paternalism.

what is paternalism?

When faced with charges of paternalism, a common strategy is to adopt

a narrow denition of

paternalism on which the charges wont stick.9

We take the opposite

tack, adopting a broad, motive-based conception

of paternalism broader even than the denitions used by critics of happi- ness-driven economics.10 Our conception of paternalism is a modied version of Seana Shi rins inuential analysis.11 Intuitively, the paternalist asserts some degree of control over an agents own a airs. But she does so, not merely for her own purposes or out of sadism, which is why a bully or an oppressor need not be paternalistic. Rather, a paternalist is primarily concerned with managing your a airs with the aim of getting them right. And the wrong of paternalism, when wrong, is that it involves usurping an agents authority to manage her own a airs. Lets make this more precise. According to Shi rin:

paternalism by A toward B may be characterized as behavior (whether through action or through omission)

(a)aimed to have (or to avoid) an e ect on B or her sphere of legitimate agency

(b)that involves the substitution of As judgment or agency for Bs

(c)directed at Bs own interests or matters that legitimately lie within Bs control

(d)undertaken on the grounds that compared to Bs judgment or agency with respect to those interests or other matters, A regards her judgment or agency to be (or as likely to be), in some respect, superior to Bs.12

This account of paternalism has some interesting features. First, it does not require restricting or otherwise actively interfering with Bs choices, still less coercion. For example, people sometimes prefer having fewer choices

9

E.g., arguably, Trout, Paternalism and Cognitive Bias.

10 Hausman and Welch, Debate.

11

Shi rin, Paternalism, Unconscionability Doctrine, and Accommodation.

12 Ibid., 218.

162 daniel m. haybron and anna alexandrova

to more, so policies that disregard such preferences to foist more options on those individuals, for their own good, would be paternalistic. Second, paternalism need not be contrary to Bs judgment, as it may instead circumvent Bs agency in carrying out her judgment. You might want to quit smoking but lack the willpower; my hiding your cigarettes doesnt override your judgment yet is paternalist, because Im preventing you from managing your own a airs by circumventing your agency. Third, Shi rins account does not require paternalism to be aimed at the agents well-being. Indeed, it neednt be concerned with anyones welfare: Forcing me to be more virtuous, talented, skilled, well-rounded, beautiful, or otherwise excellent can quite obviously be paternalistic, even if theres no thought of me or anyone else beneting.

We agree with Shi rin on these points, but propose three modications to her account. First, it is not clearly necessary, pace (b), that A’s judgment or agency be substituted for Bs: Perhaps A designates a mechanical process, bureaucracy, or panel of experts to decide for B. She might even regard her own judgment as worse than Bs. We should, then, revise (b) to (b0 ): A acts paternalistically by substituting some other entitys judgment or agency for Bs (including, perhaps, her own).

The second modication concerns condition (d), which seems too narrow: A need not regard her (or any other) judgment or agency as superior to Bs. Perhaps A holds a high opinion of Bs judgment, but doesnt bother to nd out what B really wants before acting on Bs behalf (indeed, perhaps she does so precisely because her high opinion of B causes her to presume agreement between them): She just assumes that B wants something, and secures it for her. A pushy caregiver for a wheelchair-bound sibling, say, might regularly if inadvertently override his sisters preferences, for instance making travel plans for her without getting her opinion, which he simply assumes will mirror his (Of course she wants to go to Orlando! Who wouldnt?). In such a case A acts paternalistically towards B, not out of any presumed superiority, but simply out of insensitivity or inattentiveness to Bs attitudes. Call this inattentive paternalism (or, alternatively, implicit, versus overt, paternalism).

What such cases have in common with Shi rins condition (d), we think, is a lack of deference to Bs judgment or agency. Meddling (say), out of either presumed superiority or insensitivity, is paternalistic because in both cases it reects a failure or unwillingness to defer to Bs judgment or agency in matters over which B has legitimate authority. Accordingly, we propose to replace condition (d) with:

Paternalism in economics

163

(d0 ) manifests a non-deferential attitude to Bs judgment or agency with respect to those interests or matters.

A non-deferential attitudein turn involves an unwillingness to defer to Bs judgment or agency, or foregoing reasonable opportunities to defer to Bs judgment or agency. An unwillingness to defer,as we understand it, can include refusing to acknowledge Bs authority to make the ultimate decision, even while granting Bs wish.

Third, it is not clear that the present account, with (b0 ) and (d0 ), adequately distinguishes between paternalism and ordinary self-serving bullying or oppression. Condition (c) species that the behavior must be directedat Bs interests or a airs, but that is consistent with aiming to harm B. We can amend (c) to say that the behavior is done for the sake of Bs interests or other a airs: There is an intention to get them right. So we arrive at our nal characterization of paternalism (with aforementioned changes to condition (b) as well):

Paternalism by A towards B is behavior (whether through action or through omission)

(a) aimed to have (or to avoid) an e ect on B or her sphere of legitimate agency (b0 ) that involves the substitution of some other entitys judgment or agency

for Bs

(c0 ) done (or omitted) for the sake of Bs own interests or matters that legitimately lie within Bs control

(d0 ) manifesting a non-deferential attitude to Bs judgment or agency with respect to those interests or matters.

We think this account captures the intuitive notion of paternalism reasonably well, and highlights what is morally signicant about paternalism. Further tweaking may be needed to handle other problem cases, so we consider this denition provisional. But we think it is close enough for the purposes of our argument.

is minimalism paternalistic?

We take no stand on agricultural policy. But farmers make a useful case for illustrating our points, both because they and other rural people are unusually at risk of su ering the deciencies of minimalism that we note here, and because the problem has been eloquently voiced by farmers themselves, for instance Wendell Berry. Lets start with an example. In Costa Rica some years ago, a hotel developer o ered Miguel Sanchez,

164 daniel m. haybron and anna alexandrova

a subsistence farmer, $600,000 for his land. Sanchez refused, later explaining, I have lived in this forest since I was born. I have no desire to live anywhere else. Money can be evil. People will ask me for money, and then they might not wish to pay me back. Where I once had friends, I would have enemies.And the forest, he added, matters more than the money.13 And thus a subsistence farmer declines the opportunity to become rich.

Consider a di erent sort of case. People in a community may want a convenient new shopping center nearby. But they may also be strongly committed to individual property rights; they would be appalled to see the government invoke eminent domain to forcibly remove people from their homes, thus clearing the way for a shopping center. They would be more horried still to learn that this action was taken on their behalf, to satisfy their preferences. Their moral commitments not only cause them to oppose eminent domain for trivial purposes such as this, but to regard their convenience preferences as having no weight at all in deciding whether to seize their neighborshomes. From their perspective, their wish for a new Starbucks o ers not the slightest reason even to contemplate tossing people from their homes.

In cases like these, values, moral or prudential, silence other preferences, neutralizing them for deliberative purposes.14 Silencing can come in various forms and degrees, but for now it su ces to note that such values call them value commitments – are not merely strong preferences; they are strong preferences that serve as constraints on the satisfaction of other preferences.

Note that whether people are reasonable in having such values is beside the point: What matters for our purposes is that people do, or could, have preferences like this. And that much should be plain enough. Indeed, the whole point of positing moral rights, as virtually everyone does, is to place constraints on the satisfaction of peoples preferences. Constraints are central to Kantian and other deontological theories, of which MacIntyre once wrote, For many people who have never heard of philosophy, let alone Kant, morality is roughly what Kant said it was,and theres good empirical data to back this up.15 And while rights tend not to play

13From Carothers, Letter from Costa Rica.

14The notion of silencing derives from John McDowells writings, e.g., his Virtue and Reason in The Concept of a Person in Ethical Theory.We do not mean to endorse his views about silencing, and understand the notion loosely here. It may ultimately be more useful to frame the point in other terms, e.g., exclusionary reasons(Raz, Practical Reason and Norms). We use prudentialto denote the sort of value involved in well-being.

15MacIntyre, A Short History of Ethics, 190. For empirical discussion, see, e.g., Baron and Spranca, Protected Values; Tetlock, Thinking the Unthinkable; Cushman, Young, and Greene, Our Multi-System Moral Psychology.

Paternalism in economics

165

any fundamental role in consequentialist ethics, we cannot think of any living consequentialist philosopher who denies a role for rights, or related constraints, in actual deliberative practice. (No one thinks judges ought to decide cases solely in terms of utility maximization.) Commonsense morality, and philosophical ethics as well, is steeped in constraints.

Constraints also arise in peoples conceptions of well-being. Those holding Aristotelian or Stoic views of well-being, for instance, may regard virtue or excellence as incomparably greater in importance for their lives than other goods, such as comfort. They may be unwilling to trade any amount of excellence for any amount of gain in comfort, or be unwilling to do so below some threshold of excellence, or above some threshold of comfort. Indeed, probably most people have prudential values like this, holding commitments they see as central to their identities, integrity, and well-being. To compromise those values would be to compromise their own welfare. Many farmers for instance are, like Miguel Sanchez, committed to various values such as not robbing the land,taking good care of their animals, and for that matter leading the life of a farmer.16 They may also cherish the freedom of self-employment, having to answer to no one. These are, for them, a matter of integrity and essential for their well-being. They may be unwilling even to contemplate trading o these values against mere preferences, say for extra money or consumer goods, or would do so only in limited circumstances. Their value commitments serve as constraints on the fulllment of other, ordinary preferences in the pursuit of personal well-being. Some such values (treat my livestock well) may also be moral values, but others (be a farmer) may be wholly prudential: They might matter to the person simply as aspects of personal well-being, or as elements of a meaningful life.

In itself this preference structure might pose no problems for CBA, since (setting aside mistakes) it will presumably inform peoples preference orderings. Deep trouble arises, however, when we try to evaluate actual policy options, for the hierarchy of preferences can make it very hard to impute preferences to people. MCBA in particular has to make do with an austere diet of observed choices, considering only the overt behavior involved and not the reasoning behind it. Values collapse into mere preferences, and constraints vanish from the scene altogether.

Returning to the farmer case, MCBA treats farmersvalues as mere preferences, imputing monetary equivalents for each of them, say by looking at how much money is needed to get farmers to quit the land

16 On robbing the landand kindred values, see Berry, An Argument for Diversity.

166 daniel m. haybron and anna alexandrova

and give up farming. Suppose there is some amount of money for which farmers in a region have been observed to be willing to sell o their land. It may seem we can infer that they value their property to that extent, but the appearance may be misleading. Perhaps indeed, this may be the standard case they accept the trade purely to protect other cherished values; for example, you sell your land during hard times to save your family from ruin. They may not generally be willing to make such trade- o s at all; a secure farmer, like Sanchez, might not accept any amount of money to sell his land, because mere commodities (mere wants) arent comparable at all to his core values, which serve to constrain the pursuit of commodities. And so, when a Sanchez does sell his land, it could be for a song whatever it takes to protect his other cherished values. Similarly, that some impoverished Indian parents are willing to sell their children into slavery for $12 doesnt mean they dont view their o spring as priceless; perhaps the amount is just enough to keep their other children from starving. Market prices and Willingness to Pay/Willingness to Accept assessments in these sorts of Sophies Choicecases yield approximately zero information about peoples preferences.

This is probably not fantastical case-mongering: Governments have not infrequently undertaken policies that drive farmers from their land – fishermen from their boats, etc. to join the wage economy. Mexico, for instance, allegedly set out to modernize its economy in recent decades, adopting policies (such as NAFTA) meant to move small farmers into manufacturing jobs. A great many have indeed left the farm as a result.17 The subsequent earnings of those who actually manage to get such jobs might often exceed the amounts for which they were often under duress willing to sell their property, creating the illusion of a benet where, quite possibly, many see the move as a life-shattering disaster that no amount of money can compensate. In such cases, policies are imposed on people, for their sake, that they would have judged abhorrent had anyone bothered to ask. Even when o cials correctly discern that those individuals are losing out, the policy may still fail grossly to take seriously the depth of their opposition. We regret your loss, but assure you that we gave your concerns full consideration” – when in fact the only concerns they

registered were the prices some

people had

been observed

to accept

in extremis, which are indicative

of basically

nothing except

that there

17See, e.g., Mohanty, Small Farmers and Doha Round; and a brief but illustrative discussion by development researcher Wise, Small-Scale Farmers and Development.

Paternalism in economics

167

may be even worse fates than accepting such a bargain. To treat people in this manner is, we contend, paternalistic.

The same problem arises in a di erent way in the eminent domain case, where purely moral values are at stake. Here, MCBA gives the preferences for the shopping center full weight. Yet most of the policys supposed beneciaries might vehemently object to having their convenience preferences counted as a reason for evicting their neighbors from their homes. As a result, it is entirely possible that most citizens, including those who supposedly benet from the resulting policy, would reject the measure. This would not be a particularly democratic procedure. In any event, peoples preferences are being used, on their behalf, in ways they strenuously oppose. And so their judgments about how to promote their own interests end up being overridden by policy-makers. It is rather like a gangster who fullls his wifes wish for a diamond ring by killing a bystander, over her protests, and handing the victims ring to his disgusted companion, congratulating himself on his generosity. This sort of treatment is, we submit, paternalism.

It may be objected that these cases, however morally problematic, do not amount to paternalism, since policy-makers have no intention of overriding peoples preferences. They might rmly believe theyre carrying out peoples wishes. Given their notorious aversion to paternalism, it is safe to say that minimalist economists would generally t this description. Consumer sovereignty is the name of the game, and calling such economists paternalists can seem like calling the Pope an atheist. We agree that minimalistsexplicit intentions are non-paternalistic. The problem is what they leave out: Having accepted an oversimplied model of human preference, minimalists fail seriously to consider how people actually think about their lives. Put more concretely, a policy-maker who settles on policies with deeply disruptive consequences for peoples lives, or which conict with peoples deeply held values, and does so while seeking no more information about peoples attitudes than MCBA can provide, is almost certainly foregoing reasonable opportunities to see what the interested parties think about the matter. This is what we called inattentive paternalism: paternalism through being insu ciently attentive to peoples attitudes concerning their own a airs. And the structure of the mistake is like the well-meaning but insensitive sibling: Of course theyre better o ! Theyre making more money than ever before.

In fact our cases involve paternalism in multiple forms: Take the farmer case again, but imagine as well that the policy is meant to benet, not just the farmers, but also consumers who will enjoy lower prices. In this

168 daniel m. haybron and anna alexandrova

situation we may have threefold paternalism: First, the committed farmers forced o their land, whose prudential values are discounted; second, the farmers who gladly quit their land, but who benet only coincidentally from the policy their values are still ignored or discounted; third, the consumers whose moral values would decisively rule out treating farmers that way they would much rather deal with higher prices than have farmers forced o their ancestral lands. In each case, the policy aims to account for peoples interests without taking their view of the matter seriously. Conceivably, policy-makers relying solely on choice information might settle on a policy that every last one of the stakeholders vigorously opposes: Neither the winnersnor the losers want it. Presumably, at least some of that information is available to them, if only they are willing to look beyond choice data. When a tin-eared government imposes uniformly despised policies on their citizens, for their own good, because they refuse seriously to consider what the concerned parties actually want, that sounds like paternalism to us. Note, pace the second case, that even giving people what they want can be paternalistic, if it is done without serious regard to what they think. A popular and benevolent monarch, who takes himself not to be bound by the peoples will, treats his subjects paternalistically even if they get everything they want.

MCBA-based policy threatens paternalism not just for farmers and shermen, but at least for those subject to any policy with highly disruptive e ects on peoples lives: unemployment policy, climate-change policy, major public works like dams, etc. Climate-change policy poses exceptionally grave risks of paternalism, since the value commitments of essentially all human beings, for centuries to come, may be at stake. Simply to weigh GDP impacts of policy options likely means ignoring most of the costs that people really care about. Intelligent minimalists, of course, will want to count non-monetary costs too; but their instruments arent remotely up to the job. Mere observation of choice behavior in past circumstances, particularly the circumstances of a tragic commons, is unlikely to tell us very much about how peoples values bear on the prospect of an unprecedented, centuries-long global catastrophe. The average person has probably done very little to help preserve coral reefs, but from that fact we can hardly infer that they wont much mind leaving a reef-free planet for their children.

It is di cult to imagine a more urgent demand on policy-makers deciding on public works than that the magnitude of such costs to the a ected individuals be responsibly accounted for. Because such policies have such profound impacts on peoples lives, they will invariably infringe on individualsvalue commitments. Even where the policies

Paternalism in economics

169

would gain peoples assent, MCBAs deafness to their views means that MCBA-driven policies of this sort are always, as a matter of fact, paternalistic. We have here not the mere possibility of paternalism, but, plausibly, a pervasive actuality.

Moreover, the paternalism involved is hard paternalism: Though no overt coercion or even limitation of freedom need be involved, this sort of paternalism does not, like soft paternalism, help people achieve what they value.18 Rather, it substitutes di erent ends for them altogether. While the permissibility of soft paternalism is a matter of dispute, hard paternalism is deeply unpopular among liberals, and most certainly economists. In fact the rejection of hard paternalism may be a dening feature of liberalism. And hard paternalism in the service of values that no one cares very much about must have a very small constituency indeed.

That the unwitting endorsement of hard paternalism, possibly on a massive scale, should be a prominent feature of mainstream economic thought is no small irony. After all, a commitment to promoting freedom, including sharp restraints on paternalism, arguably forms the moral core of mainstream economics. A large swath of contemporary economics thus is profoundly morally incoherent.

on the distinction between values and preferences

We are by no means the rst to observe that the di erence between values and mere preferences makes trouble for economics. A number of philosophers have drawn a distinction between values and preferences.19 This distinction has been used to criticize CBA for its inability to recognize and respect two very di erent forms of valuation. It is this inability that motivates Andersons claim that the norms of consumerssovereignty amount to a tyranny over citizens when applied to the domain of public policy.20 Though Anderson does not frame her objection in terms of paternalism, the worry resembles those raised here.

Some have attacked the distinction between values and preferences as insu ciently sharp and unmotivated.21 Our argument need not assume a hard or deep distinction. We might, for instance, simply distinguish

18Save per accidens, as for the farmers who happen to get what they want, even though their values were not taken seriously.

19E.g., Sago , Values and Preferences; Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics; Sen, Rational Fools.

20Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics, 210.

21See Orr, Values, Preferences, and the CitizenConsumer Distinction in CostBenet Analysis.

170 daniel m. haybron and anna alexandrova

di erent levels of preferences, for example higherand lower-order.22 Importantly, the basic problem of paternalism arises even if we treat all preferences as brute preferences, for the well-known reason that, on any remotely plausible notion of preference, choices radically underdetermine preferences: Only a small fraction of our preferences are actually revealed through choice, so inferring preferences from choice behavior will always be risky. (As Richard Arneson helpfully put it to us, revealed preference information is highly gappy.) When oft-traded market goods are at stake, the risks are typically minimal: Your shopping behavior may well give pretty reliable evidence about your preferences for apples. But when talking about Very Strong Preferences, to say nothing of values, things are di erent, particularly if those preferences are rarely tested in the crucible of the market, and even then only under duress. Perhaps Sanchezs neighbors sold their lands for a paltry sum; but from that fact we can infer almost nothing about their preference orderings, beyond the bare fact that something made the deal worthwhile to them at that time. Maybe they would normally refuse any amount of money, like Sanchez, but the baby needed an operation. To assign valuations based solely on observed choices in cases like these would be to fail to take seriously those individualspreferences. It would be paternalistic, at least if there is some better way to take account of their preferences. We dont need to posit values at all to make that point.

That said, we think it important to acknowledge the existence of values beyond brute preferences. Even if our best normative theory did not ultimately require any preference/value distinction, and even if any such distinction were obscure, the fact remains that people do make distinctions of that sort. You might think value commitments, protected values,or sacred valuesobscure and unfounded, and for that reason leave them out of your normative theory. But mountains of evidence attest that people do have such values, for better or worse, and are very strongly committed to honoring them. However benighted such folk might be, it is paternalistic to disregard the structure of their preferences viz., their values when setting policies on their behalf.

The problems raised here do not indicate that MCBA is incomplete, needing supplements from other kinds of information; they tell us that MCBA gets the wrong answers about what people want and hence about the welfare or utility impacts of policy options. It gets wrong precisely the sort of information welfare economics is supposed, by its own lights, to be about. Would that the deliverances of MCBA were merely incomplete; on the contrary, its bad information. In cases of paternalism, it tells us people

22 See, e.g., Sen, Rational Fools.