Добавил:
Upload Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:

Encyclopedia of SociologyVol._3

.pdf
Скачиваний:
16
Добавлен:
23.03.2015
Размер:
6.4 Mб
Скачать

MORAL DEVELOPMENT

by the form of the moral judgment, the subject is allowed to respond freely to these moral dilemmas, and is asked to explain and justify his or her answer. The interviewer can probe with specific questions to elicit more information about the basis of the subject’s decision. Interviewers are trained to collect relevant information without directing the subject’s responses.

The subject’s answers are then transcribed and coded for stage of moral development. Kohlberg identified twenty-five aspects of moral judgment, basic moral concepts that refer to such matters as rules, conscience, one’s own welfare, the welfare of others, duty, punishment, reciprocity, and motives. Each of the twenty-five aspects was defined differently for each of the six stages of moral development. Originally, Kohlberg used an as- pect-scoring system, whereby every statement made by the subject was coded for aspect and rated as to stage (‘‘sentence scoring’’). The subject’s usage of any given stage of moral reasoning was indicated by the percentage of his or her statements that was attributed to that stage. Aspect scoring also included an overall ‘‘story rating,’’ whereby a single stage was assigned to the subject’s total response.

Coding difficulties led to the abandonment of the aspect-scoring system. Because the unit of analysis for sentence scoring was so small, coding often became dependent upon the specific content and choice of words and did not lend itself to identifying the general cognitive structure underlying the statement. Conversely, whereas story rating referred to the total response as the unit of analysis, it created some uncertainty when the subject’s answer included conflicting themes.

Kohlberg and his colleagues recognized these scoring difficulties and devoted considerable attention to developing a more reliable and valid scoring system. This led to ‘‘standardized issue scoring,’’ which relies on the use of a standardized interview format. The subject is presented with three standard dilemmas, and the interviewer probes for only two issues that are specified for each dilemma (e.g., life and punishment in the Heinz dilemma). Scoring of the subject’s responses refers to a manual that describes the patterns of reasoning for Stages 1–5 on each issue (Colby et al. 1987). Stage 6 was dropped from the coding procedure, due to its empirically low incidence, but

was retained as a theoretical construct (Kohlberg et al. 1990).

Because the focus of the new scoring system is directed more toward the abstract mode of reasoning, the unit of analysis is considered larger and less concrete than the single sentence. However, because this approach focuses on specifically identified issues, norms, and elements, it is considered more precise than the global story rating. Despite the qualitative nature of this approach and its potential vulnerability to rater bias, its developers report that long-term study of its inter-rater reliability, test-retest reliability, internal consistency, and validity has produced favorable results (Colby and Kohlberg 1987).

Validity has been a major concern regarding Kohlberg’s moral judgment interview. Kurtines and Grief (1974) criticized the low utility of moral judgment scores for predicting moral action. Other questions have been raised about the validity of the data collected, even for the purposes of assessing moral judgment. For one, use of the ‘‘classical’’ dilemmas in this research has been criticized on grounds that they are not representative: Not only do they address hypothetical—as opposed to real- life—circumstances, but they refer to a limited domain of moral issues (e.g., property and punishment). Assessment may fail to indicate the extent to which the person’s moral judgment is influenced by the particular context provided by the dilemma. A related matter is whether responses are affected by the characteristics (e.g., the gender) of the story’s protagonist. Also the effect of differences in interviewing style, as interviewers interact with subjects and probe for further information, needs to be considered. Of particular importance is this method’s dependence on the subject’s verbal expression and articulation skills for the information that is collected. To the extent that the rating might be affected by either the amount of information that is provided or the manner in which it is expressed, the validity of the scoring system is called into question. (See Modgil and Modgil 1986 for discussion of these issues.)

An alternative to Kohlberg’s Moral Judgment Interview is the Defining Issues Test (DIT) (Rest 1986). This is a standardized questionnaire that presents a set of six moral dilemmas and, for each dilemma, specifically identifies twelve issues that

1898

MORAL DEVELOPMENT

could be considered in deciding upon a course of action. The subject’s task is to indicate, on a fivepoint scale, how important each issue is in deciding what ought to be done in the given situation. The subject also ranks the four most important issues.

Here, the term ‘‘issue’’ is used differently than it is in Kohlberg’s new scoring procedure. The items are prototypical statements designed to represent considerations (e.g., ‘‘whether a community’s laws are going to be upheld’’) that are characteristic of specific stages of moral reasoning as they are described in Kohlberg’s theory. The importance assigned by the subject to items that represent a particular stage is taken to indicate the extent to which the subject’s moral judgment is characterized by that stage’s mode of thinking.

There are advantages and disadvantages to the DIT compared with the open-ended interview. Whereas the interview is helpful for originally identifying the considerations that may be relevant to resolving moral dilemmas, the DIT provides a more systematic assessment of the relative importance of such considerations. In the openended interview, it is never clear whether a specific concern is not identified because it is not important or because the subject failed to articulate it. Similarly, interviews are less comparable to the extent that subjects do not all address the same issues. These problems are avoided by the more structured DIT, because the task requires the subject only to recognize what is important rather than to identify and articulate it spontaneously. However, because recognition is an easier task than spontaneous production, it tends to allow higher-level responses. Another important difference is that the DIT measures the maturity of moral judgment as a continuous variable rather than in terms of the holistic step-by-step sequence of cognitive-developmental stages. Researchers must be aware of such differences when interpreting results.

A third instrument, the Moral Judgment Test (MJT) (Lind et al. 1981; Lind and Wakenhut 1985) similarly attempts to measure moral reasoning by the subject’s endorsement of specific items. Hypothetical moral dilemmas are presented, and subjects respond to a series of twelve statements for each dilemma. Each of Kohlberg’s six stages is

represented by two statements, one in favor of and one against the particular action in question. Subjects indicate how acceptable they find each of the statements.

Citing Lind’s paper (1995) extensively, Rest and colleagues (1997) focus on an important distinction between the MJT and the DIT. Instead of adding ratings to indicate how much the subject prefers a particular stage’s statements (stage prefer- ence)—as most DIT studies do—Lind emphasizes how consistently the subject responds to different statements from the same stage (stage consistency). Lind argues that stage consistency is a more accurate measure of true cognitive structure, whereas stage preference is more indicative of an affective (like versus dislike) response.

Rest and colleagues (1997) use the DIT statements to construct a consistency measure that is similar to the one developed by Lind. They conclude that the stage-preference measure shows greater construct validity than the stage-consisten- cy measures in differentiating groups with different expertise and different education. The stagepreference measure correlates more highly with moral comprehension—indicating longitudinal de- velopment—predicts both prosocial and antisocial behavior, and correlates with political attitudes.

The question of scoring for preference or consistency and what construct is measured by each approach is a legitimate methodological concern with important implications for our understanding of moral development. However, both the DIT and the MJT can be scored for preference and for consistency. Thus, they each remain a viable alternative for attempting to empirically measure moral judgment.

Another measurement tool is the Sociomoral Reflection Measure (SRM) (Gibbs and Widaman 1982; Gibbs et al. 1982), and a more recent variation is the Short Form (SRM-SF) (Gibbs et al. 1992; Basinger et al. 1995; Communian and Gielen 1995; Garmon et al. 1996). This is an open-ended, groupadministrable instrument that asks subjects to rate the importance of such topics as keeping promises, affiliation, life, property, and law. It does not present specific dilemmas, but instead uses ‘‘leadin statements’’ that instruct subjects to generate their own example, such as ‘‘Think about when

1899

MORAL DEVELOPMENT

you’ve made a promise to a friend,’’ prior to providing their rating of importance. The short form consists of eleven items that can produce a score ranging from 100 (exclusively Stage 1) to 400 (exclusively Stage 4).

Proponents argue that not only is the SRM-SF suitable for assessing stages of moral judgment, but because examples are self-generated, items also can be used to assess differences in content emphasis (Basinger et al. 1995; Garmon et al. 1996). As such, it is suggested as especially useful for research on cultural differences, gender differences, everyday life (versus hypothetical) experience, and the relationship between moral judgment and moral behavior (Communian and Gielen 1995).

As discussed below, perhaps the single most influential criticism of Kohlberg’s theory is Carol Gilligan’s contention that it fails to describe the moral development of females (1982). Her articulation of a more female-oriented ‘‘morality of care,’’ complete with its own sequence of stages, has led to the development of the Ethics of Care Interview (ECI) (Skoe and Marcia 1991). Similar to Kohlberg’s methodology, the ECI assesses stage differences, but specifically as they are relevant to the development of care-based morality. Research with the ECI has recently been reviewed by Skoe (1998), demonstrating that the morality of care has important application to human development in general and to the development of personality in particular.

CRITICISMS AND FURTHER RESEARCH

Besides the methodological problems discussed above, Kohlberg’s theory of moral development has been criticized on a number of points. The major criticisms include the following:

1.The sequence of stages is more representative of Western culture and thus not universal or invariant across all cultures. Moreover, it is culturally biased in that it maintains the ideals of Western liberalism as the highest form of moral reasoning.

2.Like many theories of personality development, Kohlberg’s theory fails to describe the development of women accurately but provides a much better understanding of

male development. This is a specific variation of the first criticism, suggesting that the theory itself reflects the sexism of Western culture.

3.Kohlberg’s theory fails to describe adult development adequately. In particular, its emphasis on abstract principles fails to recognize how adult moral judgment is more responsive to the specific practical matters of everyday, real-life contexts. Also, its emphasis on cognitive structure fails to recognize that changes in the content of moral reflection may be the most important aspect of adult moral development.

Cultural Bias. A cornerstone of cognitivedevelopmental theory is invariant sequence, the notion that the given developmental progression is universal for all human beings within all cultures. Because the conceptual organization of any given stage is considered logically necessary before the cognitive structure of the next stage can develop, each stage is said to have logical priority to subsequent stages. Shweder and LeVine (1975) take issue with both the notion of logical priority and the doctrine of invariant sequence, although they do not address the development of moral judgment per se. Specifically, they analyze dream concepts among children from the Hausa culture in Nigeria and conclude that there are multiple sequences by which such concepts develop.

Shweder (1982) follows up this initial skepticism with a fuller critique of what he sees as Kohlberg’s failure to recognize cultural conceptions of morality as relative to one another. He disagrees with the assertion that there is a rational basis upon which morality can be constructed objectively. Rather, he argues that the postconventional morality that Kohlberg maintains as rationally superior is simply an example of American ideology.

Similarly, others (Broughton 1986; Simpson 1974; Sullivan 1977) argue that Kohlberg’s theory is necessarily culture-bound, reflective of the Western society from which it originates. Simpson suggests that the specific moral dilemmas used in the testing situation may not have the same meaning for people of different cultures and thus the scoring system may not adequately detect legitimate

1900

MORAL DEVELOPMENT

cultural variations in moral structures. Thus, she maintains that the claims to universality are not valid. Sullivan goes even further, suggesting that Stage 6 reasoning is so rooted in the philosophical rationale for current Western society that it serves to defend the status quo. In doing so, it distracts attention from the injustices of such societies.

In an early response to the charge of cultural bias, Kohlberg and colleagues (1983) acknowledge the influence of Western liberal ideology on the theory. They agree there is a need to be more sensitive to cultural differences in the meaning attributed not only to the various elements of the research protocol but, consequently, also to the responses of the subjects themselves. However, they defend the claim to universality for the sixstage sequence of moral development and maintain that empirical research using the scientific method will help to determine to what extent this position is tenable.

They also maintain that, while it is appropriate to remain impartial in the study of moral judgment, this does not make it necessary to deny the relative value of certain moral positions. They assert that some positions are rationally superior to others. They thus continue to subscribe to the ideal that any given moral conflict can be brought to resolution through rational discourse.

Kohlberg’s position on invariant sequence has been supported by a number of cross-cultural studies, although postconventional reasoning (Stages 5 and 6) may occur less frequently in nonurbanized cultures (Snarey 1985). However, in a sample of subjects from India, Vasudev and Hummel (1987) not only found stage of moral development to be significantly related to age, but also found postconventional thinking to occur among a substantial proportion of adults. Concluding that commonalities exist across cultures, Vasudev and Hummel also suggest there is cultural diversity in the way moral principles are expressed, interpreted, and adapted to real life.

More recent research has increasingly acknowledged the significance of cultural influences on moral development. In another study with a sample from India, Moore concludes that ‘‘the notion of justice, as defined by Western social scientists, was rarely used as a moral rationale’’ (1995, p.

286). Rather, results indicated moral judgment to be dependent on one’s religious ideology or social status. Similarly, Okonkwo’s study of Nigerians (1997) concludes that moral thinking and moral language are culture dependent. While some parallels to Kohlberg’s scheme were found, some ‘‘well-articulated moral expressions could not be scored’’ (Okonkwo 1997, p. 117) due to the inability of Kohlberg’s instrument to adequately assess certain concepts that served as the basis for subjects’ moral judgments.

Ma and Cheung (1996), studying samples of Chinese, English, and American adolescents and young adults, likewise found cultural differences in the way subjects interpreted specific items on the Defining Issues Test. However, after they deleted some of the items used to indicate Kohlberg’s Stage 4, their samples demonstrated a consistent heirarchical structure across the three cultures. They thus conclude that, while different cultures may encourage different perceptions of specific moral statements, there is some support for the idea of a fundamentally universal development.

Markoulis and Valanides (1997) similarly addressed the cultural bias controversy in a conciliatory fashion. Comparing students from Greece and Nigeria, they found stage differences between the two cultures, but nonetheless found that the sequence of development was similar. Again, while cultural environment is recognized as a factor, invariant sequence in development is supported.

A related concern that has been receiving more attention from researchers is the question of whether differences in political ideology within a single, larger culture may be inaccurately represented as developmental variation. Specifically, Gross (1996) compared Americans who are prolife on the abortion issue with others who are prochoice, and also compared Israelis who disagree on now to handle the West Bank settlement issue. As long as socioeconomic status was similar, he found no difference between the relevant ideological groups and thus concludes that there is no evidence that ideological bias is built into the stages of moral development.

Conversely, Emler and colleagues (1998) argue that differences in moral development as assessed by the DIT more accurately reflect differences in political ideology. Thoma and colleagues

1901

MORAL DEVELOPMENT

(1999) acknowledge overlap between political thinking and moral judgment, but argue that Emler and colleagues and St. James (1998) provide no evidence to discount the DIT as a valid measure of moral development. Narvaez and colleagues (1999) attempt to resolve the issue with a model of moral judgment and cultural ideology as engaged in parallel development, each influencing the other to produce specific moral thinking.

Whereas recent times have been characterized by an increased sensitivity to cultural diversity and political ‘‘correctness,’’ more attention has been drawn to the consideration of possible cultural and political bias in the theory of moral development. While some researchers have identified cultural differences in moral reasoning, this has led to an increased recognition of sociocultural factors in moral development (Eckensberger and Zimba 1997).

Shweder and colleagues (1987), for example, propose the social communication theory, which maintains that the learning of morality depends largely on the transmission of cultural ideology to children, by virtue of the evaluation and judgments that parents and others make. The point, of course, is that morality is socially constructed, not self-constructed (Emler 1998).

However, other researchers continue to maintain that, while we must make specific adjustments to our understanding of moral development, it is not necessary to abandon the general consideration of a single, universal pattern to human moral development. This area of inquiry thus promises to remain a controversial yet productive focus for several years.

Gender Bias. Carol Gilligan (1982) argues that the major theories of personality development describe males more accurately than females. She includes Kohlberg’s theory in this assessment and points to the prevalence of all-male samples in his early research as a partial explanation. Gilligan contrasts two moral orientations. The first is the morality of justice, which focuses on fairness, rights, and rules for the resolution of disputes. The second is the morality of care, which focuses on relationships, a sensitivity to the needs of others, and a responsibility for others. Gilligan asserts that the orientation toward morality as justice is especially characteristic of males and, conversely, that

morality as care and responsibility is especially relevant to females. To the extent that Piaget, Freud, and Kohlberg each address morality as justice, they accurately represent male moral development but inadequately represent female moral development.

Gilligan argues that women are more likely to rely on the orientation of care to frame personal moral dilemmas. Furthermore, whereas the morality of care focuses on interpersonal relationship, it resembles the Stage 3 emphasis on satisfying the expectations of others. Gilligan believes this resemblance results in a high number of female responses being misrepresented with Stage 3 ratings.

Gilligan thus argues that Kohlberg’s theory and scoring system are biased to favor men. However, Walker (1984), after systematically reviewing empirical studies that used Kohlberg’s method, concludes that men do not score higher than women, when samples are controlled for education, socioeconomic status, and occupation. Similarly, Thoma (1986) reports that sex differences on the Defining Issues Test actually favor women but that the differences are trivial.

Kohlberg and colleagues (1983) address Gilligan’s criticisms and agree that the care orientation is not fully assessed by their measurement but disagree that this leads to a biased downscoring of females. They suggest that care and justice may develop together and that Stage 6 nonetheless represents a mature integration of the care and justice moralities (see also Vasudev 1988).

Walker and colleagues (1987) found that both the care and the justice orientations were used by both males and females. Furthermore, the orientation used was related to the type of dilemma being discussed. If the dilemma was focused on personal relationships, both men and women tended to use the care orientation. If the dilemma was impersonal, both men and women tended to express a justice orientation. This suggests that observed gender differences in moral judgment may be more a reflection of the particular kind of dilemma they choose to discuss. Perhaps females tend to report more relationship-oriented dilemmas, the kind that pull for care-based judgments (Yussen 1977).

Wark and Krebs (1996) show just this pattern: Females did not score lower than males on

1902

MORAL DEVELOPMENT

Kohlbergian dilemmas; however, females were more likely to report care-based dilemmas when asked to recall and describe moral conflicts from real life; this difference in the type of moral dilemmas accounted for differences in moral orientation from males and females.

Using the Sociomoral Reflection Measure– Short Form (SRM-SF), which does not rely on specific dilemmas provided by the researcher, Garmon and colleagues (1996) found support for gender differences in moral orientation, with females more likely to refer to a morality of care. However, they reject Gilligan’s claim of a bias against females. In fact, results (Basinger et al. 1995) have indicated a possible female advantage in early adolescence. As measured by the SRM-SF, moral judgment was found to be higher among young female adolescents than among their male counterparts. No gender difference was found in late adolescence or young adulthood. Communian and Gielen (1995) found similar results in an Italian sample, with early adolescent girls scoring higher than early adolescent boys, but no gender differences in adults. In another study of seventh and eighth graders, Perry and McIntire (1995) found that subjects used a care mode, a justice mode, and a third narrowly concerned ‘‘selfish’’ mode to make moral decisions. The girls were more likely to use both the care and the justice modes, while the boys were more likely to choose the less developed selfish mode. Contrary to a bias against females, this research suggests that, at least in early adolescence, girls are more advanced in their moral development. Silberman and Snarey (1993) relate such a cognitive advantage to the earlier physical maturation of girls.

Consistent with the lack of evidence for a bias against females, Skoe (1995) found that Kohlberg’s justice-based moral reasoning was unrelated to sex-role orientation, as measured by the Bem Sex Role Inventory (Bem 1974). However, this research indicates an interesting pattern for carebased moral reasoning. Using the Ethic of Care Interview (ECI), Skoe found that care-based reasoning was higher in women who were more androgynous and who indicated higher levels of ego identity. Skoe concludes that women who relinquish the traditional female gender role are more likely to develop a mature care-based morality than are women who retain this role.

This would seem to be inconsistent with Gilligan’s argument (1982) that the morality of care depends on traditional female socialization. While this morality may be rooted in the traditional female role, Skoe’s findings suggest that its advanced development may require a more integrated, androgynous identity.

Current researchers seem to be recognizing that the different moralities go beyond simple gender role differences. Woods (1996) argues that both Kohlberg and Gilligan represent polarized, sexist views, limited to a focus on gender differences. She suggests that researchers need to take a more comprehensive view of the multiple biological and cultural variables that impact moral development, without reducing it to a discussion of sexism. Gilligan’s morality of care identifies a vital approach to morality that may have its origin and strength in feminine ideals, indeed that may be more salient in females than in males. However, women are not confined to it, nor is it confined to women, especially as gender roles become more relaxed.

Adult Development. A third major issue concerning Kohlberg’s theory is whether or not it accurately addresses continued adult development. This issue reflects a more general concern in lifespan developmental psychology regarding the inapplicability of Piaget’s model for cognitive development beyond adolescence, leading to a consideration of what has come to be called ‘‘postformal’’ development (Commons et al. 1984). Murphy and Gilligan (1980) found that college and postcollege subjects not only indicated a greater tendency to appreciate the importance of specific contexts in real-life dilemmas but also indicated a slight tendency to regress from Stage 5 moral reasoning on the classical dilemmas. They suggest that a more mature recognition of the significance of contextual particulars leads one to question the validity of abstract moral principles (hence the regressed score). This argument is consistent with other work suggesting that adult cognitive development in general is marked by a greater appreciation of the practical realities of day-to-day living (Denney and Palmer 1981; Labouvie-Vief 1984; W. G. Perry, Jr. 1970). Related to this emphasis on the practical is the finding of Przygotzki and Mullet (1997) that elderly adults, when attributing blame,

1903

MORAL DEVELOPMENT

give more importance to the consequences of an action than to the intention of the perpetrator.

Finally, Gibbs (1979) argues that adult development is characterized more by increased reflection on such existential matters as meaning, identity, and commitment than by any structural change in the way the person thinks. Similarly, Nisan and Applebaum (1995) suggest that older adults give more weight to identity-related personal considerations when considering moral choices, unless they conflict with ‘‘a moral demand’’ from an ‘‘unambiguous law.’’ Gibbs (1979) suggests that Kohlberg’s postconventional stages are not structural advances over the earlier stages but would be more appropriately described in terms of existential development. In response, Kohlberg et al. (1983) maintain that Stage 5 represents a legitimate cognitive structure. However, they acknowledge the possibility of further nonstructural development in the adult years with regard to both specific contextual relativity and existential reflection. They suggest that such development could be described in terms of ‘‘soft’’ stages that do not strictly satisfy Piaget’s formal criteria for cognitive stages.

SUMMARY

In spite of the formidable criticisms that have been levied against it, Kohlberg’s theory of moral development remains the centerpiece to which all other work in this area is addressed, whether as an elaboration or as a refutation. At the very least, Kohlberg has formulated a particular sequence of moral reasoning that adequately represents the prevalent sequence of development in traditional Western society. To that extent, it serves as a model, not only for building educational devices (see Modgil and Modgil 1986; Nucci 1989; Power et al. 1989), but also for comparing possible alternatives. Whether or not this sequence is in fact universal or relative to the particular culture—or a particular socialization process within the culture— is a debate that continues. Nonetheless, the scheme remains the prototype upon which further work in this area is likely to be based.

REFERENCES

Bandura, Albert 1977 Social Learning Theory. Englewood

Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.

——— 1982 ‘‘Self-Efficacy Mechanism in Human Agency.’’ American Psychologist 37:122–147.

Basinger, Karen S., John C. Gibbs, and Dick Fuller 1995 ‘‘Context and the Measurement of Moral Judgment.’’ International Journal of Behavioral Development

18:537–556.

Bem, Sandra L. 1974 ‘‘The Measurement of Psychological Androgyny.’’ Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology 42:155–162.

Broughton, John M. 1986 ‘‘The Genesis of Moral Domination.’’ In S. Modgil and C. Modgil, eds., Lawrence Kohlberg: Consensus and Controversy. Philadelphia: Falmer.

Colby, Anne, and Lawrence Kohlberg 1987 The Measurement of Moral Judgment, vol. 1, Theoretical Foundations and Research Validation. New York: Cambridge University Press.

———, Alexandra Hewer, Daniel Candee, John C. Gibbs, and Clark Power 1987 The Measurement of Moral Judgment, vol. 2, Standard Issue Scoring Manual. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Commons, Michael L., Francis A. Richards, and Cheryl Armon (eds.) 1984 Beyond Formal Operations: Late Adolescent and Adult Cognitive Development. New York: Praeger.

Communian, Anna Laura, and Uwe P. Gielen 1995 ‘‘Moral Reasoning and Prosocial Action in Italian Culture.’’ Journal of Social Psychology 135:699–706.

Denney, Nancy W., and Ann M. Palmer 1981 ‘‘Adult Age Differences on Traditional and Practical Prob- lem-Solving Measures.’’ Journal of Gerontology 36:323–328.

Eckensberger, Lutz H., and Roderick F. Zimba 1997 ‘‘The Development of Moral Judgment.’’ In J. W. Berry and P. R. Dasen, eds., Handbook of Cross-Cultur- al Psychology, vol. 2, Basic Processes and Human Development, 2nd ed. Boston: Allyn and Bacon.

Emler, Nicholas 1998 ‘‘Sociomoral Understanding.’’ In A. Campbell and S. Muncer, eds., The Social Child. Hove, East Sussex: Psychology Press.

———, E. Palmer-Canton, and A. St. James 1998 ‘‘Politics, Moral Reasoning, and the Defining Issues Test: A Reply to Barnett et al. (1995).’’ British Journal of Social Psychology 37:457–476.

Garmon, Lance C., Karen S. Basinger, Virginia R. Gregg, and John C. Gibbs 1996 ‘‘Gender Differences in Stage and Expression of Moral Judgment.’’ MerrillPalmer Quarterly 42:418–437.

Gesell, Arnold 1956 Youth: The Years from Ten to Sixteen. New York: Harper and Row.

Gibbs, John C. 1979 ‘‘Kohlberg’s Moral Stage Theory: A Piagetian Revision.’’ Human Development 22:89–112.

1904

MORAL DEVELOPMENT

———, Karen S. Basinger, and Dick Fuller 1992 Moral Maturity: Measuring the Development of Sociomoral Reflection. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum.

Gibbs, John C., and K. F. Widaman 1982 Social Intelligence: Measuring the Development of Sociomoral Reflection. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.

———, and Anne Colby 1982 ‘‘Construction and Validation of a Simplified Group-Administrable Equivalent to the Moral Judgment Interview.’’ Child Development 53:875–910.

Gilligan, Carol 1982 In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

Gross, Michael L. 1996 ‘‘Moral Reasoning and Ideological Affiliation: A Cross-National Study.’’ Political Psychology 17:317–338.

Kohlberg, Lawrence 1969 ‘‘Stage and Sequence: The Cognitive-Developmental Approach to Socialization.’’ In D. Goslin, ed., Handbook of Socialization Theory and Research. Chicago: Rand McNally.

———1971 ‘‘From Is to Ought: How to Commit the Naturalistic Fallacy and Get Away with It in the Study of Moral Development.’’ In T. Mischel, ed., Cognitive Development and Epistemology. New York: Academic.

———1976 ‘‘Moral Stages and Moralization: The Cognitive Developmental Approach.’’ In T. Lickona, ed.,

Moral Development and Behavior: Theory, Research, and Social Issues. New York: Holt, Rinehard, and Winston.

———, D. Boyd, and Charles Levine 1990 ‘‘The Return of Stage 6: Its Principle and Moral Point of View.’’ In T. Wren, ed., The Moral Domain: Essays in the Ongoing Discussion between Philosophy and the Social Sciences. Cambridge: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.

Kohlberg, Lawrence, Charles Levine, and Alexandra Hewer 1983 Moral Stages: A Current Formulation and a Response to Critics. Basel, Switzerland: Karger.

Kurtines, William, and Esther B. Grief 1974 ‘‘The Development of Moral Thought: Review and Evaluation of Kohlberg’s Approach.’’ Psychological Bulletin 81:453–470.

Labouvie-Vief, Gisela 1984 ‘‘Culture, Language, and Mature Rationality.’’ In K. McCluskey and H. W. Reese, eds., Life-Span Developmental Psychology: Historical and Generational Effects. New York: Academic.

Lapsley, Daniel K. 1996 Moral Psychology. Boulder, Colo.:

Westview.

Lind, Georg 1995 ‘‘The Meaning and Measurement of Moral Competence Revisited.’’ Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Educational Research Association, San Francisco.

———, J. Sandberger, and T. Bargel 1981 ‘‘Moral Judgment, Ego Strength, and Democratic Orientations: Some Theoretical Contiguities and Empirical Findings.’’ Political Psychology 3:70–110.

Lind, Georg, and R. Wakenhut 1985 ‘‘Testing for Moral Competence.’’ In G. Lind, H. A. Hartmann, and R. Wakenhut, eds., Moral Development and the Social Environment. Chicago: Precedent.

Ma, Hing-Keung, and Chau-Kiu Cheung 1996 ‘‘A CrossCultural Study of Moral Stage Structure in Hong Kong Chinese, English, and Americans.’’ Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology 27:700–713.

Markoulis, Diomedes, and Nicolaos Valanides 1997 ‘‘Antecedent Variables for Sociomoral Reasoning Development: Evidence from Two Cultural Settings.’’ International Journal of Psychology 32:301–313.

Modgil, Sohan, and Celia Modgil 1986 Lawrence Kohlberg: Consensus and Controversy. Philadelphia: Falmer.

Moore, Erin 1995 ‘‘Moral Reasoning: An Indian Case Study.’’ Ethos 23:286–327.

Murphy, John M., and Carol Gilligan 1980 ‘‘Moral Development in Late Adolescence and Adulthood: A Critique and Reconstruction of Kohlberg’s Theory.’’

Human Development 23:77–104.

Musser, Lynn M., and Christopher Leone 1986 ‘‘Moral Character: A Social Learning Perspective.’’ In R. T. Knowles and G. F. McLean, eds., Psychological Foundations of Moral Education and Character Development: An Integrated Theory of Moral Development. Lanham, Md.: University Press of America.

Narvaez, Darcia, Irene Getz, James R. Rest, and Stephen J. Thoma 1999 ‘‘Individual Moral Judgment and Cultural Ideologies.’’ Developmental Psychology 35:478–488.

Nisan, Mordecai, and Barbara Applebaum 1995 ‘‘Maintaining a Balanced and Respective Identity: Moral Choice in Late Adulthood.’’ In G. Ben-Shakhar and A. Lieblich, eds., Studies in Psychology in Honor of Solomon Kugelmass. Jerusalem: Magnes.

Nucci, Larry P. (ed.) 1989 Moral Development and Character Education: A Dialogue. Berkeley, Calif: McCutchan.

Okonkwo, Rachel U. N. 1997 ‘‘Moral Development and Culture in Kohlberg’s Theory: A Nigerian (Igbo) Evidence.’’ IFE Psychologia: An International Journal

5:117–128.

Perry, Constance M., and Walter G. McIntire 1995 ‘‘Modes of Moral Judgment among Early Adolescents.’’ Adolescence 30:707–715.

Perry, William G., Jr. 1970 Forms of Intellectual and Ethical Development in the College Years. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.

1905

MORAL DEVELOPMENT

Piaget, Jean (1932) 1948 The Moral Judgment of the Child. Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.

——— 1960 ‘‘The General Problems of the Psychobiological Development of the Child.’’ In J. M. Tanner and B. Inhelder, eds., Discussions on Child Development: Proceedings of the World Health Organization Study Group on the Psychobiological Development of the Child. New York: International Universities Press.

———, and Barbara Inhelder 1969 The Psychology of the Child. New York: Basic.

———, and J. E. Marcia 1991 ‘‘A Measure of Care-Based Morality and Its Relation to Ego Identity.’’ MerrillPalmer Quarterly 32:289–304.

Snarey, John R. 1985 ‘‘Cross-Cultural Universality of Social-Moral Development: A Critical Review of Kohlbergian Research.’’ Psychological Bulletin 97:202–232.

Sullivan, Edmund V. 1977 ‘‘A Study of Kohlberg’s Structural Theory of Moral Development: A Critique of Liberal Social Science Ideology.’’ Human Development 20:352–376.

Power, Clark F., Ann Higgins, and Lawrence Kohlberg 1989 Lawrence Kohlberg’s Approach to Moral Education. New York: Columbia University Press.

Przygotzki, Nathalie, and Etienne Mullet 1997 ‘‘Moral Judgment and Aging.’’ European Review of Applied Psychology 47:15–21.

Rest, James R. 1986 Moral Development: Advances in Research and Theory. New York: Praeger.

———, Stephen Thoma, and Lynne Edwards 1997 ‘‘Designing and Validating a Measure of Moral Judgment: Stage Preference and Stage Consistency Approaches.’’ Journal of Educational Psychology 89:5–28.

Shweder, Richard 1982 ‘‘Review of Lawrence Kohlberg’s

Essays in Moral Development, vol. 1, The Philosophy of Moral Development: Liberalism as Destiny.’’ Contemporary Psychology 27:421–424.

———, and Robert A. LeVine 1975 ‘‘Dream Concepts of Hausa Children: A Critique of the ‘Doctrine of Invariant Sequence’ in Cognitive Development.’’ Ethos 3:209–230.

———, M. Mahapatra, and Joan G. Miller 1987 ‘‘Culture and Moral Development.’’ In J. Kagan and S. Lamb, eds., The Emergence of Morality in Young Children. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Silberman, M. A., and John Snarey 1993 ‘‘Gender Differences in Moral Development during Early Adolescence: The Contribution of Sex-Related Variations in Maturation.’’ Current Psychology: Developmental, Learning, Personality, and Social 12:163–171.

Simpson, Elizabeth L. 1974 ‘‘Moral Development Research: A Case Study of Scientific Cultural Bias.’’

Human Development 17:81–106.

Skoe, Eva E. 1995 ‘‘Sex Role Orientation and Its Relationship to the Development of Identity and Moral Thought.’’ Scandinavian Journal of Psychology 36:235–245.

———, 1998 ‘‘The Ethic of Care: Issues in Moral Development.’’ In E. E. A. Skoe and A. L. von der Lippe, eds., Personality Development in Adolescence: A Cross National and Life Span Perspective. New York: Routledge.

Thoma, Stephen J. 1986 ‘‘Estimating Gender Differences in the Comprehension and Preference of Moral Issues.’’ Developmental Review 6:165–180.

———, Robert Barnett, James Rest, and Darcia Narvaez 1999 ‘‘What Does the DIT Measure?’’ British Journal of Social Psychology 38:103–111.

Vasudev, Jyotsna 1988 ‘‘Sex Differences in Morality and Moral Orientation: A Discussion of the Gilligan and Attanucci Study.’’ Merrill-Palmer Quarterly 34:239–244.

———, and Raymond C. Hummel 1987 ‘‘Moral Stage Sequence and Principled Reasoning in an Indian Sample.’’ Human Development 30:105–118.

Walker, Lawrence J. 1984 ‘‘Sex Differences in the Development of Moral Reasoning: A Critical Review of the Literature.’’ Child Development 55:677–691.

———, B. deVries, and S. Trevethan 1987 ‘‘Moral Stages and Moral Orientations.’’ Child Development 58:842–858.

Wark, Gillian R., and Dennis L. Krebs 1996 ‘‘Gender and Dilemma Differences in Real-Life Moral Judgment.’’ Developmental Psychology 32:220–230.

Woods, Cindy J. P. 1996 ‘‘Gender Differences in Moral Development and Acquisition: A Review of Kohlberg’s and Gilligan’s Models of Justice and Care.’’ Social Behavior and Personality 24:375–384.

Yussen, S. 1977 ‘‘Characteristics of Moral Dilemmas Written by Adolescents.’’ Developmental Psychology 13:162–163.

THOMAS J. FIGURSKI

MORTALITY

See Birth and Death Rates; Infant and Child Mortality; Life Expectancy.

MULTICULTURALISM

See Ethnicity; Indigenous Peoples; Race.

1906

MULTIPLE INDICATOR MODELS

MULTINATIONAL

CORPORATIONS

See Corporate Organizations; Transnational

Corporations.

MULTIPLE INDICATOR MODELS

A primary goal of sociology (and science in general) is to provide accurate estimates of the causal relationship between concepts of central interest to the discipline. Thus, for example, sociologists might examine the causal link between the amount of money people make and how satisfied they are with their lives in general. But in assessing the causal relationships between concepts—such as income and life satisfaction—researchers are subject to making errors stemming from a multitude of sources. In this article, we will focus on one common and especially large source of errors in making causal inferences in sociology and other social and behavioral sciences—specifically, ‘‘measurement errors.’’ Such errors will produce biased (underor over- ) estimates of the true causal relationship between concepts.

Multiple indicator models are a method of testing and correcting for errors made in measuring a concept or ‘‘latent construct.’’ Multiple indicators consist of two or more ‘‘alternative’’ measures of the same concept (e.g., two different ways of asking how satisfied you are with your life). Before examining models that use multiple indicators to assess and correct for measurement error, however, the reader should become familiar with the terms and logic underlying such models. ‘‘Latent constructs’’ (also described as a ‘‘latent variables’’) are unobservable phenomena (e.g., internal states such as the amount of ‘‘satisfaction’’ a person experiences) or more concrete concepts (e.g., income) that represent the hypothetical ‘‘true’’ or ‘‘actual’’ score persons would provide if we could measure a given concept without any error (e.g., a person’s actual income or actual satisfaction, as opposed to their reported income or reported satisfaction).

Additionally, an ‘‘indicator’’ is simply another name for the empirical measure (‘‘observed’’ score)

of a given construct. For instance, researchers might measure income through a single ‘‘indicator’’ on a questionnaire that asks people ‘‘How much money do your earn per year?’’—with the response options being, say, five possible income levels ranging from ‘‘income greater than $200,000 per year’’ (coded as ‘‘5’’) to ‘‘income less than $10,000 per year’’ (coded as ‘‘1’’). Similarly, researchers might provide a single indicator for life satisfaction by asking persons to respond to the statement ‘‘I am satisfied with my life.’’ The response options here might be: ‘‘strongly agree’’ (coded as ‘‘5’’), ‘‘agree’’ (coded as ‘‘4’’), ‘‘neither agree nor disagree’’ (coded as ‘‘3’’), ‘‘disagree’’ (coded as ‘‘2’’), and ‘‘strongly disagree’’ (coded as ‘‘1’’).

Social scientists might expect to find a positive association between the above measures of income and life satisfaction. In fact, a review of empirical studies suggests a correlation coefficient ranging from .1 to .3 (Larson 1978; Haring et al. 1984). Correlation coefficients can have values between 1.0 and -1.0, with 0 indicating no association, and 1.0 or -1.0 indicating a perfect relationship. Thus, for example, a correlation of 1.0 for income and life satisfaction would imply that we can perfectly predict a person’s life satisfaction score by knowing that person’s income. In other words, individuals with the highest income (i.e., scored as a ‘‘5’’) consistently have the highest life satisfaction (i.e., scored as a ‘‘5’’); those with the next-highest income (i.e., ‘‘4’’) consistently have the next-highest life satisfaction (i.e., ‘‘4’’), and so on. Conversely, a -1.0 suggests the opposite relationship. That is, people with the highest income consistently have the lowest life satisfaction; those with the second-highest income consistently have the second-lowest life satisfaction, and so on.

Furthermore, a correlation coefficient of .2, as possibly found, say, between income and life satisfaction, suggests a relatively weak association. A coefficient of this size would indicate that individuals with higher incomes only tend to have higher life satisfaction. Hence, we should expect to find many exceptions to this ‘‘average’’ pattern. (More technically, one can square a correlation coefficient to obtain the amount of variance that one variable explains in another. Accordingly, squaring the r = .2 correlation between income and life

1907

Соседние файлы в предмете [НЕСОРТИРОВАННОЕ]