Добавил:
Upload Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:
Patton - Deleuze And The Political.doc
Скачиваний:
11
Добавлен:
06.11.2019
Размер:
605.18 Кб
Скачать

Conclusion

Deleuze’s contribution to political thought is concentrated in the books he co-authored with Guattari, particularly Anti-Oedipus and A Thousand Plateaus. In the course of this brief survey, we have done little more than chart the salient features of this complex body of work and indicate some of the ways in which it offers new resources and new directions for thinking the political. We sought to show that these philosophically experimental and politically engaged books are not an aberration or a detour in relation to Deleuze’s earlier work. Rather, they exemplify a conception of philosophy which grows out of his engagement with the history of philosophy and which displays the same virtues that he discerns in the tradition which runs through Lucretius, Hume, Spinoza and Nietzsche, namely a rejection of negativity, a belief in the externality of forces and relations, a hatred of interiority, and a commitment to the cultivation of joy by means of the invention of concepts. In order to demonstrate this continuity, we argued in Chapter 1 that Deleuze’s earlier criticisms of the prevailing ‘image of thought’ in philosophy set the scene for his later attempts in collaboration with Guattari to ‘put concepts in motion’. We also pointed to some of the concepts and themes which connect this collaborative work with Deleuze’s earlier studies in the history of philosophy, especially the theory of qualitative multiplicities derived from Bergson and the structure of immanent evaluation derived from Nietzsche’s genealogy of morality. Finally, we argued that some aspects of Deleuze’s earlier writings exercised considerable influence on political thought in their own right, notably the metaphysics of difference elaborated on the basis of the concept of multiplicity and the theory of differential force outlined in Nietzsche and Philosophy.

Above all, we have sought throughout to present Deleuze’s contribution to political thought as philosophy in the sense that he and Guattari define it in What Is Philosophy? (1994). Deleuze and Guattari share with Marx, Nietzsche and many others the conviction that the task of philosophers is to help make the future different from the past. For this reason, they endow philosophy with an explicitly political vocation, defining it as the

Page 133

creation of ‘untimely’ concepts. Philosophy is untimely and ‘worthy of the event’ when it does not simply respond to social events as they appear but rather creates new concepts which enable us to counter-actualise the significant events and processes that define our historical present. Philosophy, as they understand it, has both a cognitive and a critical function. The cognitive function is achieved by the creation of concepts that provide knowledge of pure events. The critical function is achieved not by the creation of glorious images of new earths and new peoples but by the creation of new concepts that afford new means of description of the forces which shape our future and therefore new possibilities for action. Remarkable or interesting concepts are those that can be taken up again and again in new circumstances, continuing to work their subversive way through history. Our discussion of aboriginal rights in Chapter 6 shows how the concepts of equality before the law and the equality of peoples continue to function as means of counter-actualisation of the treatment of indigenous peoples in colonial countries.

In Difference and Repetition, Deleuze described the act of thought as a dice-throw, by which he meant that thinking is a form of experimentation, the success or failure of which lies outside the control of the thinker. Similarly, in What Is Philosophy? he and Guattari suggest that philosophy is a form of experimentation in the creation of new concepts, by which they mean that it is a form of critical practical reason which aims to produce new means of acting upon the present. Their account of the political vocation of philosophy is therefore linked to a pragmatic conception of the value of philosophical concepts. Obviously, the creation of concepts can neither bring about nor controvert what those concepts express, whether this be political society under a rule of law, justice, equality between the sexes or racial equality. Rather, philosophical activity contributes to making the future different from the past by affording new forms of description, thought and action. As a result, the value of philosophical concepts is not measured by their truth value but by their novelty, remarkability and degree of interest in relation to the present. It follows that the effectiveness of philosophy as they conceive it cannot be decided by philosophy alone. For this reason, Deleuze and Guattari present their own concepts as rhizomatic conceptual assemblages, the purpose of which is precisely to ‘function’ in relation to other concepts and practices outside of themselves. The only appropriate test of the concepts they invent lies in the attempt to make them function in new contexts.

Deleuze and Guattari do not offer a concept of the political as such. Rather, they provide a series of concepts in terms of which we can describe significant features of the contemporary social and political landscape. These include concepts of social, linguistic and affective assemblages; concepts of a micropolitics of desire founded on the dynamics of unconscious affect and the different ways in which this interacts with individual and

Page 134

collective subjectivities; a concept of capital as a non-territorially based axiomatic of flows of materials, labour and information; a concept of the state as an apparatus of capture which, in the forms of its present actualisation, is increasingly subordinated to the requirements of the capitalist axiomatic; a concept of abstract machines of metamorphosis which are the agents of social and political transformation; and concepts of processes of becoming-minor or becoming-revolutionary which embody a politics of difference defined in opposition to all attempts to capture or reconfigure the position of majority. Our survey of Deleuzian political philosophy retraced the path of this fragmentary approach to the political. We began with an account of their concept of philosophy, focusing on their concept of philosophical concepts, and ended with one of the most heterogeneous and mobile concepts which they invent, namely the concept of nomadic metamorphosis machines. In keeping with the nature of this concept and the imperative of pragmatic evaluation, we sought to re-present it by describing the common-law concept of aboriginal or native title as a metamorphosis machine in relation to certain legal forms of colonial capture.

The purpose of the discussion of colonisation and native title jurisprudence in Chapter 6 was not to suggest a simple application of the concept of capture to the colonial case, but rather to show that capture takes on a specific legal form in the case of constitutional colonial states, and to suggest that in this context the jurisprudence of aboriginal or native title amounts to a smooth legal space with the potential to alter significantly both the rights of indigenous peoples and the constitutional form of those states. It was not the aim of this discussion to invoke the aboriginal peoples of the new world as exemplary Deleuzian nomads. Rather, the aim was to demonstrate the complexity of their concept of nomadism by showing that it has no necessary connection with actual nomads, just as the concept of metamorphosis machines has no necessary connection with war. At the same time, we sought to emphasise the abstract character of the concepts of capture, metamorphosis machine and smooth space by showing how these could be brought to bear on the phenomenon of colonisation. It is precisely the abstract character of these concepts which allows them to be deployed in contexts other than those in which they were first developed.

Our examination of Deleuzian concepts relevant to the political is incomplete in the sense that other concepts could just as well have been the focus of attention. Among the many novel concepts proposed in the course of A Thousand Plateaus which we have not discussed are those of strata, bodies without organs, faciality, the order-word and the refrain. Even the concepts selected for discussion have sometimes been truncated in the interests of simplicity and clarity. However, over and above these contingent limitations of the present survey, there is an important sense in which any discussion of particular concepts will necessarily constitute an incomplete account of Deleuzian political thought. For what Deleuze and

Page 135

Guattari created in A Thousand Plateaus is a heterogeneous assemblage which has no built-in end-point or conclusion and a textual machine for the creation of new concepts. That is why A Thousand Plateaus ends with a series of definitions and rules rather than a conclusion. These are, on the one hand, the rules of their own construction of concepts, but also rules which might be adapted to the creation of new concepts. Thus, in guise of a conclusion the authors provide a series of facultative rules under the following headings: strata, stratification; assemblages; rhizome; plane of consistency; body without organs; deterritorialisation; abstract machines (diagram and phylum). Even this list itself is provisional since it relates back to the concepts actually elaborated in particular plateaus. The point of abstracting these rules is to show how the process could be continued and new concepts could be elaborated. In this sense, the body of philosophy created by Deleuze and Guattari is an open-ended conceptual corpus analogous to the common law. While it possesses its own internal consistency in the form of a skeleton of principles which are subject to certain formal constraints, it can be modified, extended or developed so long as these constraints are respected. It is a rhizomatic body of concepts which can allow indefinite proliferation and self-transformation.

We suggested at the outset that the conception of philosophy as the creation of concepts whose function and value cannot be measured simply in terms of their power of representation has particular relevance to the activity of political philosophy. More generally we sought to show that Deleuze and Guattari’s own work is properly regarded as political philosophy, both in its normative and its descriptive dimensions. To that end, we pointed to the distinctive concepts of power and freedom which inform their account of social, linguistic, intellectual and other assemblages. Our aim in doing so was not to suggest that these are better concepts of power and freedom than those that are more common in Anglo-American political theory, but simply to show that there are points of connection as well as similarities and differences between them. To the extent that Deleuze and Guattari describe a world in which the possibility of creative differentiation from the past is ever present, they share with other poststructuralist thinkers a commitment to what Foucault called ‘the undefined work of freedom’. In Chapter 4 we argued that this orientation relies upon a concept of critical freedom which implies more than the absence of restraints or limits to our capacity to realise fundamental goals: it implies the ability to question and revise those goals and desires which determine the present limits of individual and public reason. In Deleuze and Guattari’s philosophy, this commitment is manifest in the way that their concepts accord systematic preference to certain kinds of movement or process over others: becoming-minor over being majoritarian, metamorphosis over capture, deterritorialisation over reterritorialisation and so on.

Page 136

Deleuze and Guattari’s philosophy of the natural and social world provides both an open-ended machinic ontology and a normative framework within which to describe and evaluate movements or processes. As such, it is an ethics in Spinoza’s sense of the term. We showed how this structure of immanent evaluation could be found in Deleuze’s reconstruction of Nietzsche’s will to power, but also how this structure was reiterated in a series of conceptual oppositions throughout Anti-Oedipus and A Thousand Plateaus: schizophrenic and paranoiac assemblages of desire; molar and molecular lines versus lines of flight; processes of deterritorialisation and reterritorialisation. In retracing the conceptual contours of this evaluative ontology, we focused on some concepts and pairs of concepts at the expense of others: becoming, lines of flight or deterritorialisation, nomadism and metamorphosis machines rather than destratification, the constitution of a body without organs or the opposition between the plane of consistency and the plane of organisation. While this choice of concepts was necessarily selective in the sense that other concepts developed in A Thousand Plateaus could have been discussed, it was not unmotivated. For we argued that the concept of deterritorialisation lies at the heart of Deleuzian ethics and politics, to the extent that Deleuze and Guattari’s mature political philosophy might be regarded as a politics of deterritorialisation.

For this reason, we endeavoured to retrace some of the internal complexity of the concept of deterritorialisation. We pointed to the distinction between the conjunction or conjugation of deterritorialised flows which occurs when one process of deterritorialisation is blocked or taken over to the benefit of another on which reterritorialisation occurs, and the connection of deterritorialised flows which occurs when these enter into mutually reinforcing interactions which lead to the formation of new territorialities. The difference between these two forms of interaction between deterritorialised flows corresponds to a distinction between the exercise of power where this is reciprocal and mutually beneficial and the exercise of power in relations of domination. We also drew attention to the fundamental distinction between relative and absolute deterritorialisation, which corresponds to the distinction Deleuze draws between the two dimensions of any event, or between events as actualised in bodies and states of affairs and the pure event which is never exhausted by such actualisations. Absolute deterritorialisation is like a reserve of freedom or movement in reality or in the earth which is activated whenever relative deterritorialisation takes place. For Deleuze and Guattari, thought can also be a vector of absolute deterritorialisation: Thinking consists in stretching out a plane of immanence that absorbs the earth (or rather ‘‘adsorbs” it). The deterritorialisation effected on such a plane does not preclude reterritorialization but posits it as the creation of a new earth to come’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1994:88, trans. modified). Philosophy

Page 137

achieves this ambition by the creation of new concepts. In one sense, Deleuze and Guattari’s contribution to political thought must be judged by reference to the concepts that they have created. In another, their legacy to thinking the political lies in this idea of a philosophy which aims at new and creative forms of counter-actualisation of the present.

Page 138

NOTES

INTRODUCTION

1  

We are not concerned in this book to separate the contributions of Deleuze and Guattari to the work published under both their names. However, the focus is on Deleuze’s political thought and we read their collaborative work against the background of his earlier philosophy.

2  

See Deleuze and Guattari 1987:69; Deleuze and Parnet 1987:117. On Deleuze’s concept of concepts and their relation to metaphor, see Patton 1997c.

3  

The original title of this book is Empirisme et subjectivité: essai sur la nature humaine selon Hume. Deleuze argues that Hume presents an idea of society that is opposed to that of the social contract theorists. ‘The main idea is this: the essence of society is not the law but the institution. The law, in fact, is a limitation of enterprise and action, and it focuses only on a negative aspect of society…The institution, unlike the law, is not a limitation but rather a model of actions, a veritable enterprise, an invented system of positive means or a positive invention of indirect means…The social is profoundly creative, inventive, and positive…Society is a set of conventions founded on utility, not a set of obligations founded on contract’ (Deleuze 1991:45–6).

4  

Guattari’s exact words were: ‘Nous faisons partie d’une génération dont la conscience politique est née dans l’enthousiasme et la naïveté de la Libération, avec sa mythologie conjuratoire du fascisme’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1972:15).

5  

Several short publications by Deleuze dealing with Palestine and the Gulf War have been translated in a special issue of Discourse, vol. 20, no. 3, Fall 1998. On Palestine, see Deleuze 1998b, 1998c, 1998d and Deleuze and Sanbar 1998. On the Gulf War, see Deleuze et al. 1998 and Deleuze and Scherer 1998.

6  

‘We no longer maintain an image of the proletarian of which it is enough to become conscious’ (Deleuze 1995b:173 trans. modified).

7  

See also the discussion of public and private thinkers in ‘1227: Treatise on nomadology—the war-machine’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1987:376–7).

8  

‘Politics is active experimentation, since we do not know in advance which way a line is going to turn’ (Deleuze and Parnet 1987:137).

9  

In this manner, Gatens and Lloyd suggest that ‘Spinoza’s own political philosphy is folded into the metaphysical and ethical concerns addressed in the Ethics’ (Gatens and Lloyd 1999:8).

10  

The important distinction between absolute and relative deterritorialization is discussed in Chapter 5, pp. 106–7.

Page 139

1 CONCEPT AND IMAGE OF THOUGHT

1  

Our concern here is not with the nature of these assemblages but the practice of philosophy which gives rise to a book of this kind. Deleuze and Guattari’s concept of assemblage is discussed in more detail in Chapter 2, pp. 42–6.

2  

In an interview published after his death, Deleuze described A Thousand Plateaus as the best thing he had ever written, alone or with Guattari (Deleuze 1995a:114).

3  

The ‘secret link’ which unites these thinkers is their ‘critique of negativity, their cultivation of joy, the hatred of interiority, the externality of forces and relations, the denunciation of power’ (Deleuze 1995b:6).

4  

In What Is Philosophy? (1994), Deleuze and Guattari suggest that both contemporary analytic and communicational or conversational images of thought remain bound to the recognition model (Deleuze and Guattari 1994:138–9, 145–6).

5  

In the Critique of Judgement, Kant explicitly grounds this accord among the faculties by means of a ‘common sense’ (Kant 1987:89–90). However, in Kant’s Critical Philosophy (Deleuze 1984), and in his article published in the same year, ‘L’ldée de genèse dans l’esthétique de Kant’ (1963), Deleuze argues that the notion of such an accord between faculties or common sense is implicit in the accounts given in the preceding Critiques. Common sense is defined as ‘an a priori accord of the faculties, an accord determined by one of them as the legislative faculty’ (Deleuze 1984:35). In the case of knowledge claims, it is the imagination, understanding and reason which collaborate under the authority of the understanding to form a logical common sense, while in the case of moral judgment, it is reason which legislates. Kant ‘multiplies common senses’, creating as many as there are ‘interests of reason’ (Deleuze 1994:136–7).

6  

In Difference and Repetition, Deleuze uses Heidegger’s example (Deleuze 1994:165) but the analogy holds for any individual body attempting to coordinate bodily movement with a greater force, such as the novice rider attempting to coordinate his or her bodily movement with that of the horse. In an interview, Deleuze points to the contemporary passion for surfing (Deleuze 1995b: 121). For the example from Plato, cf. The Republic, 523b-c, and Deleuze 1994:138–9.

7  

In The Logic of Sense (1990) and later writings, Deleuze proposes that the Leibnizian domain of the event is the ultimate element of thought. In What Is Philosophy? (1994), transcendental or ‘pure’ events are singled out as the external conditions of philosophical thinking: concepts express pure events. Deleuze’s concept of events and the relation between philosophical concepts and events is discussed further below.

8  

Deleuze and Guattari insist on the difference between concepts and the plane of immanence which is not a concept but the region or milieu of thought in which particular concepts may be formed: ‘Concepts are concrete assemblages, like the configurations of a machine, but the plane is the abstract machine of which these assemblages are the working parts’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1994:36). In order to highlight continuities between the concept of philosophy outlined in What Is Philosophy? and that in Chapter 3 of Difference and Repetition, we focus on the identity asserted between the conceptual plane of immanence and the image of thought. However, it should be noted that the concept of the plane of immanence also has links to the important concept of the plane of consistency developed in A Thousand Plateaus: see for example Deleuze and Guattari 1987:70–3, 265–72.

Page 140

9  

‘I am well aware that I have never written anything but fictions. I do not mean to say, however, that truth is therefore absent. It seems to me that the possibility exists for fiction to function in truth, for a fictional discourse to induce effects of truth, and for bringing it about that a true discourse engenders or manufactures something that does not as yet exist, that is, “fictions” it’ (Foucault 1980:193).

10  

In similar fashion, Best and Kellner read Anti-Oedipus (1977) as ‘a materialist, historically grounded, Foucauldian-inspired critique of modernity with a focus on capitalism, the family and psychoanalysis’ (Best and Kellner 1991:85). At the other extreme, Philip Goodchild argues that Deleuze and Guattari’s theory ‘should never be judged according to its apparent “truth” or “falsehood’’… Deleuze and Guattari’s social theory does not tell us about society in general, nor about the society in which we live; it only tells us about the social unconscious which Deleuze and Guattari have created, out of the resources which lie to hand, and it provides a resource through which we may create our own social meanings and relations’ (Goodchild 1996:46).

11  

The equivalence of transcendental problems and pure events is reaffirmed in Deleuze’s account of the logical genesis of propositions in The Logic of Sense (Deleuze 1990:123).

12  

The passage Deleuze cites from Péguy’s Clio reads as follows: ‘Suddenly, we felt that we were no longer the same convicts. Nothing had happened. Yet a problem in which a whole world collided, a problem without issue, in which no end could be seen, suddenly ceased to exist and we asked ourselves what we had been talking about. Instead of an ordinary solution, a found solution, this problem, this difficulty, this impossibility had just passed what seemed like a physical point of resolution. A crisis point. At the same time, the whole world had passed what seemed like a physical crisis point. There are critical points of the event just as there are critical points of temperature: points of fusion, freezing and boiling points, points of coagulation and crystallization. There are even in the case of events states of superfusion which are precipitated, crystallized or determined only by the introduction of a fragment of some future event’ (Deleuze 1994:189; cf. Deleuze and Guattari 1994:111–13; 156–7). Note that it is in this context that Deleuze first introduces the categories of importance and distinctiveness as criteria for the evaluation of thought, suggesting that the problem of thought ‘is not tied to essences but to the evaluation of what is important and what is not, to the distribution of singular and regular, distinctive and ordinary points, which takes place entirely within the inessential or within the description of a multiplicity, in relation to the ideal events which constitute the conditions of a “problem”’ (Deleuze 1994:189).

13  

Kant 1992:153–7; cf. Deleuze and Guattari 1994:100.

14  

Deleuze and Guattari’s characterisation of the event as the contour of an event ‘to come’ is mirrored by Derrida’s concept of the ‘to come’ as ‘the space opened in order for there to be an event, the to-come, so that the coming be that of the other’ (Derrida 1993:216). A concept of the pure event appears in Derrida’s accounts of the undecidable objects of his quasi-concepts: for example, his discussion of signature explains the ‘enigmatic originality’ of every such mark of identity by reference to ‘the pure reproducibility of the pure event’ (Derrida 1988:20). In effect, all the objects of deconstructive a-conceptual concepts might be described as pure events, or as variations upon the one pure event of sense or meaning: writing, iteration, differance, incineration, justice, etc. The experience of the undecidable, which is associated with all of these objects, is also an experience of the event or an experience of that which is necessary in order for there to be an event. For Derrida as for Deleuze and Guattari, the concept of the pure event functions as an inaccessible incorporeal reserve of being which guarantees a freedom in things and states of affairs.

Page 141

2 DIFFERENCE AND MULTIPLICITY

1  

For example, Iris Marion Young acknowledges the importance of discussions of difference in the work of Derrida, Lyotard, Foucault and Kristeva for her approach to the politics of difference (Young 1990:7). Similarly, Seyla Benhabib notes that ‘the term “difference” and its more metaphysical permutations, “différance” in the work of Jacques Derrida, and “le différend” in the work of Jean-François Lyotard, have become rallying points for two issues: a philosophical critique of Enlightenment type rationalism, essentialism and universalism, and a cultural battle cry for those who insist on the experience of alterity, otherness, heterogeneity, dissonance and resistance’ (Benhabib 1996:5).

2  

Similarly, Alex Callinicos argues that ‘Deleuze’s significance is in part that, starting from [a] fundamentally Nietzschean position…he has sought, drawing on a variety of sources ranging from Kant and Bergson to Artaud and Scott Fitzgerald, to develop a comprehensive philosophy of difference’ (Callinicos 1982:85).

3  

See Bogue 1989:15; Schrift 1995b:60–1. Other authors who point to the importance of this book in establishing Nietzsche as a key figure in poststructuralist thought include Leigh 1978, Pecora 1986 and Perry 1993. Derrida makes reference to Deleuze’s concept of power as the effect of difference between forces in his essay ‘Différance’ (Derrida 1982:17). Foucault also testifies to the enduring effect of Deleuze’s differential reading of the will to power on his own work: see Chapter 3, note 1. In his inaugural address to the Collège de France, Foucault remarked, speaking of his teacher Jean Hyppolite, ‘I am well aware that in the eyes of many his work belongs under the aegis of Hegel, and that our entire epoch, whether in logic or epistemology, whether in Marx or Nietzsche, is trying to escape from Hegel’ (Foucault 1984a:134). His own work develops the theme of difference in a variety of ways: in his account of Nietzsche’s conception of genealogy, in his theory of discourse, and in his theory of power. Foucault returns to this theme in the anti-teleological manner in which he interprets Kant’s question about enlightenment: Kant, he writes, ‘is looking for a difference: What difference does today introduce with respect to yesterday?’ (Foucault 1984b:34).

4  

In Plato, Deleuze argues, ‘a moral motivation in all its purity is avowed: the will to eliminate simulacra or phantasms has no motivation apart from the moral. What is condemned in the figure of simulacra is the state of free, oceanic differences, of nomadic distributions and crowned anarchy, along with all that malice which challenges both the notion of the model and that of the copy’ (Deleuze 1994:265).

5  

Notably by Baudrillard (1983). See also the entry ‘Simulacrum’ by Michael Camille in Nelson and Sniff 1996:31–44, as well as the discussion of simulationist art and art criticism in Foster 1996:99–107, 127–8.

6  

See the extensive discussion of Bergson’s distinction between two types of multiplicity and its relation to his theory of duration in Turetzky 1998:194–210. On Deleuze’s use of Bergson’s concept of multiplicity and his relation to neoDarwinism, see Ansell Pearson 1999:155–9.

7  

Similarly, in Negotiations he comments: ‘I see philosophy as a logic of multiplicities’ (Deleuze 1995b:147).

Page 142

8  

Deleuze is not guilty here of misusing or mystifying mathematical concepts in the manner suggested by Sokal and Bricmont 1998:160–5. Rather, he draws upon the history of metaphysical interpretations of the calculus in order to develop a philosophical concept of transcendental Problems or Ideas from a genetic point of view, in full awareness that this is a philosophical rather than a scientific enterprise (Deleuze 1994: xvi, xxi, 170–82). For mathematically as well as philosophically informed comment on Deleuze’s remarks on the calculus, see Salanskis 1996.

9  

Constantin Boundas discusses this concept of different/ciation and its relation to Deleuze’s interpretation of Bergson in Boundas 1996:90–8.

10  

In their discussion of pack, herd and swarm multiplicities typically found in cases of becoming-animal (see Chapter 4), Deleuze and Guattari point out that these continually cross over into one another as in the case of werewolves which become vampires when they die. As such, these mythological pack animals illustrate the transformative character of all qualitative multiplicities: ‘Since its variations and dimensions are immanent to it, it amounts to the same thing to say that each multiplicity is already composed of heterogeneous terms in symbiosis, and that a multiplicity is continually transforming itself into a string of other multiplicities, according to its thresholds and doors’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1987:249).

11  

Gabriel Tarde (1843–1904) was a French philosopher, criminologist and psychologist. Along with Durkheim, he was one of the founding figures in French sociology. His major works include Lois de l’imitation, Paris: Alcan, 1890 (translated as The Laws of Imitation, Gloucester: Peter Smith, 1962); La logique sociale, Paris: Alcan, 1893; Essais et mélanges sociologiques, Lyon: Stock, 1895; and L’opposition universelle, Paris: Alcan, 1897. Other works by Tarde translated into English include Penal Philosophy, Montclair, NJ: Patterson Smith, 1968, and On Communication and Social Influence: Selected Papers, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1969. Deleuze and Guattari refer to Tarde as the founder of a ‘microsociology’ in which the social is considered from the perspective of infinitesimal gestures which form waves of influence both beneath and beyond the level of the individual, and ‘differences’ and ‘repetitions’ that elude the dialectic of identity and opposition. Tarde is cited in Difference and Repetition (1994:25–6, 76, 307, 313–4, 326), Foucault (1988:36, 142) and The Fold (1993:109–10, 154), and in A Thousand Plateaus (1987:216, 218–219, 548, 575). In part owing to the revival of interest in Tarde inspired by thinkers such as Deleuze, a series of his major works is currently being reissued by Synthélabo/Les empêcheurs de penser en rond with prefaces by Eric Alliez, Isaac Joseph, Bruno Karsenti, Maurizio Lazzarato, Jean-Clet Martin and René Scherer.

12  

In his discussion of Foucault’s theory of discourse, Deleuze comments that the primary elements of discourse, statements or énoncés, are not only inseparable from multiplicities (discursive formations) but are themselves multiplicities (Deleuze 1988b:6). With reference to his own concept of substantive multiplicity, he suggests that Foucault’s Archaeology of Knowledge represents ‘the most decisive step yet taken in the theory-practice of multiplicities’ (Deleuze 1988b:14).

13  

‘There is no doubt that an assemblage never contains a causal infrastructure. It does have, however, and to the highest degree, an abstract line of creative or specific causality, its line of flight or deterritorialization; this line can be effectuated only in connection with general causalities of another nature’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1987:283).

Page 143

14  

See Chapter 4, pp. 73–4.

15  

‘Since every search for identity includes differentiating oneself from what one is not, identity politics is always and necessarily a politics of the creation of difference’ (Benhabib 1996:3).

16  

On the differentialist arguments of the French new right, see Taguieff 1994. On the case of EEOC v.Sears see Scott 1988 and Milkman 1986.

17  

See also Deleuze 1994:130. In this context, note Deleuze’s comment in ‘Intellectuals and power’ concerning the practical lesson provided by Foucault with regard to ‘the indignity of speaking for others’: ‘We ridiculed representation and said it was finished, but we failed to draw the consequences of this “theoretical” conversion—to appreciate the theoretical fact that only those directly concerned can speak in a practical way on their own behalf (Foucault 1977b: 209).

18  

At the end of Plateau 13 ‘7000 B.C.: apparatus of capture’, they assert: ‘this is not to say that the struggle on the level of the axioms is without importance: on the contrary, it is determining (at the most diverse levels: women’s struggle for the vote, for abortion, for jobs; the struggle of the regions for autonomy; the struggle of the Third World; the struggle of the oppressed masses and minorities in the East or West’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1987:470–1).

19  

Compare William Connolly’s discussion of the politics of becoming where he comments that ‘To the extent it succeeds in placing a new identity on the cultural field, the politics of becoming changes the shape and contour of already entrenched identities as well’ (Connolly 1999:57).

3 POWER

1  

In an interview published in 1972, Foucault said to Deleuze: ‘If reading your books (from Nietzsche and Philosophy to what I imagine will be Capitalism and Schizophrenia) has been so important for me it is because they seem to me to go very far in posing this problem [who exercises power and where is it exercised?]: underneath the old theme of meaning, signified and signifier etc., at last the question of power, of the inequality of powers and their struggles…’ See ‘Intellectuals and Power’ (Foucault 1977b), originally published as ‘Les intellectuels et le pouvoir’, L’Arc, 49, 1972:3–10. Deleuze’s thinking about power has also influenced others such as Negri, who admitted that without Deleuze’s work on Spinoza, his own ‘would have been impossible’ (Negri 1991:267). See also Hardt 1993.

2  

See also The Gay Science (Nietzsche 1974: bk 5, para. 107).

3  

In his critical discussion of Nietzsche’s complicated relation to Darwinism in Viroid Life, Keith Ansell Pearson points to his rejection of the reactive concept of life prevalent in ‘English Darwinism’ in favour of an active concept of life which emphasises the priority of the ‘spontaneous’, ‘expansive’ and selfoganising ‘form-shaping forces at the expense of adaptation (Ansell Pearson 1997a:92). At the same time, he argues that Nietzsche is ‘in fact, closer to Darwin in his thinking on evolution and adaptation than to the explicit Lamarckian position frequently attributed to him’ (Ansell Pearson 1997a:87). In Germinal Life (Ansell Pearson 1999), he makes Deleuze’e engagement with biological thinkers the focus of an account of Deleuze’s own ‘philosophy of germinal life’.

4  

In Thus Spoke Zarathustra Nietzsche writes ‘where I found a living creature, there I found will-to-power; and even in the will of the servant I found the will to be master’ (Nietzsche 1969a: part 2, ‘Of self-overcoming’).

Page 144

5  

See, for example, Daybreak, bk 4, para. 262: ‘Not necessity, not desire—no, the love of power is the demon of men.’

6  

See, for example, Schacht 1983; Schutte 1984; Warren 1988; Ansell Pearson 1994; Owen 1995.

7  

The concept of the feeling of power is vital to understanding the application of Nietzsche’s theory of the will to power to human culture and society. The reading of Nietzsche as a champion of violence and hierarchy is only possible because of the failure to notice this concept. While in the past there have been societies in which exploitation and cruelty towards others were glorified, this does not imply that this is an inescapable feature of human social relations. The history of human culture is in part a history of the development of new means for attaining the feeling of power. There are many evaluative comments throughout Nietzsche’s writings which suggest a hierarchy among the possible means of acting upon others. These imply that the feeling of power obtained from contributing to the feeling of power of others is preferable to all other means of obtaining this feeling. For examples and further comment, see Patton 1993.

8  

At least, it might be considered to enhance the powers of all so long as it is considered as an association entered into by equals, without regard to the bodies of women and others whose incorporation is simply a consequence of their prior subordination. But even if we imagine a body politic founded upon the effective equality of all its adult members, there are further distinctions to be drawn before we can judge the effect of this composite body on the powers of individual members: what is the quality of the power which predominates in its formation? Does this involve a primarily negative form of capture or is it an affirmative combination and transformation of the powers of its citizens? These kinds of evaluative questions raised by Deleuze’s theory of power will be considered in the next section of this chapter.

9  

See also Deleuze and Guattari 1987:238, 293.

10  

Similarly, but contrary to widespread opinion, Nietzsche’s concept of power does not imply that the exercise of power is inherently conflictual. Discussions of Nietzsche, as well as discussions of those influenced by him such as Deleuze and Foucault, tend to overlook this point of fundamental importance with regard to the potential utility of Nietzsche’s concept of power within political theory. See, for example, Read 1989; Bogue 1989:33.

11  

For criticisms of Foucault’s failure to address normative issues, see Fraser 1989:17–34; Habermas 1987:282ff. For responses to these criticisms and discussions of the manner in which Foucault addresses normative issues in his later work, see the essays collected in Moss 1998 and Ashenden and Owen 1999.

12  

In this respect, Deleuze suggests that Nietzsche is close to Callicles in the argument with Socrates over nature versus convention in Gorgias (Deleuze 1983:58).

13  

‘From this spirit and in concert with the power and very often the deepest conviction and honesty of devotion, it has chiselled out perhaps the most refined figures in human society that have ever yet existed: the figures of the higher and highest Catholic priesthood’ (Nietzsche 1982: bk 1, para. 60).

4 DESIRE, BECOMING AND FREEDOM

1  

See Holland 1999:36–57, 78–91.

2  

Deleuze and Guattari employ the term ‘schizophrenia’ in this context to refer not to a clinical condition but rather to a semiotic process inherent in the nature of desire. See Holland 1999:2–3, 26–33.

Page 145

3  

Gatens and Lloyd point out that, for Spinoza, ‘Desires arising from joy will, by definition, be increased by affects of joy; while desires of sadness will be diminished by affects of sadness. There is in this contrast an inherent orientation of joy towards engagement with what lies beyond the self, and hence towards sociability; and there is a corresponding orientation of sadness towards disengagement and isolation. The force of desire arising from joy will be strengthened, rather than weakened, by the power of external causes. The mind’s increase of activity, which is joy, will be strengthened by its understanding of the external causes of its joy’ (Gatens and Lloyd 1999:53).

4  

See the passage from Daybreak, bk 1, para. 23, cited in Chapter 3, p. 53. Mark Warren draws attention to the importance of the ‘feeling of power’ in Nietzsche’s account of human agency. He argues that Nietzsche’s theory of the will to power must be understood primarily as an account of the conditions of the human experience of agency and that, for Nietzsche, it is the self-reflective dimension of agency as expressed in the feeling of power which is paramount: ‘In being conscious and self-conscious, humans increasingly strive less for external goals than for the self-reflective goal of experiencing the self as agent’ (Warren 1988:138).

5  

Cited in Allison 1977:107; also Klossowski 1997:55.

6  

‘By affect I understand affections of the body by which the body’s power of acting is increased or diminished, aided or restrained’ (Ethics, III, def. 3). See Deleuze’s discussion in 1988c:48–51.

7  

See Charles Stivale’s discussion of a contemporary politics of becoming in cyberpunk science fiction (Stivale 1998:124–42).

8  

At one point they suggest that ‘becoming and multiplicity are the same thing’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1987:249).

9  

These are the affects which Nietzsche associates with actors, women and others who had to survive under conditions of dependency. See Nietzsche 1974: bk 5, para. 361, ‘On the problem of the actor’.

10  

See Jardine 1985; Braidotti 1991, 1994; Grosz 1994a, 1994b; Battersby 1998. Grosz provides a useful summary of previous feminist criticisms of Deleuze and Guattari in Grosz 1994a:163–4, 173–9. Olkowski 1999:32–58 and Goulimari 1999 undertake critical readings of earlier feminist responses to Deleuze and Guattari: both offer a more positive assessment of the prospects for a ‘minoritarian feminism’. Lorraine 1999 explores common ground between Irigaray and Deleuze.

11  

Grosz reads Deleuze and Guattari in this manner, taking them to be suggesting that ‘the liberation of women’ is a necessary phase in the larger process of human liberation. See Grosz 1994a:179; 1994b:208.

12  

Diana Coole (1993:84–7) points out the extent to which Berlin relies upon a series of spatial metaphors in order to define negative liberty.

13  

Deleuze’s concept of critical freedom has affinities with Bergson, especially in Time and free Will, where free acts are regarded as rare exceptions to the habitual actions of everyday life (Bergson 1913:168). Later, he argues that ‘freedom must be sought in a certain shade or quality of the action itself and not in the relation of this act to what it is not or to what it might have been—it really consists in a dynamic progress in which the self and its motives, like real living beings, are in a constant state of becoming’ (Bergson 1913:182–3). See also Cohen 1997:153–4.

Page 146

5 SOCIAL MACHINES AND THE STATE

1  

Kenneth Surin draws attention to this feature of Deleuze and Guattari’s analysis of capitalism, suggesting that the capitalist axiomatic is capable of regulating the interaction of a series of cultural and social ‘accords’, such that in its current phase it should be regarded as a meta- or mega-accord: ‘As a set of accords or axioms governing the accords that regulate the operations of the various components of an immensely powerful and comprehensive system, capital is situated at the crossing-point of all kinds of formations, and thus has the capacity to integrate and recompose capitalist and noncapitalist sectors or modes of production. Capital, the “accord of accords’’ par excellence, can bring together heterogeneous phenomena and make them express the same world’ (Surin 1998).

2  

This phrase from Nietzsche, cited by Deleuze and Guattari 1977:34, comes from Thus Spoke Zarathustra, part 2, ‘Of the land of culture’.

3  

Deleuze and Guattari suggest that the despotic machine involves a ‘formation’ that may be found in spiritual as well as in secular empires. They point to paranoia as the equivalent formation of desire, suggesting that ‘the despot is the paranoiac’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1977:193).

4  

See the commentary on the Qin dynasty treatise on government, The Book of Lord Shang, by Kenneth Dean and Brian Massumi (1992:11–71).

5  

Elsewhere in Difference and Repetition, Deleuze points out that for every philosophy that begins from a subjective or implicit claim about what everybody is supposed to know, there is another that denies this knowledge or fails to recognise what is claimed. Such philosophies rely not upon the common man but on a different persona: ‘Someone who neither allows himself to be represented nor wishes to represent anything’ (Deleuze 1994:130). In the interview ‘Intellectuals and Power’, he suggests that it was Foucault who taught the intellectuals of his generation the indignity of speaking for others: ‘We ridiculed representation and said it was finished, but we failed to draw the consequences of this “theoretical” conversion—to appreciate the theoretical fact that only those directly concerned can speak in a practical way on their own behalf (Foucault 1977b:209).

6  

Holland 1991:57. See also the extended discussion of deterritorialisation and decoding in Holland 1999:19–21.

7  

See the theorems of deterritorialisation elaborated in Plateau 7, ‘Year Zero: faciality’ and in Plateau 10, ‘1730: becoming-intense, becoming-animal, becoming-imperceptible’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1987:174–5; 306–7).

6 NOMADS, CAPTURE AND COLONISATION

1  

For a long time, the term ‘war-machine’ was associated with the type of military-industrial complex which emerged in the advanced industrial countries after 1945. Deleuze and Guattari use the term in this sense in their description of the post-war evolution of the nation-state, when they suggest that it is now plausible to view the major industrial states as subordinated to a global warmachine, a single many-headed monster whose most striking feature is its awesome destructive power: ‘We have watched the war-machine grow stronger and stronger, as in a science fiction story’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1987:422). Since the publication of A Thousand Plateaus in France in 1980, and in the aftermath of the ‘wars’ against Iraq and Serbia, the term has become commonly used to refer to anything remotely connected to the military capacity of a nation-state or multinational organisation such as NATO.

Page 147

2  

See Stivale’s extended schizoanalytic analysis of this film and the documentary sequel Apocalypse Now, Hearts of Darkness (Stivale 1998:27–70). Stivale comments that ‘Colonel Kurtz’s apparent desire and (narrated) “becomings” that so tempt Willard during his journey relate directly to the dream of merging with the flows of a warrior band in a nomadic military operation supposedly beyond the limited logic of the US Government’s war machine’ (Stivale 1998:34).

3  

The forms of nomadism in actual societies are typically to be understood as a mixture of these distinct modes of social existence. Nevertheless, Deleuze and Guattari insist that the formal differences are important since ‘it is only on the basis of the distinct concept that we can make a judgement on the mix’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1987:410).

4  

‘The authors’ reservations about anthropology do not prevent them from using it in two important ways: first, they borrow heavily from anthropological sources, and second, they make anthropological statements of their own’ (Miller 1993:13).

5  

See their defensive comment at the end of Plateau 12: ‘We thought it possible to assign the invention of the war-machine to the nomads. This was done only in the historical interest of demonstrating that the war-machine as such was invented’ (Deleuze and Guatttari 1987:422).

6  

See William Connolly’s micropolitical analysis of the emergence of a right to die in Connolly 1999:146–9.

7  

Despite the fact that the first Governor of the colony of New South Wales was under instructions to take possession of lands only ‘with the consent of the natives’ and despite the long history of colonial negotiations and treaties with indigenous peoples in other parts of the world, the British authorities chose not to regard the indigenous inhabitants of Australia as settled peoples with their own law and government. Instead, they opted for the fiction that New South Wales had been acquired ‘as desert and uninhabited’. This principle was clearly stated by the British Privy Council in an 1889 case, Cooper v.Stuart, when it declared Australia to be a Crown colony acquired by settlement on the grounds that it was ‘a tract of territory practically unoccupied without settled inhabitants or settled law’ (Reynolds 1996:16, 110).

8  

‘Just as eighteenth century colonial law harboured rules governing such matters as the constitutional status of colonies, the relative powers of the Imperial Parliament and local assemblies, and the reception of English law, it also contained rules concerning the status of the native peoples living under the Crown’s protection, and the position of their lands, customary laws, and political institutions. These rules form a body of unwritten law known collectively as the doctrine of aboriginal rights. The part dealing specifically with native lands is called the doctrine of aboriginal title’ (Slattery 1987:737).

9  

Johnson v.M’lntosh 21 US (Wheat) 543 (1823) at pp. 547, 573–4.

10  

For Aotearoa/New Zealand see R v.Symonds (1847) NZPCC, 387; for Canada, see St Catherine’s Milling and Lumber Company v. The Queen (1888) 14 AC 46.

11  

Mabo v.Queensland (1992) is reported at 175 CLR 1; 66 ALJR 408; 107 ALJR 1. It is published in book form, with commentary by Richard H.Bartlett, as The Mabo Decision, Sydney: Butterworths, 1993.

12  

For example, the Chief Justice said in his judgment that ‘the common law of this country would perpetuate injustice if it were to continue to embrace the enlarged notion of terra nullius and to persist in characterising the indigenous inhabitants of the Australian colonies as people too low in the scale of social organisation to be acknowledged as possessing rights and interests in land’ (Bartlett 1993:41).

Page 148

13  

In a Deleuzian analysis of Canadian aboriginal politics (which in several respects parallels this account of aboriginal title jurisprudence) Kara Shaw emphasises the degree to which both the trial judge’s 1993 decision in Delgamuukw v.British Columbia and the 1997 Appeal decision by the Supreme Court amount to a reassertion of the sovereignty of the colonial State as the ground of any claim to special rights. At the same time, with reference to Deleuze and Guattari’s distinction between the politics of minority and the majoritarian politics of the axiomatic (see Chapter 2, pp. 47–8), she points to the important sense in which these legal decisions also serve to expose the irreducible gap between the aspirations of the Gitskan and Wet’suwet’en plaintiffs and the available forms of recognition within the axiomatic of the colonial State. Without seeking to deny the importance of changes at the level of the axioms, she shows the sense in which, for the aboriginal plaintiffs as for Deleuze and Guattari, the domain of politics is not exhausted by struggle at this level (Shaw 1999:280–308).

14  

Calder et al v.Attorney-General of British Columbia (1973) 34 DLR (3d) 145.

15  

Re Southern Rhodesia 1919 AC 211, at 233–4. Cited in Bartlett 1993:26–7, 144.

16  

This view was enshrined in the common law of the colony in R v.Murrell (1 Legge 72). This case, heard in 1836, involved the trial of two aboriginal men for killing another aboriginal man. The defence argument that the defendants should not be tried under British law since they were acting in accordance with tribal law was rejected on the grounds that native customs were not worthy of recognition as laws. Rather, these customs were considered ‘only such as are consistent with a state of greatest darkness and irrational superstition’ (Reynolds 1996:62). In an 1847 case, Attorney-General v.Brown (1 Legge 312), the judge explicitly refused to recognise any aboriginal customary law in relation to land when he asserted that ‘the waste lands of this colony are, and ever have been, from the time of its first settlement in 1788, in the Crown’, for the simple reason that there was ‘no other proprietor of such lands’.

17  

Delgamuukw v.British Columbia (1991) 3 WWR 97 at 219–23. Cited in Asch 1999:438.

18  

Van der Peet v. The Queen (1996) 137 DLR (4th) 289 (SCC). In this case the Canadian Supreme Court directly addressed the question of the nature and content of aboriginal rights, arguing that these should be understood as the means whereby the assertion of Crown sovereignty is reconciled with the fact of prior occupation by distinctive aboriginal societies.