Добавил:
Upload Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:
An Englishman Looks at the World.doc
Скачиваний:
4
Добавлен:
25.08.2019
Размер:
1.29 Mб
Скачать

In a very obvious way, sociology seemed to Comte to crown the edifice of

the sciences; it was to be to the statesman what pathology and

physiology were to the doctor; and one gathers that, for the most part,

he regarded it as an intellectual procedure in no way differing from

physics. His classification of the sciences shows pretty clearly that he

thought of them all as exact logical systematisations of fact arising

out of each other in a synthetic order, each lower one containing the

elements of a lucid explanation of those above it--physics explaining

chemistry; chemistry, physiology; physiology, sociology; and so forth.

His actual method was altogether unscientific; but through all his work

runs the assumption that in contrast with his predecessors he is really

being as exact and universally valid as mathematics. To Herbert

Spencer--very appropriately since his mental characteristics make him

the English parallel to Comte--we owe the naturalisation of the word in

English. His mind being of greater calibre than Comte's, the subject

acquired in his hands a far more progressive character. Herbert Spencer

was less unfamiliar with natural history than with any other branch of

practical scientific work; and it was natural he should turn to it for

precedents in sociological research. His mind was invaded by the idea

of classification, by memories of specimens and museums; and he

initiated that accumulation of desiccated anthropological anecdotes that

still figures importantly in current sociological work. On the lines he

initiated sociological investigation, what there is of it, still tends

to go.

From these two sources mainly the work of contemporary sociologists

derives. But there persists about it a curious discursiveness that

reflects upon the power and value of the initial impetus. Mr. V.V.

Branford, the able secretary of the Sociological Society, recently

attempted a useful work in a classification of the methods of what he

calls "approach," a word that seems to me eminently judicious and

expressive. A review of the first volume the Sociological Society has

produced brings home the aptness of this image of exploratory

operations, of experiments in "taking a line." The names of Dr. Beattie

Crozier and Mr. Benjamin Kidd recall works that impress one as

large-scale sketches of a proposed science rather than concrete

beginnings and achievements. The search for an arrangement, a "method,"

continues as though they were not. The desperate resort to the

analogical method of Commenius is confessed by Dr. Steinmetz, who talks

of social morphology, physiology, pathology, and so forth. There is also

a less initiative disposition in the Vicomte Combes de Lestrade and in

the work of Professor Giddings. In other directions sociological work is

apt to lose its general reference altogether, to lapse towards some

department of activity not primarily sociological at all. Examples of

this are the works of Mr. and Mrs. Sidney Webb, M. Ostrogorski and M.

Gustave le Bon. From a contemplation of all this diversity Professor

Durkheim emerges, demanding a "synthetic science," "certain synthetic

conceptions"--and Professor Karl Pearson endorses the demand--to fuse

all these various activities into something that will live and grow.

What is it that tangles this question so curiously that there is not

only a failure to arrive at a conclusion, but a failure to join issue?

Well, there is a certain not too clearly recognised order in the

sciences to which I wish to call your attention, and which forms the

gist of my case against this scientific pretension. There is a gradation

in the importance of the instance as one passes from mechanics and

physics and chemistry through the biological sciences to economics and

sociology, a gradation whose correlatives and implications have not yet

received adequate recognition, and which do profoundly affect the method

of study and research in each science.

Let me begin by pointing out that, in the more modern conceptions of

logic, it is recognised that there are no identically similar objective

experiences; the disposition is to conceive all real objective being as

individual and unique. This is not a singular eccentric idea of mine; it

is one for which ample support is to be found in the writings of

absolutely respectable contemporaries, who are quite untainted by

association with fiction. It is now understood that conceivably only in

the subjective world, and in theory and the imagination, do we deal with

identically similar units, and with absolutely commensurable quantities.

In the real world it is reasonable to suppose we deal at most with

_practically_ similar units and _practically_ commensurable quantities.

But there is a strong bias, a sort of labour-saving bias in the normal

human mind to ignore this, and not only to speak but to think of a

thousand bricks or a thousand sheep or a thousand sociologists as though

they were all absolutely true to sample. If it is brought before a

thinker for a moment that in any special case this is not so, he slips

back to the old attitude as soon as his attention is withdrawn. This

source of error has, for instance, caught nearly the whole race of

chemists, with one or two distinguished exceptions, and _atoms_ and

_ions_ and so forth of the same species are tacitly assumed to be

similar one to another. Be it noted that, so far as the practical

results of chemistry and physics go, it scarcely matters which

assumption we adopt. For purposes of inquiry and discussion the

Соседние файлы в предмете [НЕСОРТИРОВАННОЕ]