Добавил:
Upload Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:

vse_otvety / 42_Modalnost_predlozheny

.docx
Скачиваний:
28
Добавлен:
01.06.2015
Размер:
19.5 Кб
Скачать

Modality

The category of mood expresses the character of connection between the process denoted by the verb and the actual reality, either presenting the process as a fact that really happened, happens or will happen, or treating it as an imaginary phenomenon, i.e. the subject of a hypothesis, speculation, desire. It follows from this that the functional opposition underlying the category as a whole is constituted by the forms of oblique mood meaning, i.e. those of unreality, contrasted against the forms of direct mood meaning, i.e. those of reality, the former making up the strong member, the latter, the weak member of the opposition. A formal presentation and a functional presentation are the formal signs of this categorial opposition. The category of mood, like the category of voice, differs in principle from the immanent verbal categories of time, prospect, development, and retrospective coordination. The category of mood expresses the outer interpretation of the action as a whole, namely, the speaker's introduction of it as actual or imaginary.

Mood is considered to be one of the most complicated problems in the theory of English Grammar. Only the number of moods varies from 1 to 16. The main theoretical problems are connected with Oblique Moods. The variety of views on English mood can be reduced to three main approaches: 16 moods (It’s time, I wish… ), it is semantic (Deutschbein), there are 4 moods because their forms are different, formal (Smirnitsky) and the one based on both semantic and formal properties (Khlebnikova).

Purely grammatical type: type of mood (indicative, imperative, subjunctive).

Indicative (facts) – expresses what the speaker considers to be a known state of affairs.

Imperative (non-facts that turn out into facts) – is used to form commands or requests, including the giving of prohibition or permission, or any other kind of exhortation.

Subjunctive(non-facts, unreality) (Subjunctive I, Subjunctive II) – expresses various states of unreality such as wish, emotion, possibility, judgment, opinion, necessity, or action that has not yet occurred.

Indicative, imperative – direct

Subjunctive – indirect

Lexico-grammatical means: modal verbs (can, must, should, need, will, may, etc)

Purely lexical: modal words (certainly, indeed, perhaps, happily – unhappily, of course, evidently, maybe, luckily – unluckily, no doubt, naturally, probably, fortunately– unfortunately, surely, obviously, possibly, apparently, really, assuredly, actually, undoubtedly)

Exercises: multiple choice (choose the right modal verb/word); make up a sentence using modal verbs/words; make the sentence unreal/real.

Из шпаргалки

Although often associated with the category of MOOD (indicative, imperative, subjunctive, conditional) , category of MODALITY actually stands on its own, especially in the English language, where it is primarily marked by the system of modal verbs. The category of mood marks the verb phrase for factuality of the event/state (Indicative – factual, Real Conditional and Imperative non-factual, Subjunctive and Unreal Conditionals counterfactual/hypothetical. Modality may be defined as the way in which the meaning of a proposition is modified as to reflect the speaker's/ subject’s attitude towards the likelihood of the proposition content being or becoming true. Modality in English has traditionally been interpreted in terms of the use of modals, and although this is not the only resource available for the expression of this notion,there is no doubt that it is the most important one. Still,modality as a whole is not a clear area of study, for several reasons, themost important being the fact that we can identify two different kinds ofmodality: "root" (deontic) modality (dealing with obligation, permission,ability, etc.) and epistemic modality (dealing with probability, possibility,certainty, etc.). This distinction has been studied in the past, and aninteresting suggestion is that epistemic uses are dependent on, and derivefrom, deontic ones (cf. Sweetser 1982, 1990, who gives a unifiedtreatment in terms of force dynamics and causality).From a diachronic point of view, it is clear that epistemic modality derives from "root"modality, and we shall elaborate on this below. Diachrony can also be understood from a language learning perspective: children acquire thedeontic senses of modal verbs earlier than the epistemic ones Synchronically, "root" and epistemic modalities are related by means of a subsumption relation which will also be discussedhere.However, modality as a notion also needs to be examined in connection with tense and aspect. As will be shown, epistemic modality can be represented in a compact way together with tense in a graph which has time as one axis and possible worlds as the other. There is strong evidence that tense and modality are related: both are categories that are encoded in predications at the same level of depth, and both clearly interact with each other. This will also be looked into. If we consider tense, we shall also need to consider aspect, which deals with the internal configuration of time as it is expressed in verbs. The three categories tense, aspect, and modality are expressed mainly by auxiliaries; there is a great deal of crosslinguistic evidence that the three of them are closely interrelated In order to analyse the way in which this interrelation takes place, weare going to use two axes: the diachronic one (relations through historicaltime) and the synchronic one (relations in the system at a given moment). Modality receives a very complex treatment in Functional Grammar. mentions the following sub-areas of modality:Level 1: Inherent modality, which defines the relation between a participant and the realization of the SoA in which he is involved. It concerns ability or willingness, obligation, and permission.Level 2: Objective modality, which expresses the speaker's evaluation of the likelihood of occurrence of the SoA. It can be divided into two subareas with a gradation of the degree of actuality involved. These are:Epistemic objective modalities (Certain-Probable-Possible-ImprobableImpossible) and Deontic objective modalities (Obligatory-AcceptablePermissible-Unacceptable-Forbidden).Level 3: Epistemological modality. Here we have modal distinctions signalling the speaker's personal commitment to the truth of the proposition. They are: Subjective modality, in which the speaker takespersonal responsibility for the content of the proposition, and signals how certain he is about its truth; and evidential modalities, in which the speaker assesses the quality of the proposition according to how he has obtained it, be it through evidence, by personal experience, or by having heard it from someone else. As far as English modals are concerned, only objective modality will be considered here. In fact, this is the proper type of notion that corresponds to modality, according to most authors. Inherent modality covers modal distinctions such as ability, willingness, obligation, permissibility, and volition. However, Siewierska remarks that these distinctions are realised lexically . . . , not grammatically. Hengeveld suggests that there is also a semantic difference between inherent and objective modality in that by means of the former speakers merely present their knowledge of a given situation, while by means of the latter they offer an evaluation of the situation in terms of this knowledge. For many linguists, this difference excludes inherent modality from the proper domain ofmodality. As for subjective modalities, they are statements of opinion rather than fact, and Siewierska reminds us that, in English, "the modal auxiliaries are open to an objective and a subjective reading" The distinction between "root" and epistemic modality made on etymological grounds, corresponds broadly to the distinction between deontic and epistemic modalities. Root modality is closer to the etymological meaning, which has to do with evaluative judgement in many cases. Other authors also agree with this distinction, although they define modality in a way sometimes misleadingly similar to FG modality varieties for level 3 or 1. This is the case with Givón's (1993: 169) definition, in which, if we assume that modality has to do with the speaker's attitude towards a proposition, this attitude concerns two types of judgement:(a) Epistemic judgements of truth, probability, certainty, belief or evidence.(b) Evaluative judgements of desirability, preference, intent, ability,obligation or manipulation.Of the utmost interest is the fact that, regardless of their concrete valueas judgements, all these possible modalities can easily be explained inlogical terms by means of a possible worlds approach. Modality expressedlogically in terms of possible worlds (certainty and probability) has been extended in order to interpret obligation/permission (deontic logic), and knowledge/belief (epistemic logic); all these different logical models account for the opposition realis/irrealis, which Givón (1993: 172 and ff.) uses to denote a characteristic feature of modality. The logical approachtherefore provides us with an instrument which explains deontic modality as a special variety of epistemic modality, the subsumption of the former by the latter being plausible in the kind of explanatory schema suggested below. Obligation implies certainty and permission possibility; in a similar way, knowledge implies certainty and belief possibility.