
- •Contents
- •Table of Cases
- •List of Contributors
- •Introduction
- •1. Bottom-Up Theories
- •2. The Humean Approach
- •1. Introduction
- •2. The Moral Right to Labour Productively
- •2.1 The intellectual context for Lockean rights
- •2.2. Labour as a moral right
- •3. Property Acquisition in Labour Theory
- •3.1 Extending labour from the person to things
- •3.2 The social character of productive appropriation
- •3.3 Productive use as a limit on labour
- •3.4 The communicative function of productive labour
- •4. Control Rights in Labour Theory
- •5. Accession in Labour Theory
- •6. Lost Opportunities to Capture in Doctrine
- •7. Acquisition in Doctrine
- •7.1 The basic test for capture
- •7.2 Constructive capture
- •7.3 Multiple proprietary claims
- •8. Accession Policy and Ratione Soli Doctrine
- •9. On the Relation between Legal Property and Moral Rights to Labour
- •10. Conclusion
- •3: Property and Necessity
- •1. Some Conceptual Preliminaries
- •2. Winstanley’s Challenge
- •3. Grotius on Property and Necessity
- •4. Three Important Objections
- •5. Saving Property and Public Necessity
- •6. Is the Right of Necessity a Property Right?
- •4: Private Property and Public Welfare
- •1. The Fifth Amendment Paradox
- •2. Why Acquisition?
- •3.1 Physical possession
- •3.3 Exchange
- •4. Property in Civil Society
- •4.1 The origin of welfare entitlements
- •4.2 Civil society as a bifurcated entity
- •5. Property in the Political Community
- •5.1 Property in the totalitarian state
- •5.2 Property in the dialogical state
- •6. Conclusion
- •5: Average Reciprocity of Advantage
- •1. Introduction
- •2. Background
- •2.1 Judicial opinions
- •2.2 Academic commentators
- •3. Sources of Average Reciprocity of Advantage
- •4. The Limits of ‘In-Kind’ Compensation
- •4.1 General reciprocity
- •4.2 Probabilistic compensation
- •4.3 Basic structural problems
- •5. Reciprocity and Respect
- •5.1 Accepting the conclusion
- •5.2 Rejecting the premisses
- •5.3 Partial, ‘objective’ compensation
- •6. Conclusion
- •1. Introduction
- •2. Between Promise and Detachment
- •2.1 The moral principle
- •2.2 The value of LPA
- •3. Legal Enforcement
- •3.1. Encouraging pre-contractual Investment
- •3.2 Building up trust: the role of LPA
- •4. Proprietary Estoppel
- •4.1 Varieties of PE
- •a) Bargain
- •b) Gifts
- •4.2 The remedy
- •5. Conclusion
- •7: Possession and Use
- •1. Possession
- •2. The Priority of Exclusion
- •3. Bringing Actual Use Back In
- •4. Conclusion
- •8: Possession and the Distractions of Philosophy
- •1. Introduction: The Puzzle
- •3. Possession and Title
- •4. The Right of Possession and its Omnilateral Structure
- •5. Possession and the Incidents of Ownership
- •6. A Principled Practice of Property?
- •7. Conclusion
- •9: The Relativity of Title and Causa Possessionis
- •2. Privity, Estoppel, and Rights to Possess outside of Ownership
- •2.1 A public law problem?
- •2.2 Privity: the missing link between property and person
- •2.3 Let the chips fall where they may
- •3. Conclusion
- •1. Introduction
- •2. Setting the Limits of Property Rights
- •2.1 Where A has an undoubted property right
- •a) The ‘right to exclude’
- •b) The ‘right to use’
- •i. Chattels
- •ii. Land
- •c) Conclusion
- •2.2 Determining if B’s right counts as a property right
- •a) Physical things
- •b) Non-physical things
- •c) Equitable property rights
- •3. Conclusion
- •11: On the Very Idea of Transmissible Rights
- •1. Title and Succession
- •2. The Argument against Transfer or Transmissibility Stated: The Hohfeldian3 Individuation Argument
- •3. Why the Hohfeldian Individuation Argument is Wrong
- •4. Justifying Transmissible Rights
- •4.1 The power to authorize what would otherwise be a battery
- •4.2 The right to immediate, exclusive possession of property
- •4.3 The power to license and to give property away
- •4.4 The power to sell or transfer pursuant to an agreement
- •4.5 The liability to execution
- •5. A Last Word on Conventions and Social Contexts
- •12: Psychologies of Property (and Why Property is not a Hawk/Dove Game)
- •1. The Inside Perspective
- •1.1 Identity formation
- •1.2 Identity fashioning
- •1.3 Refuge
- •1.4 Empowerment
- •1.5. Generosity
- •1.6 Economic incentives
- •1.7 An admonitory postscript
- •2. The Outside Perspective
- •2.1. The picture from in rem
- •2.2 Hawks and Doves
- •2.3 The virtues of non-ownership
- •13: Property and Disagreement
- •1. Disagreements Substantive and Verbal
- •1.1 Verbal disagreements
- •1.2 Disagreement that is partly substantive and partly verbal
- •a) Clarifying the disagreement
- •b) The analysis of property
- •c) The metaphysics of property
- •d) What about W2 and W3?
- •3. A Minor Disagreement that is both Substantive and Conceptual
- •4. Penner Redux: A Major Disagreement that is both Substantive and Conceptual
- •4.1 Reservations: of Wittgenstein and Dworkin
- •4.2 Individuation and incomplete understanding
- •5. The Nature of Property
- •5.2 Smith and the architecture of property
- •6. Conclusion
- •Appendix
- •14: Emergent Property
- •1. Intensions and Conceptualism in Property Law
- •2. Formalism versus Contextualism
- •3. Functionalism
- •4. Holism and Emergence
- •5. An Application to in Rem Rights and Duties
- •6. Conclusion
- •References
- •Index
Productive Use in Acquisition, Accession, and Labour Theory |
17 |
Separately, because the judges who developed the doctrines studied in this chapter subscribed to labour theories quite like Locke’s, these doctrines illustrate how legal doctrine may and should ‘settle’ the positive law of property.21 In this chapter, I use acquisition and related doctrines to illustrate the relation between labour-based natural-rights morality and legal practice. Productive labour theory focuses acquisition-related doctrines while leaving lawyers a reasonable amount of flexibility about how those doctrines’ contents should be specified.
This chapter’s argument proceeds as follows. Sections 2–5 restate the foundations for labour-based property rights relying on productive labour theory, focusing specifically on the insights needed to apply those foundations to capture, lost capture, and ratione soli doctrines. Section 2 defines and justifies a natural-rights liberty interest in productive labour, and Section 3 extends that interest to property. Sections 4 and 5 show how labour-based property rights justify two legal principles related to accession: (in Section 4) exclusive control over land and chattels, and (in Section 5) accession principles. Sections 6–9 demonstrate my second thesis. Section 6 examines how property rights are settled in ‘lost capture’ disputes, Section 7 does the same in relation to capture doctrine and variations on it, and Section 8 does so for the fixture and ratione soli doctrines. Section 9 then makes some general observations about the relation between productive labour theory and legal practice.
2.The Moral Right to Labour Productively
2.1The intellectual context for Lockean rights
Contemporary property scholarship has lost its feel for labour theory in large part because it has lost its feel for theories of natural law and rights that shaped AngloAmerican law. During the 18th and 19th centuries, rights-based and utilitarian sources of obligation came to seem separate;22 Locke’s accounts of rights, morality, and political obligation precede that separation.23 So let me begin by defining general terms important to Locke’s accounts of rights, morality, and political obligation, and by restating a justification for a right to engage in productive labour. In case it needs saying, any such ‘restatement’ can only scratch the surface of Lockean property scholarship.24
21 When I justify and examine particular acquisition or accession doctrines in this chapter, I will do so assuming that the officer responsible for the doctrine’s content seeks conscientiously to make it conform as much as possible to the prescriptions of productive labour theory. That said, Locke himself doubted whether it was necessary or likely that most political communities would demand their officials to be this conscientious. In chapter 5 of the Second Treatise, Locke’s justification for exclusive property rights works whether the citizens agree to secure natural rights or merely converge on a ‘tacit and voluntary consent’ around such rights and an economy with exchange and money. (See Locke 1689b, Second Treatise, s. 50, pp. 301–2.)
22 |
MacIntyre 1984, 123–4. |
23 Olivecrona 1974. See Alexander and Peñalver 2012, 36–7. |
24 |
The following account relies substantially on Simmons 1992 and Buckle 1991 to describe |
productive labour theory and property rights. The account relies less on Simmons and Buckle and more on Myers 1999 and West 2012 to describe the (what West, Myers, and I believe to be the eudaimonistic and virtue-theoretic) normative foundations of such labour and rights. That said,
18 |
Eric R. Claeys |
Like other medieval or early Enlightenment theories, Locke’s account of natural rights is egoistic. Psychologically, humans are hardwired to pursue things that they believe to be good or happiness supplying and in which they believe themselves to be deficient.25 Descriptively, humans are capable of reasoning deliberately how to judge and rank different apparent goods,26 and of reasoning practically how to exercise dominion over inferior things to acquire those goods.27 This background determines the character of normative obligations for Locke. People are obligated to pursue their goods, but they also have rights to engage in activity reasonably likely and necessary to acquire those goods. Because human goods ground both duties and rights, duties and rights have the character they have in interest (or benefit) theories of rights.28 Locke confirms as much in an aside in the Second Treatise. Locke justifies law ‘in its true Notion . . . not so much [as] the Limitation as the direction of a free and intelligent Agent to his proper Interest’, and as ‘prescrib[ing] no farther than is for the general Good of those under that Law’.29
When Locke refers to moral ‘rights’, he assumes a meaning for ‘right’ consistent with these egoistic, interest-based priors. For Locke, a moral ‘right’ consists of a strong normative interest30 comprising two more specific interests. One of those interests is a claim-right, a negative right to exclude others from interfering with one’s legitimate authority to make decisions in a particular field of choice. The other specific interest is a liberty, an affirmative capacity to pursue one’s own gratification or well-being within the scope of that legitimate authority.31 A moral right (back in the broader sense) is ‘moral’ if it has binding force and if its force is pre-political and non-conventional.32
Medieval and early Enlightenment natural law and rights theories portray individuals as being entitled to a sphere of free moral agency called the suum (‘his own’),33 encompassing the individual’s rights to life, body, liberty, reputation, and other more specific rights. The moral right to labour is one of the rights included in the suum. The right to labour is the right to engage in activity reasonably likely and necessary to help the actor pursue ‘prosperity’. Every person has a ‘natural Inclination . . . to preserve his Being’. It is reasonable to infer that this inclination has a ‘purpose, to . . . use . . . those things which were serviceable for his Subsistence, and given him as means of his Preservation’.34 ‘Prosperity’ encompasses preservation
Simmons 1992, 58–9 is probably right that Locke’s main rights-claims may be grounded on overlapping foundations.
25 |
Locke 1700, II.xxi.31–69, pp. 250–81. |
26 Locke 1700, II.xxi.46, 262–3. |
27 |
Locke 1689b, First Treatise, s. 30, p. 162. |
28 See Simmons 1992, 92–4. |
29Locke 1689b, Second Treatise, s. 57, p. 305.
30In this chapter, I use ‘interest’ in the sense in which it was used in Feinberg 1984, 33–4, unless context requires otherwise.
31When I speak of ‘claim-rights’ and ‘liberties’, I mean what Wesley Hohfeld called (respectively) ‘claim-rights’ and ‘privileges’. Hohfeld 1913, 28–44. Simmons 1992, 92–3 (following Feinberg 1970) refers to the same incidents as ‘rights’ and ‘moral powers’. I use the corresponding Hohfeldian terms because Simmons’s terms are likely to seem idiosyncratic to many political-philosophy readers and most legal readers. See Kramer 1997, 15–23.
32 |
Simmons 1992, 87–94. |
33 See Olivecrona 1974, 222–5. |
34 |
Locke 1689b, First Treatise, s. 86, p. 223. |
Productive Use in Acquisition, Accession, and Labour Theory |
19 |
and the other goods people may justifiably pursue.35 Although ‘prosperity’ at least gestures toward human excellence,36 most of the time it focuses on low common denominator ‘civil goods’: ‘life, freedom, the wholeness of and freedom from pain in the body, and the possession of external things, such as a landed estate, money, equipment, et cetera’.37 To capture these tensions in ‘prosperity’, I will in the rest of this chapter refer interchangeably to ‘prosperity’ and to ‘self-preservation andimprovement’.
2.2. Labour as a moral right
The right to labour productively comes to mean the right to use one’s person and planning faculties to pursue prosperity so specified. Labour includes a Hohfeldian liberty to engage in ‘purposeful activity, directed to useful ends, and which secures preservation in the primitive state and improves human life once basic necessities have been met’.38 Labour also entails a claim-right to be free all from interferences with the liberty except those resulting from exercises of the same liberty. Similarly, ‘use’ consists of the application of one’s own person or other inputs to pursue prosperity in a manner consistent with other individuals’ pursuing prosperity concurrently. That is why, for example, Locke contrasts the ‘use of the Industrious and Rational’ with the ‘Fancy and Covetousness of the Quarrelsom and Contentious’.39 In this sense, ‘use’ is inherently productive use. The moral right of labour is the right to ‘use’ persons and things only in the course of ‘activity of improving for the benefit of life’.40
Labour’s productive character answers the challenge (recounted in the Introduction) to justify on what basis ‘one owns even the labour that is mixed with something else’. When Locke says that ‘every Man has a Property in his own Person’, and that ‘[t]he Labour of his Body, and the Work of his Hands . . . are properly his’, he may reasonably be understood to mean that men are entitled to be left alone to direct their purposive actions.41 In the Haslem case, Haslem ‘owned’ a sphere of purposive action in which to search for resources useful to his farm because he had an inherent and inalienable moral faculty to direct and enjoy the benefits from his own moral agency.
35With one caveat—Locke deliberately avoided using the term ‘prosperity’ in the Two Treatises. Locke reported King James I to have said, in a 1603 speech to Parliament, that he ‘acknowledge[d] himself to be ordained for the procuring of the Wealth and Property of his People’. In the original, the King had promised to procure the ‘Wealth and prosperitie’ of the people. Locke 1689b, Second Treatise, s. 200, p. 399 and nn. 4–11.
36I believe Locke de-emphasized perfection and excellence for fear that they would destabilize politics in Christian political communities. See Claeys 2009b, 916–34; Claeys 2008. Locke’s deliberate avoidance of the term ‘prosperity’ confirms this interpretation.
37Locke 1689a, 66 (my translation). See Claeys 2008.
38Buckle 1991, 150. See Simmons 1992, 273.
39 |
Locke 1689b, Second Treatise, s. 34, p. 291. |
40 Buckle 1991, 151. |
41 |
Locke 1689b, Second Treatise, s. 27, pp. 287–8; see also at s. 4, p. 269; Locke 1700, II.xxi.4, II. |
xxi.12, II.xxi.21, II.xxi.24, pp. 235–6, 239–40, 241–4.
- #
- #
- #
- #
- #
- #
- #
- #13.12.20224.1 Кб26._!!The Property Platform in Anglo-American Law and the Primacy of the Property Concept.pdf
- #13.12.20224.1 Кб19._(Cambridge Studies in Philosophy and Law) Stephen R. Munzer-New Essays in the Legal and Political Theory of Property -Cambridge University Press (2007).pdf
- #13.12.20224.1 Кб22._(Critical Approaches to Law) Margaret Davies-Property_ Meanings, Histories, Theories-Routledge-Cavendish (2007).pdf
- #13.12.20224.1 Кб17._(Encyclopedia of Law and Economics 5) Boudewijn Bouckaert-Property Law and Economics -Edward Elgar Publishing (2010).pdf