
The_Cambridge_Foucault_Lexicon
.pdf634 / David Webb
strategy of reading that recalls Heidegger’s “destruction” of the history of ontology, an approach aimed precisely at retrieving possibilities that had been closed off by the metaphysical tradition (Heidegger 1962, §6; Heidegger 1982, §5).
Foucault draws attention to the different roles played by time in the Critique of Pure Reason and the Anthropology, a difference that arises from the nature of the Anthropology’s inquiry into what the human individual “as a free-acting being makes of himself, or can and should make of himself” (Kant 2006, 3), not only by shaping our conduct but also by cultivating our sensibility, understanding, and taste. Kant irst explores this through a rehearsal of structures familiar from the Critique of Pure Reason (sensibility, understanding, reason) and then through a consideration of pleasure, displeasure, and desire that takes in discussions of topics such as distraction, mental illness, dreams, wit, boredom, and eating alone or in company, before going on to deal with character, physiognomy, and the character of races and the sexes, and more besides. Whereas in the Critique of Pure Reason the subject is divided between a transcendental unit that anchors the syntheses of the multiple and the empirical self that appears as an object of intuition, in the Anthropology the subject experiments with provisional variations on the human, each of which may be modiied or undone in turn. Here, writes Foucault, time is not the transparent condition of synthetic activity but rather that by which it is left obscure and incomplete. Simple determination gives way to a gradual and uncertain activity that Kant names Kunst. Time in the Anthropology is described by Foucault as the guarantee of a “dispersion that cannot be contained (qui n’est pas surmontable)” (EIKA, 89). It is “the dispersion of the synthetic activity with regard to itself” (ibid.), the noncoincidence of synthesis with itself as it works through time. By virtue of this structural incompleteness, Foucault writes, the time of the Anthropology eats away at the coherence of synthesis from within, making room for error, correction, repetition, and thereby also a certain freedom (EIKA, 91). The message that Foucault draws from this is that one must avoid a “false” anthropology that seeks to return to a beginning point, whether this be in an empirical sense or by recourse to a transcendental a priori. Instead, he proposes that the a priori of the Critique of Pure Reason be repeated “in a truly temporal dimension” (EIKA, 93). Like Heidegger, then, Foucault sees time as the key to Kant’s anthropology, and, like Heidegger, Foucault tries to identify the temporal structure of synthesis itself. However, whereas Heidegger directs his attention to the temporal dimension of the synthetic activity of the transcendental imagination, Foucault sees the locus of the problem shift to the anthropology, where the purity of this synthesis is adulterated by the time of concrete life. From the point of view of Foucault’s depiction of the way thought in modernity has been caught in an impasse, this disruption of dichotomy between the empirical and the transcendental, between the actual existence and the conditions that make it possible, seems to promise thinking a new future.
However, there are two obstacles that make it impossible simply to take Kant’s formulation in the Anthropology as a solution to the problem. First, the presentation
Martin Heidegger (1889–1976) / 635
of time as a linear series of events has to be constituted by an antecedent activity that cannot itself be represented in the series. The transcendental role of time as the condition of the order of experience is thereby kept out of view, but for this reason the disruptive potentiality of temporal dispersion is also blocked; that is, the account sits irmly within the very structure from which Foucault wishes to escape. Also playing a vital role here is language, which is seen as a regulated articulation of the freedoms by which individuals form a community and thereby accomplish a “concrete universal” (EIKA, 102). If time itself is the dimension of the “originary” (l’originaire), Foucault endorses the view that it “is not to be found in an already given, secret meaning, but in what is the most manifest path of the exchange” (EIKA, 102–103). This becomes problematic, in Foucault’s view, because Kant adopts a “popular” idiom for the Anthropology. By appealing to a common language, shared between author and public, it fosters a certainty that, in spite of the dispersion of time, something clear and whole is nonetheless given, or at least almost within our grasp. Taking up a language that is already familiar from our understanding of the world, the Anthropology deploys it to grasp the human, time is conirmed as an order of empirical events, and the radical potential of temporal dispersion is lost. So when Foucault writes that the reader of the Anthropology is placed in a milieu of “total evidence” where any number of new examples can be found, but that “‘popular knowledge’ is not the irst, the earliest, nor the most naïve form of truth” (EIKA, 94), he is on a path parallel to Heidegger’s contrast of authenticity with the common currency of the impersonal “they” (Heidegger 2010, §27). Moreover, like Heidegger, his solution is to recover a temporal form that has been concealed by this semblance of self-evidence. The difference is that for Heidegger an account of the Being of the subject is only possible once a clear distinction is made between everyday time and the original time of the ontological, whereas Foucault welcomes the way the two are folded together in Kant’s anthropology (a view that matches the one he sketched ten years earlier in his Introduction to Binswanger’s text). But in order that the transformative repercussions of this shift be felt, the screen of self-evidence placed around it when Kant cast anthropology as a “popular” discourse has to be drawn away.
Foucault’s work, as it unfolds later in the 1960s and beyond, retrieves the temporal dispersion he found in Kant from the restrictions of the “popular” idiom, allowing dispersion to shape a different understanding of the subject in its relation to ontology and to knowledge. Archaeological method suspends readymade unities (actors, discourses, works, traditions, artifacts) in the analysis of discourse, exposing history as the gradual, piecemeal, and provisional formation of such unities, their temporary stability, and their ultimate deformation. In this way, it turns a forensic eye on the genesis of forms that the analysis of discourse generally either takes for granted or deines as the conditions of possibility for a given class of events. Foucault sees the dispersion of events in their multiplicity challenge the synthetic activity by which such formal characteristics emerge and by which things, ideas, and
636 / David Webb
even thought itself become intelligible. The archaeological analogue of synthesis produces discourse from discourse, according to rules formed within discourse that are transformed along with the shifting patterns they describe and yet for which they nonetheless establish local conditions of existence. As a response to Kant, and to Heidegger’s response to Kant, archaeology opens synthesis up to what Foucault again identiies as “temporal dispersion” (EAK, 25). The difference is that now the dispersion is caused not by an underlying linear time that eventually undoes the work of the subject but by plural times that are the formation and deformation of unities and regularities. The division between the transcendental and the empirical is erased, and, in the terms Foucault used in his Introduction to Binswanger, there is no a priori distinction between ontology and anthropology.
Foucault’s subsequent introduction of power into his analyses is already well prepared here; the Nietzschean conception of the will to power maps easily onto the transformation in the conditions of existence that comes with the ongoing production of discourse. Similarly, the Nietzschean refusal to see an agent behind the act, or an ideal behind things as they appear, can already be found in archaeology. That said, there is certainly a shift in emphasis in Foucault’s work to treat the rules shaping what can be said and done in terms of power and not just in view of the various functions and positions of discourse. With the emergene of power as a theme in Foucault’s work also comes a further point of comparison with Heidegger, in that Foucault’s insistence that power is not a thing and should not be treated as if it were a substance echoes Heidegger’s approach to Being and the ontological difference. The comparison is a valid one, but only up to a certain point, and the point at which it breaks down reveals an important difference between Heidegger and Foucault over the possibility of ethics and its relation to ontology. In Being and Time, Heidegger describes how we are thrown into a historical situation we did not choose and cannot master. Even so, it is possible for us to confront our own initude and thereby modify our relation to our own ontological condition. In this way, we can transcend the immediate conditions of our factical life. What we cannot do is change the fundamental conditions by which Being is disclosed, which make up the temporal structure of our existence. As Heidegger moved beyond Being and Time, the attempt to determine the temporal horizons of the meaning of Being gave way to a recognition that Being is historical, or rather that the truth of Being is historical, its disclosure taking different forms in different epochs. Since the prevailing form of the disclosure of Being varies from epoch to epoch, at any one time we stand within an opening that sets the conditions of interpretation without itself being open to such interpretation. It is therefore impossible to draw the different epochs of the history of Being into a single account. Similarly for Foucault, how things appear as objects
Martin Heidegger (1889–1976) / 637
of discourse, and thus also the way that subjects are situated in relation to them, varies in ways that the discourses themselves cannot describe. In The Order of Things, this took the form of a division of history into different epistemes, with the working deinition of knowledge being internal to each. Even as this large-scale structure gave way to more inely differentiated analyses, it remained the case for Foucault that we become subjects in relation to what can be established as true or false at any given time, and that this is contingent on the prevailing regularities in the relations of power and knowledge. The difference between Heidegger and Foucault here turns on the question of the priority attributed to the ontological order. The history of the truth of Being as described by Heidegger sees the way Being is disclosed change from one epoch to another, but what does not change is that thinking cannot alter the form of the disclosive event of Being. By contrast, Foucault can be said to preserve the ontological difference while dispensing with the priority of the rules of givenness at any time. In this respect, Heidegger’s move from a uniied temporal horizon of the understanding of Being to a discontinuous history of the truth of Being changes very little from Foucault’s perspective. Like Heidegger, Foucault thinks we can address our own initude (albeit differently), transcend the immediate conditions of our factical life, and modify our relation to the conditions that make us what we are. But this is where the similarity ends, as the relations of power linking us to others, to institutions, and to forms of knowledge that feature in Foucault’s account are in a process of continual change to which our own discourses and critical activities can contribute. For Foucault, we can intervene not just in our relation to our own ontological condition, as Heidegger proposes, but in that very condition itself. This is evident in his later writing, where there is greater emphasis on small degrees of change, rather than epochal shifts, and also on the capacity of the subject to modify them, aided by critical discourses directed at very speciic local conditions: in “What Is Enlightenment?” Foucault describes this as the “undeined work of freedom” (EEW1, 316). For Foucault, we are contemporaries with power in a way that, for Heidegger, we are never contemporaries with Being.
Time therefore is central to Foucault’s philosophy, especially to his divergence from Heidegger. Resituating the “original” temporality by virtue of which things take on actual existence, Foucault places time within the discourse whose unities time forms. Not only does the time of discourse occur only within and as discourse, there is no formal determination of time that can be found repeatedly over a variety of circumstances. Ultimately, it is by virtue of this break with the legacy of formalism that the ontological dimension of Foucault’s analyses can be linked to a certain positivity, and this break marks the divergence between his thought and that of Heidegger.
David Webb
638 / David Webb
See Also
Finitude
Phenomenology
Ludwig Binswanger
Immanuel Kant
Suggested Reading
Han-Pile, Béatrice. 2003. “Foucault and Heidegger on Kant and Finitude,” in Foucault and Heidegger: Critical Encounters, ed. Alan Milchman and Alan Rosenberg. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 127–162.
Heidegger, Martin. 1962. Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. New York: Harper and Row.
1982. The Basic Problems of Phenomenology, trans. Albert Hofstader. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
1990. Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, trans. Richard Taft. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
2010. Being and Time, trans. Joan Stambaugh, revised with a Foreword by Dennis J. Schmidt. Albany: The SUNY Press.
Kant, Immanuel. 2006. Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View, trans. Robert B. Louden and Manfred Kuehn. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
107
JEAN HYPPOLITE (1907–1968)
Jean Hyppolite was the French translator of Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, for which he also wrote in 1946 a long commentary (Genesis and Structure of Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit); he followed this book with a study in 1952 of
Hegel’s logic (Logic and Existence). In 1954, he was appointed director of the École
Normale Supérieure in Paris; he was elected to the Collège de France in 1963. The academic connection between Jean Hyppolite and Foucault is clear. At the École Normale Supérieure in the late 1940s and early 1950s, Hyppolite was Foucault’s teacher, and Foucault replaced Hyppolite at the Collège de France in 1969 after Hyppolite died suddenly. The philosophical connection between them, however, is more dificult to determine.
Hyppolite’s interpretation of Hegel seemed to have a twofold effect on the evolution of French thought as it entered the 1960s, as the moment of French existentialism, the moment of Sartre and Merleau-Ponty, was starting to fade. On the one hand, Hyppolite stressed that Hegel’s thought was not a humanism. If one focuses on the Phenomenology of Spirit, and especially if one focuses on the master–slave dialectic (as Kojève did in his famous lectures), humanity plays a key role in that dialectic. However, even the Phenomenology ends in “absolute knowledge,” a position that transcends humanity. If one focuses on Hegel’s Logic, as Hypppolite did in Logic and Existence, this movement beyond humanity is even clearer. On the other hand,
Hyppolite clariied the movement of Hegelian transcendence. Hyppolite recognized that Hegel, before Nietzsche, had aimed at a reversal of Platonism, meaning that the movement beyond did not aim at a second ideal world. Hegel’s dialectic, for Hyppolite, is still immanent to experience. Remaining, however, immanent to experience, the dialectic is a singular movement of differentiation, a movement that hollows out a position, placing it in opposition to another position but not in opposition to another position that is external to the original position. Therefore, and here we have Hyppolite’s strongest inluence on the generation of French philosophers that
639
640 / Leonard Lawlor
includes Foucault, Derrida, and Deleuze, the central issue in Hegel’s thought is difference, the difference between nature and spirit, the difference between experience and logic, the difference between initude and ininity, and probably most importantly for Foucault, the difference between philosophy and history.
In his inaugural address at the Collège, Foucault acknowledged that he owed a lot to Hyppolite. Foucault added, however, that Hyppolite showed all of us that the task of philosophy lies not in generalization but in reestablishing contact with what precedes it, in drawing as close as possible to “the singularity of history” (EAK, 236). Undoubtedly, the task of all of Foucault’s archaeological studies can be summarized in this “task of philosophy.” At the same moment as his inaugural address, Foucault also wrote a eulogy for Hyppolite. There he makes this task clearer, saying that, “The problem that Hyppolite never stopped working on is perhaps this one: what is this limitation that is proper to philosophical discourse, the limitation that allows it or makes it appear as the speech of philosophy itself, in a word: what is philosophical initude?” (FDE1, 781, Foucault’s emphasis, my translation). The chair that
Foucault occupied at the Collège de France was the Chair of the History of Systems of Thought. We can see now that what Foucault called “systems of thought,” especially at the end of his career (see EEW1, 201), really concerned this very limitation that connects philosophy back to history. It concerned the difference that makes philosophy inite but that also allows philosophical thought to go beyond that limitation. Repeatedly, Foucault speaks of his histories having the purpose of transformation (see, for example, EAK, 130). It is this difference that allows thought to transform the very conditions in which it inds itself.
Leonard Lawlor
See Also
Archaeology
Finitude
History
Suggested Reading
Hyppolite, Jean. 1974. Genesis and Structure of Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. Samuel
Cherniak and John Heckman. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
1991. Figures de la pensée philosophique. Paris: Quadrige Presses Universitaires de France. 1997. Logic and Existence, trans. Leonard Lawlor and Amit Sen. Albany: The SUNY Press. Lawlor, Leonard. 2003. Thinking Through French Philosophy. Bloomington: Indiana University
Press.
108
IMMANUEL K ANT (1724–1804)
Shredded by the reverberations of a triply polarized conceptual ield, the experience of Kant in Foucault’s thought can hardly be univocally described. A system of echoes resonates in three chords. Foucault’s reading of Kant is split between critique as a discourse with lofty transcendental pretensions and critique as the spiritual attitude that animates it, in view of the self-transformation required for having experience in which freedom and truth are not mutually exclusive (ECF-HOS, 14–19, 25–30). Foucault's philosophical position with respect to Kant is ambivalent, divided between the need to redress its misguided epistemological ideals and the will to project its useful ontological attitude. The methodological implications for his own thought, in which there are recurrent points of intersection between method and material, are also divided, between points of resistance to the transcendental and moments of interpretive transference. And so the echoes of Kant in Foucault are caught in three layers of distortion: between a discourse described from the outside and its exercise experienced from within; between what is left and what is taken; and between the description and the use of method. This exposition plays out the irst to
the point of its reprise in the second, with a gesture in the direction of the third. Aside perhaps from Nietzsche, Kant igures more prominently than any other
philosopher in Foucault’s otherwise contentious histories. But nothing about the way Kant is portrayed in them is orthodox. Kant is a major reference in Foucault’s early analysis of discursive practices and in his late work on practices of the self, but is barely mentioned in the twelve years in between The Order of Things and “What Is
Critique?” (found in EPT and FQC). Scattered in several texts at the extremities of his work, the scope of Foucault’s accounts of Kant varies from terse historical characterizations to full-scale textual analysis. In both the early and the late characterizations, Foucault’s Kant is bipolar: the familiar speculative, transcendental thought of the Critiques is cast into a ield of interpenetration and contestation with the kind of relection found in popular works such as the Anthropology and the Enlightenment
641
642 / Marc DJABALLAH
essay. The problem of the relation between the two is the leitmotif of the experience of Kant in Foucault.
Kant’s importance for Foucault stems in part from Hyppolite, with whom he studied briely at Lycée Henri-IV in 1945 and who supervised both his Diplôme d’Études Supérieures (a French degree roughly equivalent to an advanced Master’s, degree) on Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit in 1949 and his 1961 PhD thèse complémentaire at the Sorbonne. The thesis, a translation of Kant’s Anthropology accompanied by an extensive introduction (published in 2008 as FKF), is Foucault’s irst and most sustained study of Kant. Hyppolite had reservations about it, notably that Foucault’s reading was “inspired by Nietzsche more than by Kant” (Eribon 1991, 114). The fact that Foucault was known to refer to it as his “book on Nietzsche” goes to show that he took the criticism well, to say the least (Potte-Bonneville and Defert 2010). Indeed, if Foucault’s Kant is post-Nietzschean, it is surely not a matter of exegetical weakness. One also hears echoes of Heidegger – through whom Foucault came to the study of Nietzsche – in the recurrence to “repetition” and the “originary.” But despite its unavowed inspirations, the thesis is by no means merely a student work. Clearly the culmination of years of study and teaching (the Anthropology igured in
Foucault’s teaching at least as early as 1953), its penetrating analysis of the genesis and structure of Kant’s text and of its historical signiicance is of great value for an understanding of his subsequent work. Its interrogation is genetic, systematic, and historical.
The problem of the relation between transcendental and popular standpoints in Kant surfaces at the intersection of the genetic and the systematic register. Foucault addresses Kant’s thought as a discursive practice, a form of experience that can be either described from the outside as a closed discursive system on the basis of its materialization in a text or verbal expression or exercised, by lateral insertion, as an opening onto a reality. Critical discourse circularly does the former by means of the latter: it describes forms of experience – ways to sensibly interrogate reality – by using what it describes as its method. The experience of Kant in Foucault is polarized not only between the Critiques and Anthropology or the Enlightenment essay but also with respect to the priority of the discourse of critique and of the exercise of a critical attitude. We will see that these are not theoretical options like prongs of a fork but directions of a reversible polarity; the one is just the other turned inside out.
Foucault shows that the Critiques record an epistemologically oriented version of the practice by describing the form of experience in terms of the conditions under which universal and necessary knowledge is possible. This transcendental critique reaches a level of abstraction apt for its radically general external description by moving inferentially from qualities of reality such as it is given from the inside to an external description of the rules according to which we systematically determine and regulate it as such by way of chains of indispensability relations. Absolutely general
Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) / 643
regularities are thereby sifted from our experience. The idea underlying Foucault’s reading is that this transcendental critique betrays itself as a practice. By foreclosing the objective of self-transformation as a condition of access to truth in a conception of the subject that is also the condition of impossibility of knowledge, it screens itself from the indeterminacy of its experience and denies its self-participation in what it describes, leaving only the description. The practice of transcendental critique functions as though it were not a practice at all but the material record of its exercise in a circuit of distinctions, its image in the mirror. It is as though the conceptual matter of the Critique exhausted its practice.
In The Order of Things, the historical signiicance of transcendental critique is tied to its simultaneity with ideology (Destutt de Tracy and Gerando), with which it shares a ield of application, representational relations. Their overlap is the hinge in the passage of classical representational to modern anthropological thought. Whereas the Ideologues attempted to capture the nonrepresentative in the very form of representation, critique suspends the analysis of representations by asking how representation itself is possible. Kant’s transcendental critique pulls thought out of the ininite space of representations the Ideologues had attempted to exhaustively render scientiically. At the level of nonrepresentative conditions of representation, he unmasks the attempt, and the project of representational thought in general, as dogmatic metaphysics. Paradoxically, for Foucault regrettably, this moment – the simultaneity of Ideology and Kant’s critique that denounces it – also paves the way for a new anthropological metaphysics (EOT, 241–242).
The priority in transcendental critique of discursive over practical criteria, of a closed system over its exercise as opening, is reversed in the ontological practices of critique such as recorded in the Anthropology and the Enlightenment piece. This explains Foucault’s resistance to the objectives of transcendental critique and his antipathy for post-Kantian anthropology, which replays transcendental betrayal and begs the question of the extent to which his own histories of experience do not succumb. With an ontological orientation, anthropological critique reverses this critical practice, taking the results of transcendental critique as given – the capacities and categories through which experience is conditioned – and showing that, transposed from the a priori to the originary temporal lux, they lend their igure to concrete existence.
When they were published toward the end of his life in 1798, Kant had given the Anthropology lectures for a quarter of a century, in the midst of which transcendental critique was developed and published in the irst Critique. Foucault shows that the relation between the two implies that transcendental critique is a moment in the elaboration of anthropological critique, which reaches a point of stabilization in transcendental philosophy (EIKA, 23). Foucault explains how the anthropocritical repetition brings about a shift in Kant’s thought from the cosmological standpoint of the 1760s and 1770s, which takes the world as already given, to a cosmopolitical