
The_Cambridge_Foucault_Lexicon
.pdf484 / Richard A. Lynch
sentence, a value as truth to the proposition” (EAK, 91). Statements demarcate what meanings are possible for sentences. Second, statements do not presuppose a speaking subject as cogito; rather, they create the possibility of assigning one (or more) subject position(s) to a group of signs. A mathematical treatise may encode multiple subject positions: the personal author, whose voice speaks in the acknowledgments and preface; a person-neutral subject position which speaks in the statement of axioms; and other positions (EAK, 94). Third, statements function within a network of other statements – it is this complex web that distinguishes a statement as such: “There is no statement that does not presuppose others; there is no statement that is not surrounded by a ield of coexistences, effects of series and succession, a distribution of functions and roles” (EAK, 99). Statements will effectuate distinct enunciative functions by virtue of their position within such a discursive web. Finally, statements have a material existence – they serve to place the units (sentences, propositions, etc.) in a usable space by being voiced, written, published, and so on under certain circumstances. Thus a sentence may be reiterated in different contexts, in which it constitutes different statements, with different effects. But statements, too, are thus limited “by all the other statements among which it igures, by the domain in which it can be used or applied, by the role and functions that it can perform” (EAK, 103).
Each of these four distinctions illustrates that statements serve to demarcate or delimit a ield of objects and their possible, permissible, impossible, and impermissible combinations. Thus, what distinguishes and deines a statement is not its form (as proposition, sentence, etc.) but its enunciative function – which is itself relective of the discursive ield in which the statement is realized and which the statement in turn reciprocally serves to constitute. This ield includes “all the other formulations with which the statement appears,” “all the formulations to which the statement refers,” “all the formulations whose subsequent possibility is determined by the statement,” and “all the formulations whose status the statement in question shares” (EAK, 98–99). In this sense, the statement is a key element of a discourse, for “discourse can be deined as the group of statements that belong to a single system of formation” (EAK, 107).
The ield or set of statements thus described emerges “as the locus of particular events, regularities, relationships, modiications and systematic transformations; in short ... as a practical domain that is autonomous” (EAK, 121). Foucault’s “archaeological method,” then, can be understood as the “analysis of statements” – historical, noninterpretive analysis that “questions them as to their mode of existence, what it means to them to have come into existence, to have left traces, and perhaps to remain there, awaiting the moment when they might be of use once more; what it means to them to have appeared when and where they did – they and no others” (EAK, 109).
Richard A. Lynch
STATEMENT / 485
See Also
Archaeology
Language
Literature
Parresia
Truth
Suggested Reading
Deleuze, Gilles. 1988. Foucault, trans. Seán Hand. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Gutting, Gary. 1989. Michel Foucault’s Archaeology of Scientiic Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
83
STRATEGIES (AND TAC TICS)
“Strategies” and “tactics” are both concepts that derive from
Foucault’s general approach to power as a practice rather than an institution or a substance. Insofar as power is understood as a “multiplicity of force relations” (EHS1, 92) whereby one set of actions modiies another, any general
treatment of power must be anchored in singular force relations. Only once these speciic relations have been accounted for can Foucault go on to investigate how these singular instantiations coordinate with other force relations and thereby form an apparatus. In Foucault’s oeuvre, “tactic” will refer to these local force relations, whereas “strategy” will denote the coordination of these particular instances.
In Foucault’s examinations of madness, sex, or coninement, his approach consistently identiies the most local applications of force, including the power a doctor exercises over patients, the power a father exercises over his wife and children, or the power a boss exercises over workers (FDE2a, 379). Yet these are only properly called “tactics” to the extent that they are enveloped by a strategy that integrates these local force relations of power and employs them in a global agenda. Foucault’s work is perhaps best known for identifying two major strategies operative in modern society: the disciplinary and the biopolitical. Speaking of these forms strictly as strategies, discipline and biopolitics are abstract forms that stand independent of any particular institution. For instance, “discipline” refers to the conduct imposed on a limited group of individuals in a conined space, and it matters little if we examine inmates in a prison, students in a school, or patients in a hospital. Although the panoptic form that organizes all of these relationships is exempliied by Bentham’s Panopticon, insofar as it is strategy it is not reducible to any single individual or text: “It is the diagram of a mechanism of power reduced to its ideal form; its functioning, abstracted from any obstacle, resistance or friction, must be represented as a pure architectural and optical system: it is in fact a igure of political technology that may and must be detached from any speciic use” (EDP, 205). Yet this is not at all to say
486
Strategies (and Tactics) / 487
that strategies operate as abstract forms imposed from the outside onto concrete tactics. Rather, strategies and tactics are absolutely immanent to each other as well as co-conditioning. That is, discipline could not be effective at the global level if it did not ind its support in precise relations between doctors and patients, teachers and students, and so on. Conversely, no single tactic would function were it not conjoined and coordinated with other tactics. Foucault will call this co-dependence between strategies and tactics their “double conditioning” (EHS1, 99–100), but “double” here does not refer to any kind of copying or modeling between tactics and strategies. We would misunderstand this relationship completely if we thought tactics were miniature copies that emanated from a model strategy: “[T]he father in the family is not the ‘representative’ of the sovereign or state; and the latter are not projections of the father on a different scale. The family does not duplicate society, just as society does not imitate the family” (EHS1, 100). Strategies do not exist before tactics. Rather, the tactical relationship that deines the family is conjoined with other tactics in medicine, statistics, and psychiatry to form a strategy, and the “double conditioning” between strategies and tactics must refer to the way in which strategies enable particular force relations to ind their consistency and stability, whereas tactics must anchor a strategy in precise and concrete points of support.
This heterogeneity of tactics and strategies is important when we consider the fact that although tactics are often carried out quite explicitly by individuals at the local level, the way in which they are connected to one another to form a comprehensive system is entirely anonymous in Foucault’s account. That is to say, there is no subject who invents or is responsible for carrying out a strategy, and furthermore, the strategy that comes to envelop a tactic may be quite antithetical to the aims of those who “invented” any particular practice. Yet the anonymity of strategies does not result in a kind of physical determinism: even though strategies coordinate tactics to form a general line of force, the particular force relations that are traced out and conjoined are by no means entirely stable. This instability derives from the contingent nature of any tactical relation. Although these local force relations do anchor strategies and function as their points of support, their tenuous nature constantly harbors the possibility of a redistribution or realignment of any broader strategy of power. Thus, because tactics are not only the concrete supports of any strategy but also the site of these strategies, we might say that tactics are situated as a sort of hinge between the potentially totalizing effects of strategies and the resistance to these very strategies.
How does a simple relationship between confessor and pastor, doctor and patient, or inmate and guard transform itself into the restructuring of complex political strategies such as biopower or disciplinary power? An example is instructive. In Foucault’s lectures at the Collège de France from 1977–1978, we ind several maneuvers at the tactical level that are essential to the struggle against the Christian pastorate, including tactical shifts in eschatology, Scripture, mysticism, the community,
488 / John Nale
and askesis. Let us briely examine askesis, which will of course become a major theme in Foucault’s late work.
One of the tenets of the Christian pastorate is that the pastor must be concerned with the conduct of each and every individual so as to guarantee their salvation. This functions in part through what Foucault calls a “complete subordination” (ECF-STP, 178) whereby each and every individual completely renounces his will and submits himself to the pastor. This relationship of servitude is manifested in the minute details of monastic life and ultimately comes to take the form of a “test of good obedience” within the monastic institution. Referring to these tests of obedience, Foucault explains, “As soon as an order is given to a monk, he must immediately stop whatever he happens to be doing at the time and carry out the order without wondering why he has been given this order or whether it wouldn’t be more worthwhile to continue with what he was doing” (ECF-STP, 176). Accordingly, this form of power relies on a complete renunciation of the will, and the sincerity of the renunciation is guaranteed by a series of tests. However, the Christian pastorate will enter a “crisis” when this test of obedience and the renunciation of the will becomes a test of askesis. These ascetic practices, deined by Foucault as “an exercise of self on self” (ECF-STP, 205), involves the self-imposition of a series of tests such as fasting, whipping oneself, or burning oneself that become progressively more dificult and insufferable. But the intent of these exercises is essentially incompatible with pastoral obedience because these self-imposed sufferings ultimately create an individual who “becomes the guide of his own asceticism” (ECF-STP, 205). That is to say, through these tests, the ascetic no longer stands in a position of servitude to a superior but rather achieves mastery over himself and his body – a self-mastery that is antithetical to the pastoral obedience to another. This is merely a single tactical reversal, but when it is coordinated with other practices such as mysticism, eschatology, and so on, a crisis and restructuring at the strategic level is brought about.
Examples of tactical reversals such as this, where a dominated group or individual seizes on a tactic as a means of escape, help us see why Michel de Certeau, following both von Clausewitz and Foucault, will declare, “a tactic is an art of the weak” (Certeau 2002, 37). However, what is essential to note is that although this tactical reversal is opposed to the Christian pastorate’s call for obedience, this is not an opposition that operates from outside the pastoral system of power. Rather, asceticism resists pastoral power by reimplementing or reutilizing its own elements, such as the “test,” and thereby must be deined as an immanent form of counter-conduct or resistance. Foucault emphasizes the immanence of resistance when he writes, “the struggle [against pastoral power] was not conducted in the form of double exteriority, but rather in the form of the permanent use of tactical elements that are pertinent to the anti-pastoral struggle insofar as they fall within, in a marginal way, the general horizon of Christianity” (ECF-STP, 215, my emphasis). Thus, whenever we ind an instance of resistance or opposition in Foucault’s work, we must be careful
Strategies (and Tactics) / 489
that it is not actually based on practices of “reimplementation” or “reutilization,” or even repetition, that underpin oppositions to a strategy. In sum, because resistance occurs at the tactical level, and because tactics and strategies are co-conditioning and immanent to each other, any resistance to strategies such as pastoral power, disciplinary power, or biopower must be anchored in tactics constituting these very strategies. That is, the possibility of an escape or light from any strategic regime is always immanent to every speciic application of power, and this aspect of power derives from the “double conditioning” of tactics and strategies, whereby unstable tactical relations constitute potentially totalizing strategies and these strategies are built on unpredictable, tenuous tactical relations.
John Nale
See Also
Biopolitics
Discipline
Politics
Power
Suggested Reading
Certeau, Michel de. 2002. The Practice of Everyday Life. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Deleuze, Gilles. 1988. “Strategies or the Non-stratiied: The Thought of the Outside (Power),” in Foucault, trans. Seán Hand. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 47–69.
Derrida, Jacques. 1985. “The Ends of Man,” in Margins of Philosophy, trans. Alan Bass. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, pp. 109–136.
Thompson, Kevin. 2003. “Forms of Resistance: Foucault on Tactical Reversal and SelfFormation,” Continental Philosophy Review 36, no. 2:113–138.
84
STRUC TURALISM
When Foucault was asked in 1969 if he was a structuralist, he answered with a riddle: “What’s the difference between Bernard Shaw and Charlie Chaplin? There is none, because they both have a beard, except Chaplin,
of course” (FDE1, 788). For two reasons, Foucault’s relation to structuralism is particularly dificult to characterize. First and most simply, structuralism has never been deined by a clear set of doctrines or ideas. It is traditionally seen as a movement that has its roots in the early twentieth century, in the linguistics of Ferdinand de Saussure, and that was later developed by French scholars who worked in ields as different as anthropology (Claude Lévi-Strauss), psychoanalysis (Jacques Lacan), Marxism (Louis Althusser), literature (Roland Barthes), and history (Foucault) (for a general historical survey, see Dosse 1998). What all these authors share intellectually is not directly apparent, and it is not without reason that when in 1983 Foucault relected on the heyday of structuralism, he admitted that “no one really knew what [structuralism] was” (FDE4, 431; see also FDE2, 268).
To further complicate the situation, Foucault himself gave contradictory assessments of his relation to structuralism. From the early 1960s on, especially with the publication of Birth of the Clinic in 1963, he clearly and unapologetically embraced structuralism. The apotheosis of this structuralist period is The Order of Things, which was originally to be entitled The Archaeology of Structuralism (Dreyfus and Rabinow 1983, 17), and in which he analyzed “in terms of structure the birth of structuralism itself” (FDE1, 583). For a short while after the publication of The Order of Things, Foucault did not mind being called a structuralist. To an interviewer who claimed that he was “the priest of structuralism,” he replied that he was only its “altar boy,” because he was part of a movement that had begun long before him (FDE1, 581). Soon thereafter, however, he tried to distance himself from the structuralist movement, to the point of calling those who believed he had ever been a structuralist “idiots, naïves and ignoramuses” (FDE2, 296). In 1972, he signiicantly altered Birth
490
STRUCTURALISM / 491
of the Clinic for its second edition, notably by erasing several of the irst edition’s explicit references to structuralism.
But Foucault’s reversal took more the form of a visceral self-defense than that of a leshed-out argument, and his position ended up being at times incoherent. For instance, at the end of the “Foreword” to the English edition of The Order of Things, he claimed that he had “used none of the methods, concepts, or key terms that characterize structural analysis” (EOT, xiv). But in a conference presentation given that same year (1970), he explained that what he had done in his work was “only to have recourse to the structuralist method” (FDE2, 133). One year later, he lipped back and afirmed that he had “never, at any time, used the methods peculiar to the structural analyses” (FDE2, 209–210, 216). Interestingly, in the early 1970s, Georges Dumézil, who strongly inluenced Foucault throughout his career, was uttering similar contradictory statements about his own position toward structuralism (see Eribon 1992, 329–334).
Foucault was probably more exasperated by structuralism as a label that was uncritically and automatically stamped on his work than as a method for studying cultural issues. Instead of trying to determine whether Foucault was a structuralist, it is more enlightening to look at the points of intersection between some general aspects of structuralism and Foucault’s work. Whether these commonalities are suficient to win Foucault a membership card in the structuralist club will depend on how exclusive one wants this club to be, but at the very least this analysis will make clear that Foucault rode the wave of structuralism that took over France as he was beginning his work.
Already in his very irst interview, given in 1961, Foucault explained that he had been greatly inluenced by Dumézil’s idea of structure (FDE1, 168). Dumézil had showed in his analyses of myths how the same structure can be found, with some modiications, in the myths of radically different cultures. In good structuralist fashion, a structure was therefore independent from its concrete elements. After the publication of The Order of Things in 1966, Foucault presented his book as a type of Dumézilian work, in which he had tried to show how there is “an isomorphism between discourses at a given time period” (EOT, xi). Against historians who believe they can fully explain a discourse by reducing it to its social and economic conditions, Foucault emphasized the importance of the structural level: one must “take into consideration the force and consistency of ... isomorphisms” (FDE1, 591).
Although The Order of Things marks the pinnacle of Foucault’s focus on discursive isomorphisms, he kept privileging structures and rules over substantial elements in his later works. Most radically, in The Archaeology of Knowledge, he explained that what he wished to do was “to dispense with ‘things’,” which meant to deine objects “without reference to the foundation of things, but by relating them to the body of rules that enable ... them [to be formed] as objects of a discourse and thus to constitute the conditions of their historical appearance” (EAK, 48). As Foucault later
492 / Patrick Singy
said of sexuality, for instance, its “fundamental characteristics ... correspond to the functional exigencies of the discourse that must produce its truth.... It is the ‘economy’ of discourses, that is to say their intrinsic technology, the necessities of their operation, the tactics that they employ, the effects of power which underlie them and which they transmit – it is this ... that determines the fundamental characteristics of what they say” (EHS1, 68–69). “Sexuality” was for Foucault nothing more than the nodal point of a set of “functional exigencies,” very much like for Saussure the knight in a chess game is not deined substantially (by its shape, color, size, matter, etc.) but structurally: any object can be a knight as long as it follows the rules that knights must follow (Saussure 1995, 153–154; see Veyne 1978, 423, for the rapprochement between Foucault’s method and the Saussurean chess analogy).
Several important methodological consequences follow from the primacy given to structures over their elements. First, the relations governing the elements within or between structures are not causal but “of a logical kind, like implication, exclusion, [and] transformation” (FDE1, 607). Foucault criticized the traditional historians’ focus on causal relations: “one must get rid of the prejudice according to which a history without causality would not be a history” (FDE1, 607). Acknowledging the inluence of linguistic structuralism, the new type of history that he advocated looked at the problem of “the insertion of logic into the very heart of reality” (FDE1, 824). After the publication of The Order of Things, Foucault played down this type of abstract terminology and claimed instead that “language can be analyzed in its formal properties only if we take into account its concrete functioning” (FDE1, 595). Yet even in later works he continued to show very little interest in causal relations, which have always been front and center in traditional historiography, and kept focusing on structural relations of implication or exclusion. For instance, in Discipline and Punish he was not primarily interested in the causes of the emergence of modern prisons. What he tried to do was to show that there is a relation of implication between the modern modality of power, which he called “the disciplines,” and a series of elements that include not only prisons but also schools, the army, hospitals, psychiatry, and criminology. The disciplines also logically exclude practices that were typical of the power of the Old Régime, such as torture. Torture was thus presented by Foucault as being “irrational” in relation to the disciplines (FDE4, 26).
Second, inasmuch as a structure is not an aggregation of discrete elements but a holistic system, a transformation of one element is necessarily accompanied by the transformation of all the other elements (see FDE1, 839). This implies that the transition from one structure to another can only occur in a block: history is discontinuous. In The Order of Things, the three discourses on which Foucault focused (the discourses on natural creatures, on economic exchanges, and on language) are transformed synchronically and abruptly, since these discourses are the three elements of
STRUCTURALISM / 493
one structure, or episteme. Foucault wanted to abandon “the grand and old biological metaphor of life and evolution” that had plagued the traditional, continuous type of history since the nineteenth century (FDE2, 280–281).
Third, Lévi-Strauss had claimed that the fundamental difference between ethnology and history is not a difference in goals, objects, or methods but in the fact that ethnology, unlike history, is primarily concerned with the unconscious conditions of social existence (Lévi-Strauss 1958, 24–25). In that regard, Foucault’s history is an application of Lévi-Strauss’s ethnology to Western civilization. He tried to “ind in the history of science, of knowledge [connaissances] and of human knowledge [savoir humain] something that would be like their unconscious” (FDE1, 665–666; see also EOT, xi). There is, however, a crucial difference between Foucault’s and LéviStrauss’s concepts of the unconscious: Foucault always conceived of the unconscious as something thoroughly historical, whereas Lévi-Strauss claimed that it remains fundamentally the same in every civilization (Lévi-Strauss 1958, 28, 224–225; see Revel 2008, 126).
Last, and most importantly, Foucault found in structuralism an eficient weapon against humanism. His main target was Jean-Paul Sartre, to whom he opposed LéviStrauss, Lacan, and Dumézil (see FDE1, 513–516). As Foucault said in a laconic formula, with structuralism “the ‘I’ has exploded ... it is the discovery of the ‘there is’” (FDE1, 515; see also FDE1, 591). Hence he makes the following counterintuitive statement in The Order of Things: the classical episteme “has made possible these individualities that we call Hobbes, or Berkeley, or Hume, or Condillac” (FMC, 77; see also FDE2, 59–61). Methodologically, the structural dissolution of the subject undermined “the great myth of interiority” and therefore the “old exegetic tradition” that required identifying the “true thought of an author” (FDE1, 592). Foucault wanted instead to “determine the conditions of [a statement’s] existence, to ix as exactly as possible its limits, to establish its correlations with the other statements with which it might be linked, to show what other forms of enunciation it excludes” (FDE1, 706). Accordingly, Foucault relentlessly attacked the writing of “commentaries,” which “by deinition admits an excess of the signiied over the signiier” (FNC, xii), and gave himself the task of making “visible what is invisible only because it is too much on the surface of things” (FDE1, 772).
Anti-humanism had emerged early in French thought, and independently from structuralism (Geroulanos 2010). Foucault himself identiied at least three other breaches made to the Sartrean subject: the philosophy of Nietzsche (FDE1, 775; FDE4, 48), the literary works of Blanchot and Bataille (FDE1, 614–615; FDE4, 48), and a new kind of history, which according to Foucault had its origin in Marx and had been developed by the Annales school (FAS, “Introduction”; FDE1, 700; FDE2, 280–281). Despite this overdetermination of anti-humanism, Foucault’s repeated mentions of structuralism’s ability to “call into question the importance