
The_Cambridge_Foucault_Lexicon
.pdf324 / David-Olivier Gougelet
For Foucault, the possibility for new forms of thinking requires that violence be done to thought. In heterotopias, the familiar connection between language and being is “untied.” Whereas utopias are spaces in which words and things are ordered in such a way as to comfort us, and therefore close off any possibility for new forms of thought, heterotopias “disquiet” us precisely because they forcibly place thought into contact with disorder, with an ordering of discourses and their objects with which thought is unfamiliar and is therefore impossible for it to think (EOT, xviii). In this sense, the heterotopia is a space of impossibility in which lies the very possibility for thinking. Heterotopias open up an “unthinkable space” and “transgress all imagination, all possible thought” (EOT, xvi). They are unthinkable, and this undergoing of the impossibility of the heterotopia is a violent one for thought. This is why Foucault writes of the experience of “disquiet,” of “unease” in having thought “shaken” from its “familiarities.” But in that violence, in the unthinkability of the outside, lies the very possibility for thinking.
Heterotopias undo the taut and familiar connection between words and things, in the process ruining all of the identities, the very order, to which thought is accustomed. Heterotopias ruin classiication, taxonomy, and, ultimately, the manifest ordering of words and things. And this is precisely why they open up the possibility for new ways of thinking. This opening up begins with an experience of profound unease, as thought encounters the unthinkable. But, for Foucault, thinking can only arise out of an encounter with that which cannot be thought: the undergoing of its own initude, in the form of the problematic or paradoxical, on the part of thought is the necessary condition for the possibility of thinking.
Therein lies the importance of the modern epoch’s nascent fascination with the being of language and that of its attempts to arrive once more at a certain unity of discourse, a unity whose dispersion had made the birth of the form of thinking called “man” possible. As the unity of classical representation became undone, man, Foucault explains, “composed his own igure in the interstices of [a] fragmented language” (EOT, 386). And if it is now possible to think of even the mere possibility of the disappearance of man, understood as a concept produced by and producer of the very discourses that purport to take “man” as their object, as a concept therefore manifesting a certain order, it is because the “return of language” in its unity serves to ill the spaces within language where “man” has dwelled since the advent of the modern epoch.
These inal moments, in which Foucault wonders for the irst time whether it might not be possible to see, in the return of language, the imminent death of man, are intimately tied to his earlier discussion of heterotopias and their relation to thought and order. It is linguistics and literature that pose the question of the being of language in such a way that a space for the disappearance of “man” might inally open up. Literature, in its posing of the question of language to itself, manifests “the fundamental forms of initude” in their “empirical vivacity.” For Foucault, what is
OUTSIDE / 325
announced in literature’s posing of the question of language is that “man is ‘inite’” (EOT, 383).
Thus, far from bringing “man,” as a modern igure of thought, back to his own identity, the experience of literature instead pushes man to the “edge of what limits it,” to the outside. In undergoing the experience inherent in literature, man is brought into contact with the unthinkable regions of his own initude, in the forms of death and madness. It is in this sense that the thought of the being of language is a thought from and of the outside: literature confronts man with the space of his own end, “where death prowls, where thought is extinguished, where the promise of the origin interminably recedes” (EOT, 383). In this sense, the bare experience of language is the very perversion of the analytic of initude to which the igure of man is so inextricably tied and that Foucault famously analyzes in Chapter 9 of The Order of Things.
This bare experience of language opens up a space in which man “undergoes” the “forms of initude in language,” which is another way of saying that the igure of man, the subject, is put into question at its very foundation. In the language of literature, the “igure of initude” manifests itself, this time not in the positivity of knowledge but in terms of the unthinkable negativity of death: the igure of man inds itself for the irst time determined from without, and initude takes the form of an unthinkable limit. The outside, for Foucault, is precisely the form of thought in which this undoing of the subject takes place. The undergoing of the forms of initude manifested in the space of literature is one in which the particular ordering of words and things that is man is put into question and in which the possibility for new manifestations of order opens up. The experience of the outside, then, is an experience of “death,” of “unthinkable thought,” of “repetition,” of “initude” (EOT, 384); it is the undergoing of alterity, and in it the fragile play of identity on which the igure of man was erected is undone as the subject is coerced into contact with a region it must, but cannot, think of: its own limit.
Accordingly, as Foucault reiterates in “The Thought from Outside,” his homage to Maurice Blanchot, it is language, in the form of literature, that leads us to “the outside where the speaking subject disappears.” In other words, the “naked experience of language,” by coercing the subject into an encounter with its own initude, opens up a space in which the “I am” is undone; therein lies its “danger” to established thought and subjective identity (EFB, 13). In the modern epoch, the opening up of this experience from which the subject is excluded and in which its identity is shattered is to be found in a form of thought that is able to think of the peculiar relation that exists between language and the subject: “the being of language only appears for itself in the disappearance of the subject” (EFB, 15). Or, alternately, the bare experience of language is one in which the unity of the subject is shattered. This is a form of thought that “stands outside of any subjectivity” in order to make apparent “its limits” from without, in order to announce “its end” and “its dispersion”; it is
326 / David-Olivier Gougelet
a form of thought that “with respect to the interiority of our philosophical relection and with respect to the positivity of our knowledge, constitutes what one could call the thought from the outside” (EFB, 15–16). As in “Preface to Transgression” and The Order of Things, this thought is the thought of the impossible, of the unthinkable; it demands to be referred not to the unity of the cogito but rather to the fractured I, to the undone and dispersed subject. Thinking, in the sense of creation, occurs only in the shattering of thought, as a result of the violent encounter with the unthinkable. The works of Borges, Sade, Artaud, Roussel, Nietzsche, Mallarmé, Klossowski, Bataille, and Blanchot are all forms of a thought from and of the outside, in the sense that they coerce thought into an experience of language in which it encounters what is for it unthinkable, and in so doing opens up the possibility for a new ordering of the relation between language and being. Only through the undergoing of what is most foreign to it can thought, for Foucault, engage in actual thinking.
David-Olivier Gougelet
See Also
Contestation
Death
Finitude
Language
Literature
Space
Georges Bataille
Maurice Blanchot
Suggested Reading
Blanchot, Maurice. 1992. “Atheism and Writing, Humanism and the Cry,” in The Ininite Conversation, trans. Susan Hanson. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp.
246–263.
Borgés, Jorge Luis. 2000. “John Wilkins’ Analytical Language,” in Borgés: Selected Non-Fictions, trans. Eliot Weinberger. New York: Penguin, pp. 229–232.
Deleuze, Gilles. 1988. “Strategies or the Non-stratiied: The Thought of the Outside (Power),” in Foucault, trans. Seán Hand. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 47–69.
56
PAINTING (AND PHOTOGRAPHY)
Two of Foucault’s signature essays on painting are especially well known: the analysis of Velazquez’s Las Meninas, and an essay on René Magritte that includes a striking account of how abstraction displaced representation in Western art. In addition, many of Foucault’s texts are studded with acute descriptions of major painters from Breughel to Warhol; he gave lecture courses on quattrocento painting and Manet and published essays on several contemporary artists (Rebeyrolle, Fromanger, Michals). Since one of Foucault’s major themes was the relation between visibility and discursivity, it is not surprising to ind that painting is a favored site for exploring variations in this conjuncture. Throughout his work, painting and the visual arts serve as emblems of the epistemes that characterize distinct epochs of thought. At the same time, Foucault’s engagement with contemporary art reveals his sense of its political signiicance and force. These themes coincide in Foucault’s continuing interest in how art forms can break with acquired archives, apparatuses, and practices. In (mostly implicit) contrast with romantic concepts of genius (as in Kant, or more generally in the time of “man and his doubles”), Foucault attempted to analyze and articulate the processes of rupture and transformation that mark speciic changes in what is called style. Dominant trends in art history either sought to trace relatively continuous developments (following a Hegelian lineage) or operated with sets of categories derived from Geistesgeschichte such as Heinrich
Wölllin’s linear and painterly modes. Philosophical aesthetics (as Derrida observes) has systematically (from Plato to Heidegger) given premier status to the linguistic arts of poetry and literature. Both of those ways of understanding visual art are put into question by Foucault’s engagement with painting and photography.
In The History of Madness, Foucault articulates a distinction between visibility and discursivity in sixteenth-century constructions of madness. He contrasted writers like Erasmus and Sebastian Brant, who treated madness as an occasion for instruction and moral satire, with painters like Breughel, Bosch, and Grünewald,
327
328 / Gary Shapiro
who displayed madness as much more dangerous, eruptive, and invasive than the literary parallels they occasionally followed. This contrast leads to a relection on a “cleavage” ( partage) that emerged then between literary and visual art. If texts and images had once been mutually illustrative, now “painting was beginning the long process of experimentation that would take it ever further from language, regardless of the supericial identity of a theme. Language and igure are beginning to take two different directions” (EHM, 16). Whereas Foucault’s emphasis in The History of Madness involves the presentation of madness, he soon expanded his observation in a review of books by the art historian Erwin Panofsky. He praises Panofsky for mapping the complexity of the igurative and discursive: “chiasm, isomorphism, transformation, translation, in a word, all of the festoon [ feston] of the visible and sayable that characterize a culture in a moment of its history” (FDE1, 621). In the case of painters like Bosch, the partage of discourse and igure meant that the power of the image was “no longer to teach but to fascinate,” a power that brings it close to the dream. Earlier, Foucault had developed a highly visual account of dreaming, taking issue with Freud’s more linguistic analysis (EDE). He describes sixteenth-century painting as “opening the way for a symbolism more often associated with the world of dreams”; that is, creating a public or collective dream (EHM, 17).
Just as The Order of Things is a deinitive break with phenomenology, which is trapped in the oscillations of “man and his doubles,” so its opening essay on Las Meninas can be read as a critical alternative to the concept of painting in phenomenologists like Merleau-Ponty (whose philosophy of ambiguity is seen as a typical product of the analytic of initude). Merleau-Ponty had taken modern painting, especially as it took shape in Cézanne, to be a form of phenomenological inquiry: it suspends the natural attitude in order to explore forms of intentionality through which the visible world takes shape for consciousness. Foucault reads Las Meninas archaeologically rather than phenomenologically. Eschewing anything like the psychological account Merleau-Ponty offers of Cézanne’s continuous effort to discover the roots of perception, Foucault articulates the principles by which “classical” painting constructs its representations. As he suggests in The Archaeology of Knowledge, he takes it to be possible to delineate the rules, sequences, and transformations that a certain form of painting assumes, embodies, and occasionally disrupts or transforms (EAK, 193–194). He therefore describes Las Meninas in terms of its deploying multiple strategies of representation typical of the classical age, including linear perspective and the simulation of “natural” light within the image. Moreover, this remarkable painting pushes the limits of representation by explicitly thematizing the roles of artist, model, and spectator involved in the classical model. Foucault takes note of the painting’s apparent attempt to inventory all elements and aspects of representation (the core of the classical episteme). In viewing the painting, we must successively imagine the place in front of the picture as occupied by the royal models, the artist, or the spectator (ourselves). No one of these representative functions
Painting (and Photography) / 329
can claim priority, so the position outside the painting, which seems to promise us a deinitive understanding, is instead the scene of an endless oscillation among these constituents of representation. Foucault inally reads this indeterminate oscillation as the sign of an absence marking our modern distance from classical painting and indeed from the entire practice of classical representation. The three oscillating igures could be regarded as analogues of the three epistemes analyzed in The Order of Things: the sovereign models would personify that of resemblance, the painter that of classical representation, and the spectator that of man, the inite being tasked with comprehending his own initude (Tanke 2010, 33–40). Foucault’s reading of the painting reveals “an essential void: the necessary disappearance of that which is its foundation – of the person it resembles and the person in whose eyes it is only a resemblance” (EOT, 16). The absent igure is “man,” who will be delineated more fully as an “empirical-transcendental doublet,” a being whose task is to discover the conditions of his own initude; Foucault will argue that this is an impossible and endless task, one that could be abandoned if, as seems to be happening, the igure of man is erased “like a face drawn in sand at the edge of the sea” (EOT, 386–387).
Foucault’s essay is both an instance of ekphrasis, the verbal description of a visual work of art, and a relection on that genre. Given his insistence on the distinction between visibility and discursivity, as well as their multiple forms of conjunction, it should not be surprising that Foucault is sensitive to the question of how his verbal analysis is related to the painting as a visual image. At the same time that the text of the essay is disclosing an absence in the painting, that of man, the writing marks its own distance from the image. The essay itself is divided into two numbered parts. The irst proceeds by rigorously excluding any discussion of the historical identities of the igures in the painting or of art-historical context. This has the effect of defamiliarizing the work and forcing us to concentrate on its play of representation, a focus intensiied by Foucault enlisting us within a “we,” a community of observers under the guidance of a connoisseur. The second section of the essay takes a new turn by asking whether it is now time to name the persons in the image (Velazquez, the royal igures, and their entourage). Warning that this could lead to a reductive approach, Foucault insists that “the relation of language to painting is an ininite relation. It is not that words are imperfect, or that, when confronted by the visible, they prove insuperably inadequate. Neither can be reduced to the other’s terms: it is in vain that we say what we see; what we see never resides in what we say.” This relation, Foucault maintains, should be kept open, so as to “treat their incompatibility as a starting-point for speech instead of an obstacle to be avoided” (EOT, 9). At the same time, there is no explicit relection on the feigned community of “we” who follow the path of Foucault’s ekphrasis. Yet such relection becomes unavoidable much later in the text, as Foucault introduces the analysis of “Man and His Doubles” by reiterating the absence implied by the painting. It is as if man, “enslaved sovereign, observed spectator,” appears “in that vacant space towards which Velazquez’s whole
330 / Gary Shapiro
painting was directed” (EOT, 312). We readers realize that in order to discover the absence of man in the painting, we ourselves have to assume the initially unnamed position of “enslaved sovereign, observed spectator.” Yet once such a position has been named, it becomes possible to take our distance from it and ask, as Foucault does, whether this position is inevitable or rather one that arose in a speciic context and is subject to disappearance.
Foucault saw Manet as a painter who rethought the position of the viewer. Soon after publishing The Order of Things, Foucault took up temporary residence in Tunisia, where he lectured on quattrocento painting and Manet. His projected book on Manet (Le noir et les couleurs) was apparently never completed; however, a transcript of one lecture, along with some passages in “Fantasia of the Library,” indicate how Foucault understood a body of work that overturned the conventions of representational painting (EMP). Just as Flaubert produced a self-conscious literature of the library and the archive in a novel like The Temptation of Saint Anthony
(itself inspired by a painting, as Foucault notes), Manet took the museum and its conditions of display as a frame to be altered and manipulated. Manet, in this analysis, rejected certain ictions of the art of his predecessors. These involved the idea that the canvas was a virtual window on a three-dimensional segment of an actual or possible world, a supposition enabled by the picture’s use of linear perspective and the simulation of lighting internal to the painting. Drawing on Foucault’s later, more explicit development of the concepts of apparatus and diagram (as in Discipline and Punish), we can articulate the lines of Manet’s innovations. Bentham’s Panopticon realized a diagram of visibility: each individual cell of the prison was observable from a central observation tower, thus encouraging prisoners to assume that they could be the subjects of surveillance at any moment and so discipline themselves to meet the behavioral expectations of the prison system. The museum, which rose and lourished in the nineteenth century, produced another viewing apparatus in which each canvas presented itself to the observer as a window opening onto an imagined scene. Manet effectively transformed this arrangement by creating paintings that insisted on their two-dimensionality and did not simulate an internal source of lighting. One no longer had the experience of looking through a window but of engaging with a lat canvas on the wall. By emphasizing rectangular elements and deliberately distorting perspectival expectations (as in The Bar at the Folies Bergère),
Manet established a new diagram of viewing. Even the looks of the igures within the painting contribute to unsettling the experience of viewing, either by seeming to stare directly at the viewer (as in the scandalous Olympia), looking at the invisible (The Gare Saint-Lazare), or forming a set of disconnected gazes (The Balcony, with its disturbing trio).
“Force of Flight,” an essay on the painter Paul Rebeyrolle, extends the analysis of visual framing explored in the lecture on Manet, making more explicit the possibilities of resistance and rebellion latent in the account of the museum and its
Painting (and Photography) / 331
diagrams of vision. The subject of Foucault’s essay is a series of paintings entitled Dogs, each depicting a dog in captivity, in various stages of coninement, struggle, suffering, or escape. Constructed as collages with wire lattices and wooden frames, the works reinforce the materiality of the situations represented. Foucault notes that the conditions of display also emphasize the sense of constriction: “Here you are held fast by ten pictures, that circle a room in which all the windows have been carefully closed. In prison, in your turn, like the dogs that you see standing on their hind legs and butting up against the grillwork?” Who are we who create, gaze at, or turn our eyes away from prisons? Foucault was involved at this time in political activity focused on French prison conditions; he takes Rebeyrolle’s series as concerned with “the prison ... a place where forces arise and show themelves, a place where history takes shape, and whence time arises” (FDE2, 401). The featureless windows forming the background of the Dogs series are only illusory exits. Leaving through the window would leave the apparatus of coninement intact. Rather, “in human struggles, nothing great ever passes by way of the windows, but everything, always, by the triumphant crumbling [l’effrondrement] of the walls” (FDE2, 403). Here, as in his account of Manet, Foucault shows how the apparatus of painting can deploy conventions of representation against themselves, but now the political potential of this relexive move and its questioning of the viewer has become more evident.
In This Is not a Pipe, Foucault traces another route painting has taken in the wake of Manet’s undoing of representation. Foucault claims that the movement of twentieth-century abstraction challenged two constitutive principles of Western painting that ruled since the ifteenth century: (1) rigorous separation of linguistic and visual signs, and (2) the assumption that resemblance implies afirmation, or that painting refers to a world external to itself (ENP, 32). Klee is credited with breaking down the irst of these protocols by introducing words, letters, and signs (e.g., arrows) as compositional elements into paintings that retain a representational aspect (elsewhere Foucault suggests that Klee has an emblematic relation to his time analogous to that Velazquez had to his [FDE1, 544]). Kandinsky broke with the second protocol by irst introducing nonrepresentative “things” into his paintings that were “neither more nor less objects than the church, the bridge, or the knight with his bow,” and then producing paintings consisting solely of shapes, colors, and their relations (ENP, 34–35).
Foucault sees Magritte as intensifying the assault on representation begun by Klee and Kandinsky. Foucault does this by challenging both principles: separation and afirmation. Yet Magritte accomplishes this not through abstraction but by pushing the techniques of representation to their limits. Impossible objects and proportions, perspectival distortions, or incoherent but “realistic” scenes are produced with exaggerated representational clarity. Words, sentences, inscriptions, and titles play constitutive roles in Magritte’s canvases. So far, Foucault suggests, a painting like Les deux mystéres (Ceci n’est pas une pipe) can be compared to a calligram, a diagrammatic
332 / Gary Shapiro
representation formed by written words and letters. Yet to speak more carefully, he continues, we must describe the work as an “unraveled calligram” in which neither the visual nor discursive order becomes dominant; the painting sets up an unlimited interplay of the two modes.
While Foucault highlights Magritte’s rejection of the afirmative sense of the image (the implicit claim to resemble something external to itself), he sees another afirmation emerging in his work. Magritte’s paintings afirm the simulacrum or phantasm, the image without an original, and therefore proliferating without limit. Freed from the constraints of resemblance, the image loats free, like the “pipe” in the famous painting. Here Foucault draws on Deleuze’s transvaluation of the simulacrum (as in The Logic of Sense) that Plato had attempted to marginalize. Other partners in this conversation are Klossowski, whose rethinking of the simulacrum Foucault explored in “The Prose of Actaeon,” and Nietzsche, the thinker of eternal recurrence. “Seven Seals of Afirmation,” the title of the concluding section of This Is not a Pipe, paraphrases that of “The Seven Seals,” a song that Nietzsche’s
Zarathustra sings to celebrate the thought of recurrence. That thought can be understood as a radical intensiication of multiplicity, where each moment has an ininite depth. That Nietzsche calls these moments Augenblicke, “twinklings of the eye” or “momentary glances,” enables Foucault to play on the idea of a multiplicity of the visual image, a theme to which he alludes in his essay on Flaubert (ELCP, 101). Foucault also detected the ininitely multiple or “eternal phantasm” in Pop Art, which he invokes in the last line of This Is not a Pipe (“Campbell, Campbell, Campbell, Campbell”) and in his brief ekphrasis of Andy Warhol’s images of repetition in “Theatrum Philosophicum.” Arising from those images “that refer to each other to eternity” he discovers that “the striped form of the event tears through the darkness, and the eternal phantasm informs that soup can, that singular and depthless face” (ELCP, 189).
Other possibilities of repetition and fantasy are enabled by photography; these are in turn repositionings of the viewing subject. Foucault followed transformations in the apparatus of the visual arts by investigating several such adaptations and mutations. He provides a brief genealogy in “Photogenic Painting,” where he recalls the freedom of experimentation in early photography’s many ways of altering and recording the image, before the emergence of a canonical form of photographic art in the early twentieth century. Foucault’s focus in this essay is the art of Gérard Fromanger, who produces images by painting over projected photographic images of street scenes and public life. For Foucault, this technique mobilizes the image: “Fromanger’s paintings do not capture images: they do not ix them, they pass them on” (EPGP, 95). Here painting abandons any aspiration to ixity and solidity, embodying in its form the nomadic transitivity of contemporary life: “this is the autonomous transhumance of the image ... it agrees to become a thoroughfare,
Painting (and Photography) / 333
an ininite transition, a busy and crowded painting” (EPGP, 102). Here Foucault introduces the theme of territoriality into his account of art.
In “Thought and Emotion” (1982), Foucault discussed the work of the American photographer Duane Michals (FDE4, 243–250). Emphasizing the dreamlike quality of Michals’s images and photographic narratives, Foucault returns, in a sense, to themes from his early exploration of the visual, the 1954 essay “Dream and Existence.” Michals experiments with photography in a different direction than Fromanger. Whereas Fromanger took painting into the street through photography, Michals captures and provokes fragile moments of “thought-emotion.” Foucault endorses Michals’s observation that photography has an advantage in provoking thoughts about the unseen, spectral, and dreamlike because it is initially taken to be a more realistic medium than painting. The text is contemporary with Foucault’s later writings and lectures on the aesthetics of existence and the process of subjectivization. In The Care of the Self, Foucault notes that the physicians and writers on love testify to the power of visual images ( phantasiai) whether remembered, dreamed, or seen (EHS3, 136–139). Michals, as a gay man whose work alters the possibilities of photography while exploring varieties of sexuality, gender, and fantasy, becomes an exemplar of the self-experimenting artist and the practitioner of an aesthetics of existence.
Gary Shapiro
See Also
Literature
Madness
The Visible
Maurice Merleau-Ponty
Suggested Reading
Deleuze, Gilles. 1988. Foucault, trans. Seán Hand. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Shapiro, Gary. 2003. Archaeologies of Vision: Foucault and Nietzsche on Seeing and Saying. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Tanke, Joseph. 2010. Foucault’s Philosophy of Art: A Genealogy of Modernity. New York:
Continuum.