Добавил:
Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:

The_Cambridge_Foucault_Lexicon

.pdf
Скачиваний:
61
Добавлен:
29.10.2019
Размер:
8.36 Mб
Скачать

124 / Richard A. Lynch

text’s work is an analysis of discourse, in particular sexual discourse: “Yet when one looks back over these last three centuries with their continual transformations, ...

around and apropos of sex, one sees a veritable discursive explosion” (EHS1, 17); “[t]here was a steady proliferation of discourses concerned with sex – speciic discourses, different from one another both by their form and by their object: a discursive ferment that gathered momentum from the eighteenth century onward” (EHS1, 18). Nevertheless, discourse is being reframed: “But more important was the multiplication of discourses concerning sex in the ield of exercise of power itself” (ibid.). It is now one element within a larger framework deined by the operation of power relations, and discourses are juxtaposed against, on a par with, other institutions in this new framework. (Indeed, Part IV of The History of Sexuality is one of

Foucault’s most sustained, explicit elaborations of his new framing theory of power relations.) And so sexuality “appears rather as an especially dense transfer point for relations of power” (EHS1, 103). The way power relations permeate sexual discourse is illustrated, for example, by repression and resistance to it. It has been argued that we repress our sexuality, and so we can free ourselves from repression by engaging in more open discourses about sexuality. On the contrary, Foucault argues, these attempts at resistance merely serve to reduplicate and multiply the already existing discourses about sexuality – discourses that facilitate control and normalization of sexuality – and so attempts to break out from repression serve merely to play into and reinforce the normalization of sexuality that we were seeking to escape. Thus:

The doubts I would like to oppose to the repressive hypothesis are aimed less at showing it to be mistaken than at putting it back within a general economy of discourses on sex in modern societies since the seventeenth century.... The object, in short, is to deine the regime of power-knowledge-pleasure that sustains the discourse on human sexuality in our part of the world. (EHS1, 11)

Discourses are now sustained by a regime of power/knowledge relations.

The example of “resistance to repression” serving to reinforce, not escape, sexual normalization, as well as Foucault’s commitment to self-critique as illustrated by the evolving signiication and signiicance of “discourse,” have important implications for Foucault’s ethical thinking. Both illustrate a need for tentative, provisional judgments and a willingness to constantly reconsider and revise what we accept as knowledge. As Foucault put this in a 1983 interview, “My point is not that everything is bad, but that everything is dangerous. If everything is dangerous, then we always have something to do” (EEW1, 256).

One of the most salient features of all of Foucault’s work is its relentlessly selfcritical character. At each stage of his thinking, he reexamines, criticizes, and attempts to revise and correct earlier ideas. The evolution of “discourse” illustrates this character. In The Archaeology of Knowledge it becomes the organizing and framing concept

DISCOURSE / 125

that allows Foucault to revise and correct his earlier studies. By volume one of The History of Sexuality, it, too, has been revised, corrected, and resituated; “discourse” is no longer the linchpin for a theoretical framework but rather an important set of elements within a different conceptual framework articulated around power/knowledge relations. Indeed, this essential revisability is a key feature internal to Foucault’s understanding of discourse itself and discursive formations – hence his emphasis on historical discontinuities in The Archaeology of Knowledge. And this essential revisability underscores the provisional character not only of Foucault’s (and our) claims to knowledge but his (and our) ethical claims, too. The changing role of “discourse” in fact reveals an important constant of Foucault’s thought, as well as a tool or lesson for the rest of us.

Richard A. Lynch

See Also

Archaeology

Language

Practice

Statement

Structuralism

Suggested Reading

Dreyfus, Hubert L., and Paul Rabinow. 1983. Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

23

DISPOSITIF (APPARATUS)

Foucault’s philosophy is often presented as an analysis of concrete “dispositifs” or apparatuses. But what is an apparatus? First of all, it is a skein, a multilinear whole. It is composed of lines of different natures. The lines in the apparatus do not encircle or surround systems that are each homogeneous in

themselves, the object, the subject, language, and so on, but follow directions, trace processes that are always out of balance, that sometimes move closer together and sometimes further away. Each line is broken, subject to changes in direction, bifurcating and forked, and subjected to derivatives. Visible objects, articulable statements, forces in use, and subjects in position are like vectors or tensors. Thus the three main instances Foucault successively distinguishes – Knowledge, Power, and Subjectivity – by no means have contours that are deined once and for all but are chains of variables that are torn from each other. Foucault always inds a new dimension or a new line in a crisis. Great thinkers are somewhat seismic; they do not evolve but proceed by crises or quakes. Thinking in terms of moving lines was Herman Melville’s operation: ishing lines, dividing lines, dangerous, even deadly, lines. There are lines of sedimentation, Foucault says, but also lines of “issure” and “fracture.” Untangling the lines of an apparatus means, in each case, preparing a map, a cartography, a survey of unexplored lands – what he calls “ield work.” One has to be positioned on the lines themselves, and these lines do not merely compose an apparatus but pass through it and carry it north to south, east to west, or diagonally.

The irst two dimensions of an apparatus, or the ones Foucault irst extracts, are the curves of visibility and the curves of enunciation. Because apparatuses are like Raymond Roussel’s machines, which Foucault also analyzed, they are machines that make one see and talk. Visibility does not refer to a general light that would illuminate preexisting objects but rather is made up of lines of light that form variable igures inseparable from an apparatus. Each apparatus has its regimen of light, the way it falls, softens, and spreads, distributing the visible and the invisible, generating

126

Dispositif (APPARATUS) / 127

or eliminating an object, which cannot exist without it. This is true not only of painting but of architecture as well: the “prison apparatus” as an optical machine for seeing without being seen. If there is a historicity of apparatuses, it is the historicity of regimes of light but also regimes of statements. Statements in turn refer to lines of enunciation where the differential positions of the elements of a statement are distributed. And the curves themselves are statements because enunciations are curves that distribute variables and a science at a given moment, or a literary genre, state of laws, or social movement is precisely deined by the regimes of statements they engender. They are neither subjects nor objects but regimes that must be deined for the visible and the utterable with their derivations, transformations, and mutations. In each apparatus, the lines cross thresholds that make them either aesthetic, scientiic, political, or whatever.

Third, an apparatus contains lines of force. One might say that they move from one single point to another on the previous lines. In a way, they “rectify” the previous curves, draw tangents, surround the paths from one line to another, operate to and fro from seeing to speaking and vice versa, acting like arrows that constantly mix words and things without ceasing to carry out their battles. A line of force is produced “in every relationship between one point and another” and moves through every place in an apparatus. Invisible and unspeakable, this line is closely combined with the other but can be untangled. Foucault pulls this line and inds its trajectory in Roussel, Brisset, and the painters Magritte and Rebeyrolle. It is the “dimension of power” and power is the third dimension of space, interior to the apparatus and variable with the apparatuses. Like power, it is composed with knowledge.

And inally, Foucault discovered lines of subjectiication. This new dimension has already given rise to so much misunderstanding that it is hard to specify its conditions. More than any other, this discovery came from a crisis in Foucault’s thought, as if he needed to rework the map of apparatuses, ind a new orientation for them to prevent them from closing up behind impenetrable lines of force imposing deinitive contours. Leibniz expressed in exemplary fashion this state of crisis that restarts thought when it seems that everything is almost resolved: you think you have reached shore but are cast back out to sea. And as for Foucault, he sensed that the apparatuses he analyzed could not be circumscribed by an enveloping line without other vectors passing above or below: “crossing the line,” he said, like “going to the other side” (EEW3, 161)? This going beyond the line of force is what happens when it bends back, starts meandering, goes underground or rather when force, instead of entering into a linear relationship with another force, turns back on itself, acts on itself or affects itself. This dimension of the Self is not a preexisting determination that can be found ready-made. Here again, a line of subjectiication is a process, a production of subjectivity in an apparatus: it must be made to the extent that the apparatus allows it or makes it possible. It is a line of light. It escapes the previous lines; it escapes from them. The Self is not knowledge or power. It is process

128 / Gilles Deleuze

of individuation that affects groups or people and eludes both established lines of force and constituted knowledge. It is a kind of surplus value. Not every apparatus necessarily has it.

Foucault designates the apparatus of the Athenian city-state as the irst place where a subjectiication was created. According to his original deinition, the citystate invents a line of forces that moves through the rivalry between free men. From this line on which a free man can have command over others, a very different line separates itself according to which the one who commands free men must also be master of himself. These optional rules for self-mastery constitute an autonomous subjectiication, even if it is later called on to furnish new knowledge and inspire new powers. One might wonder whether lines of subjectiication are the extreme edge of an apparatus and whether they trace the passage from one apparatus to another. In this sense, they would prepare “lines of fracture.”And lines of subjectiication have no more of a general formula than other lines. Cruelly interrupted, Foucault’s research was going to show that processes of subjectiication eventually took on modes other than the Greek mode, for example in Christian apparatuses and modern societies. Couldn’t we cite apparatuses where subjectiication no longer goes through aristocratic life or the aestheticized existence of free men but through the marginalized existence of the “excluded”? The sinologist Tokei explains how freed slaves in a way lost their social status and found themselves relegated to an isolated, plaintive, elegiac existence from which they had to draw new forms of power and knowledge (Sárkány, Hann, and Skalník 2005). The study of variations in the processes of subjectiication seems to be one of the tasks Foucault left those who came after him. I believe this research will be extremely fruitful, and the current endeavors toward a history of private life only partially overlap it. Sometimes the ones subjectivized are the nobles, the ones who say “we are the good” according to Nietzsche. But under other conditions, the excluded, the bad, the sinners, or the hermits, monastic communities, or heretics, are subjectivized: an entire typology of subjective formations in changing apparatuses. And with these apparatuses we have combinations to be untangled everywhere: productions of subjectivity escaping the powers and knowledge of one apparatus to reinvest themselves in another through other forms to be created.

Apparatuses are therefore composed of lines of visibility, enunciation, lines of force, lines of subjectiication, lines of cracking, breaking, and ruptures that all intertwine and mix together and where some augment the others or elicit others through variations and even mutations of the assemblage. Two important consequences ensue for a philosophy of apparatuses. The irst is the repudiation of universals. A universal explains nothing; it, on the other hand, must be explained. All of the lines are lines of variation that do not even have constant coordinates. The One, the Whole, the True, the object, and the subject are not universals but singular processes of uniication, totalization, veriication, objectiication, and subjectiication immanent to an apparatus. Each apparatus is therefore a multiplicity where certain processes in

Dispositif (APPARATUS) / 129

becoming are operative and are distinct from those operating in another apparatus. This is how Foucault’s philosophy is a pragmatism, a functionalism, a positivism, and a pluralism. Reason may cause the greatest problem because processes of rationalization can operate on segments or regions of all the lines discussed so far. Foucault pays homage to Nietzsche for a historicity of reason. And he notes all of the importance of epistemological research on the various forms of rationality in knowledge (Koyré, Bachelard, Canguilhem) and of sociopolitical research into the modes of rationality in power (Max Weber). Maybe he kept the third line for himself, the study of types “reasonable” in potential subjects. But he refused essentially to identify these processes in a reason par excellence. He rejected any restoration of universals of relection, communication, or consensus. In this sense, one could say that his relationship with the Frankfurt School and the successors to this school consists of a long series of misunderstandings for which he is not responsible. And no more than there are universals of a founding subject or exemplary reason that would allow for judgment of apparatuses, there are not universals of the disaster of reason being alienated or collapsing once and for all. As Foucault told Gérard Rauler, there is not one bifurcation of reason; it constantly bifurcates, there are as many bifurcations and branches as instaurations, as many collapses as constructions following the cuts carried out by the apparatuses and “there is no meaning to the statement that reason is a long story that is over now” (EEW2, 433–458). From this point of view, the objection raised with Foucault regarding knowing how to assess the relative value of an apparatus if no transcendental values can be called on as universal coordinates is a question that could lead us backward and lose its meaning itself. Should one say that all apparatuses are equal (nihilism)? Thinkers like Spinoza and Nietzsche showed long ago that modes of existence had to be weighed according to immanent criteria, according to their content in “possibilities,” freedom, and creativity, with no call to transcendental values. Foucault even alluded to “aesthetic” criteria, understood as life criteria, that substitute an immanent evaluation for a transcendental judgment every time. When we read Foucault’s last books, we must do our best to understand the program he is offering his readers. An intrinsic aesthetics of modes of existence as the inal dimension of apparatuses?

The second result of a philosophy of apparatuses is a change in orientation, turning away from the eternal to apprehend the new. The new is not supposed to designate fashion but on the contrary the variable creativity for the apparatuses: in conformance with the question that began to appear in the twentieth century of how the production of something new in the world is possible. It is true that, within his entire theory of enunciation, Foucault explicitly rejected the “originality” of a statement as criterion that is hardly pertinent, that is hardly interesting. He only wants to consider the “regularity” of statements. But what he meant by regularity was the slope of the curve passing through the singular points or the differential values of the group of statements. (He also deined the relationship of forces as distributions

130 / Gilles Deleuze

of singularities in a social ield.) By rejecting the originality of statements, he meant that the potential contradiction of two statements is not enough to distinguish them or to indicate the newness of one in relation to the other. What counts is the newness of the regime of enunciation itself in that it can include contradictory statements. For example, we could ask what regime of statements appeared with the French Revolution or the Russian Revolution: it is the newness of the regime that counts and not the originality of the statement. Each apparatus is thus deined by its content of newness and creativity, which at the same time indicates its ability to transform itself or even to break for the sake of an apparatus of the future unless, on the contrary, it transforms itself for the sake of an increase of force to the hardest, most rigid or solid lines. Since they escape the dimension of knowledge and power, lines of subjectiication seem particularly apt to trace paths of creation, which are constantly aborted but also taken up again and modiied until the old apparatus breaks. Foucault’s as yet unpublished studies on the various Christian processes will certainly open many directions in this regard. One should not believe, however, that the production of subjectivity is left only to religion; antireligious struggles are also creative, just as the regimes of light, enunciation, and domination move through very diverse domains. Modern subjectiications resemble the Greek subjectiications no more than they resemble the Christian ones; the same is true of light, statements, and powers.

We belong to these apparatuses and act in them. The newness of an apparatus in relation to those preceding it is what we call its actuality, our actuality. The new is the actual. The actual is not what we are but rather what we become, what are in the process of becoming, in other words the Other, our becoming-other. In every apparatus, we have to distinguish between what we are (what we already no longer are) and what we are becoming: the portion that is history, the portion that is actual. History is the archive, the design of what we are and cease being, whereas the actual is the sketch of what we are becoming. Thus history or the archive is what still separates us from ourselves, whereas the actual is this Other with which we already coincide. Some have thought that Foucault was painting the portrait of modern societies as disciplinary apparatuses in opposition to the old apparatuses of sovereignty. This is not the case: the disciplines Foucault described are the history of what are slowly ceasing to be and our actuality is taking shape within arrangements of open and constant control that are very different from the recent closed disciplines. Foucault agrees with Burroughs, who announced that our future would be more controlled than disciplined. The question is not which is worse, because we also call on productions of subjectivity capable of resisting this new domination and that are very different from the ones used in the past against the disciplines. A new light, new statements, new power, new forms of subjectiication? In every apparatus, we must untangle the lines of the recent past from the lines of the near future: the archive from the actual, the portion of history and the portion of becoming, the portion of

Dispositif (APPARATUS) / 131

analysis and the portion of diagnosis. If Foucault is a great philosopher, it is because he used history for something else: as Nietzsche said, to act against time and thus to act on time in favor, I hope, of a time to come. What Foucault saw as the actual or the new was what Nietzsche called the untimely, the “non-actual,” the becoming that splits away from history, the diagnosis that relays analysis on different paths, not predicting, but being attentive to the unknown knocking at the door. Nothing reveals this better than a fundamental passage from The Archaeology of Knowledge that applies to all his work:

Analysis of the archive therefore includes a privileged area: it is both close to us and different from our actuality. It is the edge of time that surrounds our present, overlooks it and points to our present in its alterity; the archive is what, outside of us, delimits us. The description of the archive unfolds its possibilities (and the mastery of its possibilities) starting with discourses that have just stopped being ours; its threshold of existence begins with the break that separates us from what we can no longer say and what falls outside our discursive practices; it begins with the outside of our own language; its place is the distance from our own discursive practices. In this sense it can serve as our diagnosis. Not because it would allow us to draw a portrait of our distinctive traits and sketch out in advance the aspect we will have in the future. But it releases us from our continuities; it dissipates the temporal identity where we like to look at ourselves to avoid the ruptures of history; it breaks the thread of transcendental teleologies; and while anthropological thought would examine the being of humans or their subjectivity, it exposes the other, the outside. Diagnosis in this sense does not establish the recognition of our identity through the play of distinctions. It establishes that we are difference, that our reason is the difference between discourses, our history the difference between times, our self the difference between masks. (EAK, 130–131)

The different lines of an apparatus are divided into two groups: lines of stratiication or sedimentation and lines of actualization or creativity. The inal result of this method concerns Foucault’s entire work. In most of his books, he determines a speciic archive with extremely new historical means, the general hospital in the seventeenth century, the clinic in the eighteenth century, the prison in the nineteenth century, subjectivity in ancient Greece and then in Christianity. But that is only half of his task. Out of a concern for rigor, because of a will not to mix everything together, because he has conidence in his readers, Foucault does not formulate the other half. He only formulates it explicitly in the interviews given alongside the publication of his major works: What are madness, prison, and sexuality today? What new modes of subjectiication do we see appearing today that are certainly not Greek or Christian? This last question haunted Foucault until the end (we who are no

132 / Gilles Deleuze

longer Greek or even Christian). Foucault attached so much importance to his interviews in France and even more so abroad not because he liked interviews but because in them he traced lines of actualization that required a mode of expression other than the assimilable lines in his major books. The interviews are diagnoses. It is as in Nietzsche, whose works are dificult to read without the Nachlass that is contemporary to each. Foucault’s complete works, as Defert and Ewald imagine them, cannot separate the books that have left such an impression on us from the interviews that lead us toward a future, toward a becoming: the strata and the actualities.

Gilles Deleuze

See Also

Actuality

Statement

Subjectiication

Friedrich Nietzsche

Suggested Reading

Deleuze, Gilles. 1988. Foucault, trans. Seán Hand. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota

Press.

Sárkány, Mikhály, Chris M. Hann, and Peter Skalník, eds. 2005. Studying Peoples in the People’s Democracies: Socialist Era Anthropology in East-Central Europe. Münster: Lit

Verlag, pp. 98–99.

24

THE DOUBLE

Foucault’s discussion of the double in the ninth chapter of The Order of Things contains one of the most forceful critiques of phenomenology to appear in his early work. The igure of “the double” is invoked here to illustrate a

problem posed to phenomenology by virtue of the fact that (1) phenomenology as a method aims at the elaboration of the transcendental conditions of human experience, and (2) that phenomenology situates this examination of the transcendental in the empirical reality of man. The problem that results is one of circularity: the ground of phenomenological inquiry is constantly shifting, such that the subject is implicated in a kind of shadow dance. The effects of the Foucauldian rendering of the modern subject are multiple; Foucault’s analysis of the double bears consequences for the possibility of a modern ethics and ultimately leads him to forecast the “death of man.”

To speak of “the double,” however, is misleading, since there are three doubles that Foucault addresses in The Order of Things, each of which marks a paradox that proves troublesome for phenomenology. The three “doubles of man” are the empirical and the transcendental, the cogito and the unthought, and the retreat and return of the origin. The irst of these, the doublet of the empirical and the transcendental, refers to the fact that man is at once an empirically determined being and a transcendental subject. Man is a inite existent in the world, subject to the laws of natural science, even as he is the transcendental grounds of these very laws: “he is a being such that knowledge will be attained in him of what renders all knowledge possible” (EOT, 318). A paradox results. The transcendental status of phenomenological investigation is undermined by the fact that man is not only the transcendental grounds of the empirical sciences but also their proper object. For this reason, the subject’s knowledge of that world can never be clear or entire, as it inds itself implicated in the appearance of the world in ways that obscure certain kinds of knowledge even as others emerge. This tension grounds Foucault’s exploration of the “analytic

133