
Ethics in Practice
.pdfSexual and Racial Discrimination
prejudice. Intrinsic racism may be as irrationally held as any other view, but it does not have to be directed against anyone.
So far as theory is concerned I believe racialism to be false: since theoretical racism of both kinds presupposes racialism, I could not logically support racism of either variety. But even if racialism were true, both forms of theoretical racism would be incorrect. Extrinsic racism is false because the genes that account for the gross morphological differences that underlie our standard racial categories are not linked to those genes that determine, to whatever degree such matters are determined genetically, our moral and intellectual characters. Intrinsic racism is mistaken because it breaches the Kantian imperative to make moral distinctions only on morally relevant grounds - granted that there is no reason to believe that race, in se, is morally relevant, and also no reason to suppose that races are like families in providing a sphere of ethical life that legitimately escapes the demands of a universalizing morality.
Notes
Bernard Lewis, Semites and Anti-Semites (New
York: Norton, 1986).
2I shall be using the words "racism" and "racialism" with the meanings I stipulate: in some dialects of English they are synonyms, and in most dialects their definition is less than precise. For discussion of recent biological evidence see M. Nei and A. K. Roychoudhury, "Genetic Relationship and Evolution of Human Races," Evolutionary Biology, vol. 14 (New York: Plenum, 1983), pp. 1-59; for useful background see also M. Nei and A. K. Roychoudhury, "Gene Differences between Caucasian, Negro, and Japanese Populations," Science 177 (August 1972); 43+-5.
3See my "The Uncompleted Argument: Du Bois and the Illusion of Race," Critical Inquiry 12 (Autumn 1985); reprinted in Henry Louis Gates (ed.), "Race," Writing, and Difference (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1986), pp. 21-37.
4This fact shows up most obviously in the assumption that adopted children intelligibly make claims against their natural siblings: natural parents are, of course, causally responsible for their child's existence and that could be the basis of moral
claims, without any sense that biological relatedness entailed rights or responsibilities. But no such basis exists for an interest in natural siblings; my sisters are not causally responsible for my existence. See "The Family Model," later in this essay.
5Obviously what evidence should appropriate~y change your beliefs is not independent of your social or historical situation. In mid-nineteenth- century America, in New England quite as much as in the heart of Dixie, the pervasiveness of the institutional support for the prevailing system of racist belief - the fact that it was reinforced by religion and state, and defended by people in the universities and colleges, who had the greatest cognitive authority - meant that it would have been appropriate to insist on a substantial body of evidence and argument before giving up assent to racist propositions. In California in the 1980s, of course, matters stand rather differently. To acknowledge this is not to admit to a cognitive relativism; rather, it is to hold that, at least in some domains, the fact that a belief is widely held - and especially by people in positions of cognitive authority - may be a good prima facie reason for believing it.
6Ideologies, as most theorists of ideology have admitted, standardly outlive the period in which they conform to the objective interests of the dominant group in a society; so even someone who thinks that the dominant group in our society no longer needs racism to buttress its position can see racism as the persisting ideology of an earlier phase of society. (I say "group" to keep the claim appropriately general; it seems to me a substantial further claim that the dominant group whose interests an ideology serves is always a class.) I have argued, however, in "The Conservation of 'Race,''' that racism continues to serve the interests of the ruling classes in the West; in Black American Literature Forum, 23 (Spring 1989), pp. 37-60.
7As I argued in "The Uncompleted Argument: Du Bois and the Illusion of Race." The reactive (or dialectical) character of this move explains why Sartre calls its manifestations in Negritude an "antiracist racism"; see "Orphee Noir," his preface to Senghor's Anthologie de la nouvelle poesie negre et malagache de languefranraise (Paris: PUF, 1948). Sartre believed, of course, that the synthesis of this dialectic would be transcendence of racism; and it was his view of it as a stage - the antithesis - in that process that allowed him to see it as a positive advance over the original "thesis"
|
|
|
|
RaCisms |
of European racism.! suspect that the reactive |
9 |
Christianity, Islam and the Negro Race (1887; |
||
character of antiracist racism accounts for the |
|
reprinted |
Edinburgh: |
Edinburgh University |
tolerance that is regularly extended to it in liberal |
|
Press, 1967), p. 197. |
|
|
circles; but this tolerance is surely hard to justify |
10 |
This is in part a reflection of an important asym- |
||
unless one shares Sartre's optimistic interpret- |
|
metry: loathing, unlike love, needs justifying; |
||
ation of it as a stage in a process that leads to |
|
and this, I would argue, is because loathing |
||
the end of all racisms. (And unless your view of |
|
usually leads to acts that are in se undesirable, |
||
this dialectic is deterministic, you should in any |
|
whereas love leads to acts that are largely in se |
||
case want to play an argumentative role in moving |
|
desirable - |
indeed, supererogatorily so. |
|
to this next stage.) |
II See my "Racism and |
Moral Pollution," Philo- |
||
For a similar Zionist response see Horace Kal- |
|
sophical Forum 18 (Winter-Spring 1986-7): 185- |
||
len's "The Ethics of Zionism," Maccabean, |
|
202. |
|
|
August 1906. |
12 |
Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Phil- |
||
8 Alexander Crummell, "The Race Problem in |
|
osophy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University |
||
America," in Brotz's Negro Social and Political |
|
Press, 1985), p. 12. I do not, as is obvious, |
||
Thought (New York: Basic Books, 1966), p. 184. |
|
share Williams's skepticism about morality. |
40
Anita M. Superson
I Introduction
By far the most pervasive form of discrimination against women is sexual harassment (SH). Women in every walk of life are subject to it, and I would venture to say, on a daily basis. Even though the law is changing to the benefit of victims of SH, the fact that SH is still so pervasive shows that there is too much tolerance of it, and that victims do not have sufficient legal recourse to be protected.
The main source for this problem is that the way SH is defined by various Titles and other sources does not adequately reflect the social nature of SH, or the harm it causes all women. As a result, SH comes to be defined in subjective ways. One upshot is that when subjective definitions infuse the case law on SH, the more subtle but equally harmful forms of SH do not get counted as SH and thus are not afforded legal protection....
IIThe Social Nature of Sexual Harassment
Sexual harassment, a form of sexism, is about domination, in particular, the domination of the group of men over the group of women. 1 Domination involves control or power which can be seen in the economic, political, and social spheres of society. Sexual harassment is not
simply an assertion of power, for power can be used in beneficial ways. The power men have over women has been wielded in ways that oppress women. The power expressed in SH is oppression, power used wrongly.
Sexual harassment is integrally related to sex roles. It reveals the belief that a person is to be relegated to certain roles on the basis of her sex, including not only women's being sex objects, but also their being caretakers, motherers, nurturers, sympathizers, etc. In general, the sex roles women are relegated to are associated with the body (v. mind) and emotions (v. reason).
When A sexually harasses B, the comment or behavior is really directed at the group of all women, not just a particular woman, a point often missed by the courts. After all, many derogatory behaviors are issued at women the harasser does not even know (e.g., scanning a stranger's body). Even when the harasser knows his victim, the behavior is directed at the particular woman because she happens to be "available" at the time, though its message is for all women. For instance, a catcall says not (merely) that the perpetrator likes a woman's body, but that he thinks women are at least primarily sex objects and he - because of the power he holds by being in the dominant group - gets to rate them according to how much pleasure they give him. The professor who refers to his female students as "chicks" makes a statement that
women are intellectually inferior to men as they can be likened to non-rational animals, perhaps even soft, cuddly ones that are to serve as the objects of (men's) pleasure. Physicians' using Playboy centerfolds in medical schools to "spice up their lectures" sends the message that women lack the competence to make it in a "man's world" and should perform the "softer tasks" associated with bearing and raising children. 2
These and other examples make it clear that SH is not about dislike for a certain person; instead, it expresses a person's beliefs about women as a group on the basis of their sex, namely, that they are primarily emotional and bodily beings. Some theorists - Catherine MacKinnon, John Hughes and Larry May - have recognized the social nature of SH. Hughes and May claim that women are a disadvantaged group because (1) they are a social group having a distinct identity and existence apart from their individual identities, (2) they occupy a subordinate position in American society, and (3) their political power is severely circumscribed.3 They continue:
Once it is established that women qualify for special disadvantaged group status, all practices tending to stigmatize women as a group, or which contribute to the maintenance of their subordinate social status, would become legally suspect.4
This last point, I believe, should be central to the definition of SH.
Because SH has as its target the group of all women, this group suffers harm as a result of the behavior. Indeed, when anyone woman is in any way sexually harassed, all women are harmed. The group harm SH causes is different from the harm suffered by particular women as individuals: it is often more vague in nature as it is not easily causally tied to any particular incident of harassment. The group harm has to do primarily with the fact that the behavior reflects and reinforces sexist attitudes that women are inferior to men and that they do and ought to occupy certain sex roles. For example, comments and behavior that relegate women to the role of sex objects reinforce the belief that
Sexual Harassment
women are sex objects and that they ought to occupy this sex role. Similarly, when a female professor's cogent comments at department colloquia are met with frowns and rolled eyes from her colleagues, this behavior reflects and reinforces the view that women are not fit to occupy positions men arrogate to themselves.
The harm women suffer as a group from any single instance of SH is significant. It takes many forms. A Kantian analysis would show what is wrong with being solely a sex object. Though there is nothing wrong with being a caretaker or nurturer, etc., per se, it is sexist - and so wrong - to assign such roles to women. In addition, it is wrong to assign a person to a role she may not want to occupy. Basically women are not allowed to decide for themselves which roles they are to occupy, but this gets decided for them, no matter what they do. Even if some women occupy important positions in society that men traditionally occupy, they are still viewed as being sex objects, caretakers, etc., since all women are thought to be more "bodily" and emotional than men. This is a denial of women's autonomy, and degrading to them. It also contributes to women's oppression. The belief that women must occupy certain sex roles is both a cause and an effect of their oppression. It is a cause because women are believed to be more suited for certain roles given their association with body and emotions. It is an effect because once they occupy these roles and are victims of oppression, the belief that they must occupy these sex roles is reinforced.
Women are harmed by SH in yet another way. The belief that they are sex objects, caretakers, etc., gets reflected in social and political practices in ways that are unfair to women. It has undoubtedly meant many lost opportunities that are readily available to men. Women are not likely to be hired for jobs that require them to act in ways other than the ways the sex roles dictate, and if they are, what is expected of them is different from what is expected of men. Mothers are not paid for their work, and caretakers are not paid well in comparison with people in jobs traditionally held by men. Lack of economic reward is paralleled by lack of respect and appreciation for those occupying
Sexual and Racial Discrimination
such roles. Certain rights granted men are likely not to be granted women (e.g., the right to bodily selfdetermination, and marriage rights).
Another harm SH causes all women is that the particular form sex stereotyping takes promotes two myths: (1) that male behavior is normally and naturally predatory, and (2) that females naturally (because they are taken to be primarily bodily and emotional) and even willingly acquiesce despite the appearance of protest. 5 Because the behavior perpetuated by these myths is taken to be normal, it is not seen as sexist, and in turn is not counted as SH.
The first myth is that men have stronger sexual desires than women, and harassment is just a natural venting of these desires which men are unable to control. The truth is, first, that women are socialized not to vent their sexual desires in the way men do, but this does not mean these desires are weaker or less prevalent. Masters and Johnson have "decisively established that women's sexual requirements are no less potent or urgent than those of men.,,6 But secondly, SH has nothing to do with men's sexual desires, nor is it about seduction; instead, it is about oppression of women. Indeed, harassment generally does not lead to sexual satisfaction, but it often gives the harasser a sense of power.
The second myth is that women either welcome, ask for, or deserve the harassing treatment. Case law reveals this mistaken belief. In Lipsett v. Rive-Mora7 (1987), the plaintiff was discharged from a medical residency program because she "did not react favorably to her professor's requests to go out for drinks, his compliments about her hair and legs, or to questions about her personal and romantic life.,,9 The court exonerated the defendant because the plaintiff had initially reacted favorably by smiling when shown lewd drawings of herself and when called sexual nicknames as she thought she had to appease the physician. The court said that "given the plaintiffs admittedly favorable responses to these flattering comments, there was no way anyone could consider them as 'unwelcome.,,,9 The court in Swentek v. US AirlO (1987) reacted similarly when a flight attendant who was harassed with obscene remarks and gestures was denied legal recourse because previously
she had used vulgar language and openly discussed her sexual encounters. The court concluded that "she was the kind of person who could not be offended by such comments and therefore welcomed them generally.,,11
The idea that women welcome "advances" from men is seen in men's view of the way women dress. If a woman dresses "provocatively" by men's standards, she is said to welcome or even deserve the treatment she gets. One explanation harassing professors give for their behavior is that they are bombarded daily with the temptation of physically desirable young women who dress in what they take to be revealing ways.12 When the case becomes public, numerous questions arise about the attractiveness of the victim, as if she were to blame for being attractive and the consequences thereof. Catcallers often try to justify their behavior by claiming that the victim should expect such behavior, given her tight-fitting dress or shorts, low-cut top, high heels, etc. This way of thinking infests discussions of rape in attempts to establish that women want to be raped, and it is mistaken in that context, too. The myth that women welcome or encourage harassment is designed "to keep women in their place" as men see it. The truth of the matter is that the perpetrator alone is at fault.
Both myths harm all women as they sanction SH by shifting the burden onto the victim and all members of her sex: women must either go out of their way to avoid "natural" male behavior, or establish conclusively that they do not in any way want the behavior. Instead of the behavior being seen as sexist, it is seen as women's problem to rectify.
Last, but certainly not least, women suffer group harm from SH because they come to be stereotyped as victims. 13 Many men see SH as something they can do to women, and in many cases, get away with. Women come to see themselves as victims, and come to believe that the roles they can occupy are only the sex roles men have designated for them. Obviously these harms are quite serious for women, so the elimination of all forms of SH is warranted.
I have spoken so far as if it is only men who can sexually harass women, and I am now in a position to defend this controversial view. When a
woman engages in the very same harassing behavior men engage in, the underlying message implicit in male-to-female harassment is missing. For example, when a woman scans a man's body, she might be considering him to be a sex object, but all the views about domination and being relegated to certain sex roles are absent. She cannot remind the man that he is inferior because of his sex, since given the way things are in society, he is not. In general, women cannot harm or degrade or dominate men as a group, for it is impossible to send the message that one dominates (and so cause group harm) if one does not dominate. Of course, if the sexist roles predominant in our society were reversed, women could sexually harass men. The way things are, any bothersome behavior a woman engages in, even though it may be of a sexual nature, does not constitute SH because it lacks the social impact present in male-to-female harassment. Tort law would be sufficient to protect against this behavior, since it is unproblematic in these cases that tort law fails to recognize group harm.
IIISubjective vs. Objective Definitions of Sexual Harassment
Most definitions of "sexual harassment" make reference to the behavior's being "unwelcome" or "annoying" to the victim. Black's Law Dictionary defines "harassment" as a term used "to describe words, gestures and actions which tend to annoy, alarm and abuse (verbally) another person.,,14 The American Heritage Dictionary defines "harass" as "to disturb or irritate persistently," and states further that "[h]arass implies systematic persecution by besetting with annoyances, threats, or demands.,,15 The EEOC Guidelines state that behavior constituting SH is identified as "unwelcome sexual advances, requests for sexual favors, and other verbal or physical conduct of a sexual nature." 16 In their philosophical account of SH, Hughes and May define "harassment" as "a class of annoying or unwelcome acts undertaken by one person (or group of persons) against another person (or group of persons).,,17 And Rosemarie Tong takes the feminists' definition
Sexual Harassment
of noncoercive SH to be that which "denotes sexual misconduct that merely annoys or offends the person to whom it is directed.,,18
The criterion of "unwelcomeness" or "annoyance" is reflected in the way the courts have handled cases of SH, as in Lipsett, Swentek, and Meritor, though in the latter case the court said that the voluntariness of the victim's submission to the defendant's sexual conduct did not mean that she welcomed the conduct. 19 The criterion of unwelcomeness or annoyance present in these subjective accounts of harassment puts the burden on the victim to establish that she was sexually harassed. There is no doubt that many women are bothered by this behavior, often with serious side-effects including anything from anger, fear, and guilt,z° to lowered self-esteem and decreased feelings of competence and confidence,21 to anxiety disorders, alcohol and drug abuse, coronary disturbances, and gastro-intestinal disorders. 22
Though it is true that many women are bothered by the behavior at issue, I think it is seriously mistaken to say that whether the victim is bothered determines whether the behavior constitutes SH. This is so for several reasons.
First, we would have to establish that the victim was bothered by it, either by the victim's complaints, or by examining the victim's response to the behavior. The fact of the matter is that many women are quite hesitant to report being harassed, for a number of reasons. Primary among them is that they fear negative consequences from reporting the conduct. As is often the case, harassment comes from a person in a position of institutional power, whether he be a supervisor, a company president, a member of a dissertation committee, the chair of the department, and so on. Unfortunately for many women, as a review of the case law reveals, their fears are warranted. 23 Women have been fired, their jobs have been made miserable, forcing them to quit, professors have handed out unfair low grades, and so on. Worries about such consequences mean that complaints are not filed, or are filed years after the incident, as in the Anita Hill v. Clarence Thomas case. But this should not be taken to imply that the victim was not harassed.
Sexual and Racial Discrimination
Moreover, women are hesitant to report harassment because they do not want anything to happen to the perpetrator, but just want the behavior to stop.24 Women do not complain because they do not want to deal with the perpetrator's reaction when faced with the charge. He might claim that he was "only trying to be friendly." Women are fully aware that perpetrators can often clear themselves quite easily, especially in tort law cases where the perpetrator's intentions are directly relevant to whether he is guilty. And most incidents of SH occur without any witnesses ~ many perpetrators plan it this way. It then becomes the harasser's word against the victim's. To complicate matters, many women are insecure and doubt themselves. Women's insecurity is capitalized upon by harassers whose behavior is in the least bit ambiguous. Clever harassers who fear they might get caught or be reported often attempt to get on the good side of their victim in order to confuse her about the behavior, as well as to have a defense ready in case a charge is made. Harassers might offer special teaching assignments to their graduate students, special help with exams and publications, promotions, generous raises, and the like. Of course, this is all irrelevant to whether he harasses, but the point is that it makes the victim less likely to complain. On top of all this, women's credibility is very often questioned (unfairly) when they bring forth a charge. They are taken to be "hypersensitive." There is an attitude among judges and others that women must "develop a thick skin.,,25 Thus, the blame is shifted off the perpetrator and onto the victim. Given this, if a woman thinks she will get no positive response ~ or, indeed, will get a negative one ~ from complaining, she is unlikely to do so.
Further, some women do not recognize harassment for what it is, and so will not complain. Sometimes this is because they are not aware of their own oppression, or actually seem to endorse sexist stereotypes. I recall a young woman who received many catcalls on the streets of Daytona Beach, Florida, during spring break, and who was quite proud that her body could draw such attention. Given that women are socialized into believing their bodies are the most important feature of themselves, it is no
surprise that a fair number of them are complacent about harassing behavior directed at them. Sandra Bartky provides an interesting analysis of why every woman is not a feminist, and I think it holds even for women who understand the issue. 26 Since for many women having a body felt to be "feminine" is crucial to their identity and to their sense of self "as a sexually desiring and desirable subject," feminism "may well be apprehended by a woman as something that threatens her with desexualization, if not outright annihilation. ,,27 The many women who resist becoming feminists are not likely to perceive harassing behavior as bothersome. It would be incorrect to conclude that the behavior is not harassment on the grounds that such victims are not bothered. What we have is a nowin situation for victims: if the behavior bothers a woman she often has good reason not to complain; and if it does not bother her, she will not complain. Either way, the perpetrator wins. So we cannot judge whether women are bothered by the behavior on the basis of whether they say they are bothered.
Moreover, women's behavior is not an accurate indicator of whether they are bothered. More often than not, women try to ignore the perpetrator's behavior in an attempt not to give the impression they are encouraging it. They often cover up their true feelings so that the perpetrator does not have the satisfaction that his harassing worked. Since women are taught to smile and put up with this behavior, they might actually appear to enjoy it to some extent. Often they have no choice but to continue interacting with the perpetrator, making it very difficult to assert themselves. Women often make up excuses for not "giving in" instead of telling the perpetrator to stop. The fact that their behavior does not indicate they are bothered should not be used to show they were not bothered. In reality, women are fearful of defending themselves in the face of men's power and physical strength. Given the fact that the courts have decided that a lot of this behavior should just be tolerated, it is no wonder that women try to make the best of their situation.
It would be wrong to take a woman's behavior to be a sign that she is bothered also because
doing so implies the behavior is permissible if she does not seem to care. This allows the perpetrator to be the judge of whether a woman is harassed, which is unjustifiable given the confusion among men about whether their behavior is bothersome or flattering. Sexual harassment should be treated no differently than crimes where harm to the victim is assessed in some objective way, independent of the perpetrator's beliefs. To give men this power in the case of harassment is to perpetuate sexism from all angles.
An objective view of SH avoids the problems inherent in a subjective view. According to the objective view defended here, what is decisive in determining whether behavior constitutes SH is not whether the victim is bothered, but whether the behavior is an instance of a practice that expresses and perpetuates the attitude that the victim and members of her sex are inferior because of their sex. Thus the Daytona Beach case counts as a case of SH because the behavior is an instance of a practice that reflects men's domination of women in that it relegates women to the role of sex objects. 28
The courts have to some extent tried to incorporate an objective notion of SH by invoking the "reasonable person" standard. The EEOC Guidelines, as shown earlier, define SH partly as behavior that "has the purpose or effect of unreasonably interfering with an individual's work performance ... The Restatement of Torts, referring to the tort of intentional infliction of emotional distress, states that the emotional distress must be "so severe that no
reasonable man could be expected to endure
it. ,,30
In various cases the courts have invoked a reasonable man (or person) standard, but not to show that women who are not bothered still suffer harassment. Instead, they used the standard to show that even though a particular woman was bothered, she would have to tolerate such behavior because it was behavior a reasonable person would not have been affected by. In
Rabidue v. Osceola Refining Co. 3l (1986), a woman complained that a co-worker had made obscene comments about women in general and her in particular. The court ruled that "a reasonable person would not have been signifi-
Sexual Harassment
cantly affected by the same or similar circumstances,,,32 and that "women must expect a certain amount of demeaning conduct in certain work environments. ,,33
But the reasonable man standard will not work, since men and women perceive situations involving SH quite differently. The reasonable person standard fares no better as it becomes the reasonable man standard when it is applied by male judges seeing things through male eyes. Studies have shown that sexual overtures that men find flattering are found by women to be insulting. And even when men recognize behavior as harassment, they think women will be flattered by it. 34 The difference in perception only strengthens my point about the group harm that SH causes all women: unlike women, men can take sexual overtures directed at them to be complimentary because the overtures do not signify the stereotyping that underlies SH of women. A reasonable man standard would not succeed as a basis upon which to determine SH, as its objectivity is outweighed by the disparity found in the way the sexes assess what is "reasonable."
Related to this last topic is the issue of the harasser's intentions. In subjective definitions this is the counterpart to the victim's being bothered. Tort law makes reference to the injuror's intentions: in battery tort, the harasser's intent to contact, in assault tort, the harasser's intent to arouse psychic apprehension in the victim, and in the tort of intentional emotional distress, the harasser's intent or recklessness, must be established in order for the victim to win her case.
But like the victim's feelings, the harasser's intentions are irrelevant to whether his behavior is harassment. As I just pointed out, many men do not take their behavior to be bothersome, and sometimes even mistakenly believe that women enjoy crude compliments about their bodies, ogling, pinching, etc. From perusing cases brought before the courts, I have come to believe that many men have psychological feelings of power over women, feelings of being in control of their world, and the like, when they harass. These feelings might be subconscious, but this should not be admitted as a defense of the harasser. Also, as I have said,
Sexual and Racial Discrimination
many men believe women encourage SH either by their dress or language, or simply by the fact that they tolerate the abuse without protest (usually out of fear of repercussion). In light of these facts, it would be wrongheaded to allow the harasser's intentions to count in assessing harassment, though they might become relevant in determining punishment. I am arguing for an objective definition of SH: it is the attitudes embedded and reflected in the practice the behavior is an instance of, not the attitudes or intentions of the perpetrator, that makes the behavior SH.
Yet the idea that the behavior must be directed at a certain person in order for it to count as harassment, seems to suggest that intentions do count in assessing harassment. This feature is evident both in my definition, as well as in that found in Black's Law Dictionary, which takes harassment to be conduct directed against a specific person causing substantial emotional distress. If conduct is directed at a particular individual, it seems that the person expressing himself must be intentionally singling out that individual, wanting to cause her harm.
I think this is mistaken. Since the harasser can subconsciously enjoy the feeling of power harassing gives him, or might even consider his behavior to be flattering, his behavior can be directed at a specific person (or group of persons) without implying any ill intention on his part. By "directed at a particular individual," I mean that the behavior is in some way observed by a particular person (or persons). This includes, for example, sexist comments a student hears her professor say, pornographic pictures a worker sees, etc. I interpret it loosely enough to include a person's overhearing sexist comments even though the speaker has no idea the person is within earshot (sometimes referred to as "nondirected behavior"). But I interpret it to exclude the bare knowledge that sexist behavior is going on (e.g., female employees knowing that there are pornographic pictures hidden in their boss's office). If it did not exclude such behavior it would have to include knowledge of any sexist behavior, even if no person who can be harmed by it ever observes it (e.g., pornographic magazines strewn on a desert island).
Though such behavior is sexist, it fails to constitute SH.
IV Implications of the Objective
Definition
One implication ofmy objective definition is that it reflects the correct way power comes into play in SH. Traditionally, SH has been taken to exist only between persons of unequal power, usually in the workplace or an educational institution. It is believed that SH in universities occurs only when a professor harasses a student, but not vice versa. It is said that students can cause "sexual hassle," because they cannot "destroy [the professor's] self-esteem or endanger his intellectual self-confidence," and professors "seldom suffer the complex psychological effects of sexual harassment victims.,,35 MacKinnon, in her earlier book, defines SH as "the unwanted imposition of sexual requirements in the context of a relationship of unequal power. ,,36
Though it is true that a lot of harassment occurs between unequals, it is false that harassment occurs only between unequals: equals and subordinates can harass. Indeed, power is irrelevant to tort law, and the courts now recognize harassment among co-workers under Title VII.
The one sense in which it is true that the harasser must have power over his victim is that men have power - social, political, and economic - over women as a group. This cannot be understood by singling out individual men and showing that they have power over women or any particular woman for that matter. It is power that all men have, in virtue of being men. Defining SH in the objective way I do allows us to see that this is the sense in which power exists in SH, in all of its forms. The benefit of not restricting SH to cases of unequal institutional power is that all victims are afforded protection.
A second implication of my definition is that it gives the courts a way of distinguishing SH from sexual attraction. It can be difficult to make this distinction, since "traditional courtship activities" are often quite sexist and frequently involve behavior that is harassment. The key is to examine the practice the behavior is an instance of. If the behavior reflects the
attitude that the victim is inferior because of her sex, then it is SH. Sexual harassment is not about a man's attempting to date a woman who is not interested, as the courts have tended to believe; it is about domination, which might be reflected, of course, in the way a man goes about trying to get a date. My definition allows us to separate cases of SH from genuine sexual attraction by forcing the courts to focus on the social nature of SH.
Moreover, defining SH in the objective way I do shifts the burden and the blame off the victim. On the subjective view, the burden is on the victim to prove that she is bothered significantly enough to win a tort case; or under Title VII, to show that the behavior unreasonably interfered with her work. In tort law, where the perpetrator's intentions are allowed to figure in, the blame could easily shift to the victim by showing that she in some way welcomed or even encouraged the behavior, thereby relinquishing the perpetrator from responsibility. By focusing on the practice the behavior is an instance of, my definition has nothing to do with proving that the victim responds a certain way to the behavior, nor does it in any way blame the victim for the behavior.
Finally, defining SH in a subjective way means that the victim herself must come forward and complain, as it is her response that must be assessed. But given that most judges, law enforcement officers, and even superiors are men, it is difficult for women to do so. They are embarrassed, afraid to confront someone of the same sex as the harasser, who is likely not to see the problem. They do not feel their voices will be heard. Working with my definition will, I hope, assuage this. Recognizing SH as a group harm will allow women to come to each other's aid as co-complainers, thereby alleviating the problem of reticence. Even if the person the behavior is directed at does not feel bothered, other women can complain, as they suffer the group harm associated with SH.
V Conclusion
The definition of SH I have defended III this paper has as its main benefit that it acknowledges
Sexual Harassment
the group harm SH causes all women, thereby getting to the heart of what is wrong with SH. By doing so, it protects all victims in all cases from even the most subtle kinds of SH, since all cases of SH have in common group harm.
Of course, as with any definition, problems exist. Though space does not allow that I deal with them, a few are worth mentioning. One is that many behaviors will count as SH, leading perhaps to an unmanageable number of claims. Another is that it will still be a matter of interpretation whether a given behavior meets the criteria for SH. Perhaps the most crucial objection is that since so many kinds of behavior count as SH, the right to free speech will be curtailed in unacceptable ways.37
I believe there are at least partial solutions to these problems. My proposal is only programmatic, and a thorough defense of it would include working through these and other problems. Such a defense will have to wait.
Notes
I would like to thank John Exdell and Lois Pineau for helpful discussions and many insightful comments on an earlier draft of this paper.
I This suggests that only men can sexually harass women. I will defend this view later in the paper.
2Frances Conley, a 50-year-old distinguished neurophysician at Stanford University, recently came
forward with this story. Conley resigned after years of putting up with sexual harassment from her colleagues. Not only did they use Playboy spreads during their lectures, but they routinely called her "hon," invited her to bed, and fondled her legs under the operating table. Chicago Tribune, Sunday,June 9,1991, Section I,
|
p.22. |
|
|
3 Hughes, J. |
and May, L. "Sexual Harassment," |
||
|
Social Theory and Practice no. 3 (Fall 1980), pp. |
||
|
264-5. |
|
|
4 |
Ibid., p. 265. |
|
|
5 These same myths surround the |
issue of rape. |
||
|
This is discussed fruitfully by Lois Pineau in |
||
|
"Date Rape: A Feminist Analysis," Law and Phil- |
||
|
osophy 8 (1989): 217-43. |
|
|
6 |
Catherine |
MacKinnon, Sexual |
Harassment oj |
Working Women: A Case oj Sex Discrimination
(New Haven: Yale University Press, 1979), p. 152.