Добавил:
Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:

The Routledge Companion to the Study of Religion by John Hinnells

.pdf
Скачиваний:
35
Добавлен:
18.03.2022
Размер:
2.98 Mб
Скачать

216â Key approaches to the study of religions

for capturing the intentional characteristics of religious manifestations. Phenomenologists of religion criticize reductionist approaches for denying the unique intentionality of religious phenomena.

Religious experiences reveal structures of transcendence in which human beings intend a transcendent referent, a supernatural meta-empirical sacred meaning. Religious language points to intended sacred structures and meanings that transcend normal spatial, temporal, historical, and conceptual categories and analysis. That is why religious expressions are highly symbolic, analogical, metaphorical, mythic, and allegorical.

At the same time, no intentional referent and meaning is unmediated. For meaningful religious experience and communication, intended transcendent referents must be mediated and brought into an integral relation with our limited spatial, temporal, historical, cultural world with its intended objects and meanings. This is why symbolism is essential for revealing, constituting, and communicating religious intentional meaning. Religious symbolic expressions serve as indispensable mediating bridges. On the one hand, they always point beyond themselves to intended transcendent meanings. On the other hand, by necessarily using symbolic language drawn from the spatial, temporal, natural, historical world of experience, they mediate the transcendent referent, limit and incarnate the sacred, allow disclosure of transcendent as imminent, and render sacred meanings humanly accessible and relevant to particular existential situations.

This specific religious intentionality ensures that the structures of experience, as well as interpretations and understandings, remain open-ended. The necessary structural conditions for religious experience, disclosure of phenomena, construction of texts, and formulation of interpretations ensure that meaningful human understandings necessarily reveal limited intentional perspectives. And such relative, situated, intentional, religious perspectives always point beyond themselves to structures of transcendence; to inexhaustible possibilities for revalorizing symbolic expressions, for bursting open self-imposed perspectival closures, and for new, creative, self-transcending experiences, interpretations, and understandings.

Epoché, empathy, and sympathetic understanding

By bracketing and suspending our unexamined assumptions and ordinary preconceptions and judgments, we become attentive to a much fuller disclosure of what manifests itself and how it manifests itself in experience. This allows for greater awareness of phenomena experienced on prereflective, emotive, imaginative, nonconceptual levels of intentional experience, thus leading to new insights into the specific intentionality and concrete richness of experience.

The phenomenological epoché, with an emphasis on empathy and sympathetic understanding, is related to methodological antireductionism. By suspending all personal preconceptions as to what is real and insisting on the irreducibility of the religious, phenomenologists attempt sympathetically to place themselves within the religious ‘lifeworld’ of others. This phenomenological orientation, different from the ideal of detached, impersonal scientific objectivity, recognizes limitations to such personal empathetic participation, since the other always remains to some extent ‘other.’ Critics charge that phenomenologists often give little more than vague appeals to abstain from value judgments and for empathetic participation.

In assuming a sympathetic attitude, the phenomenologist is not claiming that religious phenomena are not ‘illusory’ and that the intentional objects are ‘real’ as existing behind the phenomenal appearance. (As a matter of fact, many phenomenologists make such theological

Phenomenology of religionâ 217â

and metaphysical assumptions and judgments, but these usually violate the limits of their phenomenological perspectives.) The phenomenological bracketing entails suspension of all such value judgments regarding whether or not God, the holy, or sacred is actually an experience of ultimate reality.

Many phenomenologists argue for the necessity of religious commitment, a personal religious faith, or at least personal religious experience in order for a scholar to be capable of empathy, participation, and sympathetic understanding. Other phenomenologists argue that such personal religious commitments generally produce biased descriptions. A particular faith or theological commitment is not a precondition for accurate phenomenological descriptions. Rather it is a commitment, manifested in terms of intellectual curiosity, sensitivity, and respect, that is indispensable for participation and understanding. Believers and nonbelievers alike may share such a commitment.

Insight into essential structures and meanings

No subject matter is more central to philosophical phenomenology than analyses of eidetic reduction and eidetic vision, intuition of essences, method of free variation, and other techniques for gaining insight into essential structures and meanings. By contrast, phenomenology of religion, even in the specific sense of an approach concerned with describing essential structures and meanings, has usually avoided such methodological formulations.

One generally finds that most phenomenologists of religion accept both Bleeker’s qualification that such terms as ‘eidetic vision’ are used only in a figurative sense and his warning that phenomenology of religion should not meddle in difficult philosophical questions of methodology. The result is that one is frequently presented with phenomenological typologies, ‘universal structures,’ and ‘essential meanings’ that lack a rigorous analysis of just how the phenomenologist arrived at or verified these discoveries.

Phenomenologists aim at intuiting, describing, and interpreting the essence of religious phenomena, but there is considerable disagreement as to what constitutes an essential structure. For some phenomenologists, an ‘essential structure’ is the result of an empirical inductive generalization expressing a property that different phenomena have in common. In the sense closest to philosophical phenomenology, essence refers to deep or hidden structures, which are not apparent on the level of immediate experience and must be uncovered and interpreted through the phenomenological method. These structures express the necessary invariant features allowing us to distinguish religious phenomena and to grasp religious phenomena as phenomena of a certain kind.

Controversial issues

The examination of major characteristics of phenomenology of religion raises many controversial issues.

Descriptive versus normative claims

Controversial issues arise from phenomenology of religion’s claim that it is a descriptive discipline with a descriptive method, especially since most phenomenologists go beyond a mere description of the data, offering comparisons and evaluations, universal structures, and essential meanings.

218â Key approaches to the study of religions

Some of these issues arise from the adoption by many phenomenologists of religion of a traditional, at times absolute, descriptive–normative dichotomy consistent with classical empiricism of such philosophers as David Hume, with the Kantian philosophical framework, and with most nineteenth and twentieth-century approaches to religions.

Even phenomenologists of religion who go beyond Kristensen’s descriptive restrictions frequently adopt a clear distinction between collection and description of religious data, which is objective and scientific, and interpretation of meaning, which is at least partially subjective and normative. Phenomenology of religion, despite its rejection of positivism, has sometimes unintentionally retained positivistic assumptions regarding the description of unconstructed, uninterpreted, objective ‘facts.’

Recent scholarship challenges this absolute dichotomy. What is taken as objective and scientific is historically, culturally, and socially situated and constructed in terms of implicit and explicit value judgments. For example, how does one even begin the investigation? What facts should be collected as religious facts? One’s principles of selectivity are never completely value-free. Philosophical phenomenologists have never accepted this sharp dichotomy, since the phenomenological project is founded on possibilities of describing meanings. The challenge to phenomenology of religion is to formulate a phenomenological method and framework for interpretation that allows the description of essential structures and meanings with some sense of objectivity.

Understanding versus explanation claims

Many controversial issues involve a sharp understanding–explanation dichotomy. This ‘understanding’ often has the sense of Verstehen as formulated by Dilthey as the method and goal of hermeneutics. Phenomenologists aim at understanding, describing and interpreting the nature and meaning of religious and other ‘human’ phenomena, as opposed to scientific, reductionistic approaches that give historical, psychological, and other explanations but do not grasp the irreducibly human and irreducibly religious dimensions of phenomena.

Critics challenge such methods and goals as unscientific and question whether phenomenological understanding and nonphenomenological explaining can be so completely separated. Explanatory approaches involve understanding, and understanding involves critical explanatory reflection. For example, for phenomenological understanding, expressions of religious others are not the absolute final word. The other may have a limited understanding of her or his phenomena, provide false explanations, and engage in blatantly unethical behavior. Phenomenology of religion necessarily involves critical reflection, including contextual awareness and scholarly interpretations, understandings, and explanations that go beyond describing expressed positions of religious others.

This in no way denies the value of phenomenological approaches that are self-critical in rendering explicit one’s presuppositions, suspend one’s value judgments, empathize, and describe phenomena and intended meanings of the religious other. Such phenomenology of religion aims at allowing other voices to be heard and is informed by a history of dominant, normative approaches and explanations that ignore, silence, and misinterpret the religious phenomena of others.

Phenomenology of religionâ 219â

Antireductionist claims

Many critics attack phenomenology of religion’s antireductionism, arguing that it is methodologically confused and often arises from the theological intention of protecting religion from secular analysis. All methodological approaches are perspectival, limiting, and necessarily reductionistic. The assumption of the irreducibility of the religious limits what phenomena will be investigated, what aspects of the phenomena will be described, and what meanings will be interpreted. Phenomenologists of religion cannot argue that other reductionistic approaches are necessarily false and that their approach does justice to all dimensions of religious phenomena.

Phenomenology of religion must show that its religious antireductionism is not methodologically confused and does not beg serious questions by simply avoiding scholarly challenges. It can argue for an antireductionist methodological primacy on the basis of such key notions as intentionality and insight into essential structures and meanings. It must show that its particular perspective is essential for shedding light on religious structures and meanings.

Empirical and historical claims

Much of philosophical phenomenology, even when described as radical empiricism, is conceived in opposition to traditional empiricism. Husserl called for a ‘phenomenological reduction’ in which the phenomenologist ‘suspends’ the ‘natural standpoint’ and its empirical world in order to become more attentive to phenomena and to intuit the deeper phenomenological essences.

Critics claim that phenomenology of religion starts with a priori nonempirical assumptions, utilizes a method that is not empirically based, and detaches religious structures and meanings from historical and cultural contexts. Critics often assume a clear-cut dichotomy between empirical, inductive, historical approaches and nonempirical, often rationalist, deductive, antihistorical approaches. They identify phenomenology of religion with the latter and argue that it cannot meet minimal empirical, historical, scientific, inductive criteria, including rigorous criteria for verification and falsification.

Controversies arise from criticisms that phenomenology of religion makes nonempirical, nonhistorical, a priori, theological, and other normative assumptions and grants an ontologically privileged status to religious phenomena and to specific kinds of religious experience. Critics charge that Otto, van der Leeuw, Eliade, and others have nonempirical and nonhistorical, extraphenomenological, theological, and other normative assumptions, intentions, and goals that take them beyond descriptive phenomenology and any rigorous scientific approach.

The status granted to essential religious structures and meanings is also controversial insofar as they exhibit the peculiarity of being empirical, based on investigating a limited sample of historical data, and, at the same time, universal. These structures are therefore empirically contingent and yet also the essential necessary features of religious phenomena.

Finally, there is controversy regarding the insistence by many phenomenologists of religion that they proceed by empirical inductive inference. Critics charge that they cannot repeat this inductive inference, that phenomenological structures do not appear in the empirical data, and that phenomenologists read into their data all kinds of essential meanings. Some, such as Douglas Allen in Structure and Creativity in Religion, respond by formulating a method of ‘phenomenological induction’ different from classical empirical induction, in which essential structures and meaning are based on, but not found fully in, the empirical data.

220â Key approaches to the study of religions

Questions of verification

Many criticisms of phenomenology of religion as methodologically uncritical involve questions of verification. Phenomenological ‘intuition’ does not free one from responsibility of ascertaining which interpretation of given phenomena is most adequate. Different phenomenologists, using a phenomenological method to investigate the same phenomena, present different eidetic intuitions. How does one resolve this contingency introduced into phenomenological insights? How does one verify interpretations and decide between different interpretations?

Such questions pose specific difficulties for a phenomenological method of epoché and intuition of essences. A phenomenological method often suspends the usual criteria of ‘objectivity’ that allow scholars to verify interpretations and choose between alternative accounts. Does this leave phenomenology of religion with a large number of personal, subjective, hopelessly fragmented interpretations of universal structures and meanings, each relativistic interpretation determined by the particular temperament, situation, and orientation of the phenomenologist?

Phenomenologists of religion submit that past criteria for verification are inadequate and offer a false sense of objectivity, but phenomenology of religion must also overcome the charges of subjectivity and relativism. It must formulate procedures for testing its claims of essential structures and meanings that involve criteria for intersubjective verification.

Response to controversial issues

Many writers describe phenomenology of religion as in a state of crisis. They usually minimize the invaluable contributions made by phenomenology to the study of religion, such as the impressive systematization of so much religious data and the raising of fundamental questions of meaning.

If phenomenology of religion is to deal adequately with controversial issues, the following are several of its future tasks. First, it must become more aware of historical, philological, and other specialized approaches to, and different aspects of, its religious data. Second, it must critique various approaches of its critics, thus showing that its phenomenological method is not obliged to meet inadequate criteria for objectivity. And most importantly, it must reflect more critically on questions of methodology so that it can formulate a more rigorous method, allowing for description of phenomena, interpretation of their structures and meanings, and verification of its findings.

Recent developments in phenomenology of religion

Developments within phenomenology of religion during the last decades of the twentieth century and early years of the twenty-first century convey a very mixed and confusing picture about the present status and future prospects for the field.

Within religious studies

Phenomenology of religion continues as a discipline and approach within the general scholarly study of religion. Earlier phenomenologists influence phenomenologists of religion, and they share the general phenomenological orientation defined by major characteristics previously delineated. Phenomenology of religion has also been successful to the extent that many other

Phenomenology of religionâ 221â

scholars, who do not consider themselves phenomenologists, adopt a phenomenological approach during early stages of their investigations because it has great value in allowing them to assemble data and do justice to the perspectives of religious persons.

At the same time, phenomenology of religion is sometimes described as being stagnant and in a state of crisis. There has been a recent renewal of interest in religion in French philosophical phenomenology and in phenomenological theology, but it is not clear how this relates to phenomenology of religion within religious studies. There are no contemporary phenomenologists of religion who enjoy the status and influence once enjoyed by a van der Leeuw or an Eliade. Some scholars are uncomfortable with the term since it carries so much baggage from Husserlian philosophical foundations and from Eliadean and other phenomenology of religion. In general, contemporary phenomenologists of religion attempt to be more contextually sensitive and more modest in their phenomenological claims.

Within philosophical and theological phenomenology

The emphasis in this chapter has been on phenomenology of religion as a discipline and method within religious studies and not on philosophical phenomenology with its limited focus on religion. Special mention may be made of two influential European philosophers. Emmanuel Levinas, a student of Husserl, became an influential continental philosopher in the late twentieth century. With his major focus on ethics, spirituality, and Jewish philosophy, Levinas emphasizes radical alterity and the primacy of the ‘other,’ thus reversing earlier phenomenological self–other emphasis on the privileged status of the constituting self or ego. Ricoeur, also with deep roots in Husserl, has made invaluable contributions to our understanding of religious phenomena with his analysis of philosophy as hermeneutical interpretation of meaning and with his focus on religious language, symbolism, and narrative.

Beginning in the late twentieth century, continental philosophy, especially French phenomenology, often takes a religious turn. Scholars such as Michel Henry and especially Jean-Luc Marion are often identified as part of ‘the new phenomenology’ and ‘theological phenomenology.’ However, it is not always clear whether to classify such developments under ‘the phenomenology of religion.’ Most of these scholars have been deeply influenced by Husserl’s phenomenology, but they often seem to transgress phenomenology’s boundaries and express ambiguous relations to phenomenology.

While significant developments in continental philosophy increasingly focus on religion, it is not yet clear whether such phenomenological and theological developments will have a significant influence on phenomenology of religion within religious studies.

Recent challenges

Most scholarly challenges to phenomenology of religion continue major criticisms previously described. Robert Segal and other scholars of religion, usually identified with social scientific and reductionist approaches, criticize phenomenology of religion for being unscientific, highly subjective, and lacking scholarly rigor. Scholars identifying with reductionistic cognitive science and neuroscience provide recent challenges.

There are also challenges to phenomenology of religion that offer opposite criticisms. Scholars criticize phenomenology of religion’s claim to uncover universal structures and essences as being too reductionistic in denying the diversity and plurality of religious

222â Key approaches to the study of religions

phenomena. Included here are a variety of approaches often described as postmodernist, deconstructionist, post-structuralist, narrativist, pragmatist, feminist, and relativist.

Gavin Flood and other scholars identified with critical theory, postmodernism, and other recent approaches criticize essentialist phenomenology of religion for being nonhistorical and nontemporal; for ignoring the situated contextualism of all phenomena and all approaches; for presenting a false view of human consciousness, experience, and language; and for romanticizing and defending religious phenomena and religious faith while ignoring the exploitative and oppressive dimensions of religious phenomena reflecting ideologies and power relations of domination.

Several recent contributions

Finally, there are three, recent, interrelated contributions to phenomenology of religion that often contrast with earlier characteristics: focus on the ‘other,’ ‘givenness,’ and contextualization.

Philosophical phenomenology and phenomenology of religion emphasize the need to become aware of one’s presuppositions, suspend one’s value judgments, and accurately describe and interpret the meaning of phenomena as phenomena. Earlier approaches have been critiqued for ignoring or distorting intentional structures and meanings of religious phenomena of the ‘other.’ More recent phenomenologists recognize that earlier phenomenology, with its essentializing projects and universalizing claims, often did not pay sufficient attention to diverse experiences and meanings of others. One sometimes learns more about the scholar’s phenomenological theory of religion than about the particular religious phenomena of others. Recent phenomenology has been more sensitive to providing an approach for becoming attentive to the tremendous diversity of religious voices of others.

Related to this is the focus on givenness. There is the more ontological, theological, and controversial move by Marion and others to emphasize a phenomenological reduction of phenomena to a primary experience of givenness. In a more widespread and less controversial contribution, philosophical phenomenology and phenomenology of religion emphasize the need for an active openness and deeper kind of attentiveness to how religious phenomena appear or are given to us in experience. Over the decades, phenomenology of religion has become much broader, more self-critical, and more sophisticated in recognizing the complexity, ambiguity, and depth of our diverse modes of givenness. For example, in their very dynamic of givenness, religious phenomena both reveal and conceal structures and meanings; are multidimensional and given meaning through pre-understandings, the prereflective, the emotive, and the imaginative, as well as rational and conceptual analysis; are not disclosed as bare givens but as highly complex, inexhaustible, constituted, selftranscending givens; and are given in ways that affirm the open-ended perspectival nature of all knowledge and the nonclosure of descriptions, interpretations, and explanations.

Phenomenologists of religion are much more sensitive to the complex, mediated, interactive, contextual situatedness of their phenomenological tasks. Often criticized for claiming to uncover nonhistorical, nontemporal, noncontextualized, essential structures and meanings, phenomenologists of religion tend to be more sensitive to the perspectival and contextual constraints of their approach and more modest in their claims. There is value in uncovering religious essences and structures, but as embodied and contextualized, not as fixed, absolute, ahistorical, eternal truths and meanings.

Phenomenology of religionâ 223â

These three contributions in phenomenology of religion of greater focus on the other, givenness, and contextualization can be related to a significant development in ‘the late Husserl.’ In his Crisis of European Science (1936), Husserl revisions his phenomenological project, especially by introducing the concept of the Lebenswelt or Lifeworld. He turns away from his earlier pure absolute idealism in which all judgments about phenomena are bracketed so that intentional phenomena are reduced to the consciousness of the constituting transcendental ego. Husserl now begins to rethink the pre-epistemological ground of his phenomenology in terms of the shared, intersubjective givenness of the lifeworld of lived experience. In such an intersubjective universe of what is given in lived experience, the dynamic horizon within which phenomena appear, consciousness is already embedded in the lifeworld of meanings and pre-judgments that are contextually, historically, socially, and culturally situated and constituted. Although Husserl did not develop this concept adequately, later philosophical phenomenology and some recent contributions in phenomenology of religion can be seen as ways of broadening and deepening this Husserlian orientation.

By now, it may be clear that phenomenology of religion has had a profound impact on religious studies, sometimes overtly and sometimes almost imperceptibly. Many scholars within religious studies, who would never call themselves phenomenologists, have had their teaching and research shaped by the contributions of phenomenology of religion. Their concerns about uncritical presuppositions and reductionism, empathy and essential structures, as well as their focus on such topics as sacred space and time, myth and ritual, have been influenced by their exposure to phenomenology of religion.

Within its specific discipline and approach, a more self-critical and modest phenomenology of religion has much to contribute to the study of religion. In providing descriptions and interpretations of phenomena, it will include awareness of its presuppositions, its historical and contextualized situatedness, and its limited perspectival knowledge claims. But it will not completely abandon concerns about essential structures, commonality and unity of human beings, as well as differences. Such a phenomenology of religion will attempt to formulate essential structures and meanings through rigorous phenomenological methods, while also attempting to formulate new, dynamic, open-ended, contextually sensitive projects involving creative encounter, contradiction, and synthesis.

Bibliography

Allen, D. (1978) Structure and Creativity in Religion, The Hague: Mouton. Bleeker, C. J. (1963) The Sacred Bridge, Leiden: Brill.

Eliade, M. (1963) Patterns in Comparative Religion, trans. R. Sheed, New York: World. —— (1969) The Quest, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Flood, G. (1999) Beyond Phenomenology, London: Cassell.

Husserl, E. (1970) The Crisis of European Science and Transcendental Phenomenology, trans. D. Carr, Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

Idinopulos, T. A. and E. A. Yonan, eds. (1994) Religion and Reductionism, Leiden: Brill. Kristensen, W. B. (1960) The Meaning of Religion, trans. J. B. Carman, The Hague: Nijhoff.

Leeuw, G. van der (1963) Religion in Essence and Manifestation, 2 vols., trans. J. E. Turner, New York: Harper & Row.

Otto, R. (1950) The Idea of the Holy, trans. J. W. Harvey, New York and London: Oxford University Press.

Scheler, M. (1960) On the Eternal in Man, trans. B. Noble, London: SCM. New York: Harper. Sharpe, E. J. (1986) Comparative Religion, La Salle, IL: Open Court.

224â Key approaches to the study of religions

Smart, N. (1973) The Science of Religion and the Sociology of Knowledge, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Suggested reading

Eliade, M. (1963) Patterns in Comparative Religion, trans. R. Sheed, New York: World.

Morphological work illustrating Eliade’s phenomenological framework for interpreting religious meaning.

—— (1969) The Quest, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Essays on Eliade’s phenomenological method and discipline.

Leeuw, G. van der (1963) Religion in Essence and Manifestation, 2 vols., trans. J. E. Turner, New York: Harper & Row.

Classic work in phenomenology of religion.

Otto, R. (1950) The Idea of the Holy, trans. J. W. Harvey, New York and London: Oxford University Press.

Influential phenomenological account of religious experience.

Chapter 13

Comparative religion

William E. Paden

Comparativereligion originated as an academic movement in the late nineteenth century. It signified then, as today, the cross-cultural study of all forms and traditions of religious life, as distinguished from the study or exposition of just one. As such, it entails the disciplined, historically informed consideration of any commonalities and differences that appear among religions.

Seeing similarities and differences is a basic activity of the human mind. The perception of relationships and patterns is the way individuals and cultures organize their experience of the world. It is a process without which there would be undifferentiated chaos, or at best only isolated facts. Likewise, specialized knowledge in any field advances by finding or constructing concepts and categories that give order and intelligibility to otherwise unrelated data. Comparison, among other things, is the process by which generalizations and classifications are produced, and is the basis of scientific and interpretive enterprises of every kind. The very concept ‘religion,’ as an academic definition of a certain area of culture, is such a cross-cultural, comparative category.

There can be no systematic study of religion as a subject matter without cross-cultural perspective. Lacking this, studies of religion would amount either to separate collections of unrelated historical data, or to speculative generalizations based only on the perspective of one culture. Modern generations of scholars have therefore tried to build an objective, or at least transcultural, vocabulary for describing a subject matter that is found in very different times, places and languages. For one cannot generalize about religion on the basis of the language and norms of just a single case, just as geologists do not construct a geology on the basis of the rocks that merely happen to be in one’s neighborhood. The neighborhood rocks, analogues to one’s own local religion, are themselves instances of certain common, universal properties of geological formations, chemical structures, and evolutionary development. Accordingly, without knowing these ‘comparative’ elements, one cannot know what is common and what is different about any particular religious phenomenon. Without them, one might not be able to see certain transcultural structures and functions in a given religious system.

Comparative analysis, then, both builds and applies the perspectives, reference points, and materials for any cumulative, interpretive study of religion. Moreover, these resources must necessarily be the collective, synthetic result of the contributions of many specialists, as no single person will have first-hand and technical knowledge of all of the world’s religious cultures. While comparison is a tool that can be applied locally or among restricted historical and regional data, this essay focuses mostly on its cross-cultural, generalizing functions.