Добавил:
Upload Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:
2 c.58-115.doc
Скачиваний:
0
Добавлен:
01.07.2025
Размер:
803.84 Кб
Скачать

57

IV. The self in sankhya-yoga

The sixth century B.C. is one of the most remarkable centuries in human history. It is the century of Isaiah, Jeremiah, Zoroaster, the Buddha, Mahavira, Confucius, and Lao Tzu. It is the century of Thales, Anaximander, and Anaximenes, who originated in the Greek world an approach to reality later to be called philosophy. And it is the century in which philosophy appeared in India. Many Indians and Indophiles will doubtlessly dispute this state­ment and will point to the Vedas and the Upanishads to support their claim for a much earlier date for the beginnings of philos­ophy in India; but these works cannot be considered as philos­ophy in the strictest sense, for they lack systematic presentation and rational argument, without which one may have religion or speculation, but not philosophy.

Das Gupta has said of the Vedas, "It is here we find interesting philosophical questions of a more or less cosmological character expressed in terms of poetry and imagination." J The same author says of the Upanishads, "These are not reasoned statements, but utterances of truths intuitively perceived or felt as unquestionably real and indubitable, and carrying great force, vigour, and persua­siveness with them."2 The speculations in the Vedic literature were - and still are - a vast mine of material for Indian philos­ophers. The ancient Greek philosophers could draw some philo­sophical material from the Iliad and the Odyssey, but these epics cannot match the Rig Veda and the Upanishads in quality and

1 Surendranath Das Gupta, a History of Indian Philosophy, Vol. 1 (Cam­ bridge, Cambridge University Press, 1957), p. 6.

2 Ibid., p. 7.

The Self in Sankhya-Yoga

quantity of religious and philosophical insights. This deficiency was not without merit. The Greeks, lacking a body of material assumed to be revealed, were not tempted to develop a Greek scholasticism; whereas one of the constant dangers in Indian phi­losophy has always been the stifling of original thought in the presence of authoritarian ideas. Greek philosophers did not write commentaries on the Iliad and the Odyssey; Indian philosophers, on the other hand, had difficulty in thinking except in the context of the Upanishads. This fundamental difference between the two philosophies can be brought out by noting that the terms orthodox and heterodox are irrelevant in Greek philosophy, but in Indian philosophy these terms are used to classify philosophers and phi­losophies.

Philosophy in ancient Greek civilization came to be when a few lonians, motivated by intellectual curiosity and courageously ig­noring mythology, began to speculate freely about the natural causes of physical motion and the fundamental reality which they surmised must lie behind the manifold world of everyday experi­ences. This early Greek thought was philosophical, not merely speculative, because argument was an integral part of it. Philos­ophy in India did not originate as an effort to satisfy scientific interests; rather it arose out of the emotional necessity of protect­ing and defending a precious body of truths. The Buddhist revolt was part of the intellectual ferment in sixth century India which forced Indian minds to desert dogmatism and adopt reason as a method of arriving at truths and values. Appeals to the authority of Upanishadic seers were futile against those who rejected Vedas and Upanishads. Analysis had to be countered with better anal­ysis, not with speculations; criticism with more penetrating criti­cism, not with revelations; system with system, not with intuitions; naturalistic and humanistic thought with logical examination, not with poetic rhapsody or mystical ecstasy. The Buddha may not have been the first Indian philosopher, but he is the earliest Indian thinker to be dated with accuracy who presented his message in a philosophical manner. His basic message, now called The Four Noble Truths, was presented as an inference from three postulates:

58

The Self in Sankhya-Yoga

The Self in Sankhya-Yoga

59

First Postulate: All living beings suffer.

Second Postulate: All suffering is caused by desires.

Third Postulate: Whatever is caused can be stopped by remov­ing the cause.

The Inference: Therefore, suffering can be stopped by the elim­ination of desires.

The Buddha was one of many who challenged the scholastic meth­od of discovering truth by searching in Vedic lore. Out of this challenge has grown Indian philosophy which was once described by Maulana Abul Kalam Azad, the first Minister of Education in the Government of India, as "one of the proudest possessions of human civilization".3

The term Indian philosophy is used with three different mean­ings. The broadest use of the term is the one which would include all speculation in the sub-continent of India. According to this use, the Rig Veda and all the Upanishads are part of Indian phi­losophy. From what has been said above, it is clear that this is not the sense in which the term is being used in this study. The term can be used in a second sense to include all the systematic and rational schools of thought which have developed in India, regardless of their relationship to the Vedas and the Upanishads. This use would include both the astika (orthodox) schools, which accept the Vedas and the Upanishads, and the nastika (unortho­dox) schools, which reject the Vedas and the Upanishads. The nastika schools are Carvaka or Lokayata, Jainism, and Buddhism. The narrowest use of the term would limit its denotation to the orthodox schools. It is in this sense that the term is used in this study.

The astika and the nastika philosophies - with the exception of the Carvaka - agree in three assumptions: (1) This world is a place of sorrow. (2) The soul is subject to transmigration. (3) The Vedic tradition contains some truths. Each philosopher interprets these assumptions in the context of his own philosophical position. The last assumption is especially varied in the systems; only the

3 Radhakrishnan et al, History of Philosophy, Eastern and Western, Vol. 1 (London, Allen and Unwin, 1952), p. 5.

Carvaka rejects the Upanishads completely and absolutely. A brief statement of how the self is conceived in each of the nastika systems will be helpful in understanding the self in the astika systems.

According to Carvaka there is no spiritual substance. The phys­ical body is the self. Life is one of the possible arrangements of matter, and consciousness is a by-product of physical activity.4

In Jainism all reality is divided into two categories: jlva (the vital principle) and ajlva (the non-vital principle). Jlvas are real individual substances having neither beginning nor end. Although jlvas are spiritual in nature, they have a physical dimension, but, unlike atoms, jlvas vary in size according to the size of the body the jlva inhabits. There are an infinite number of jlvas. They are all alike in that sentience is their essential nature, yet they differ by reason of the number of senses they have. Some jlvas have but one sense, e.g., jlvas in stones, lumps of clay, salt, and chalk have but the sense of touch; other jlvas have as many as five senses, e.g., human beings, lower animals, creatures of hell, and demi­gods. Jlvas upon becoming associated with the non-vital principle

- a principle which is divided into time, space, motion, stability, and matter — suffer curtailment of powers. The ami of human life is to cast off all limitations so the jlva can gain omniscience. The means of salvation is the avoidance of destruction of jlvas and the release from dependance upon ajlvaJ'

Gautama the Buddha rebelled against metaphysical specula­tions. He formulated a list of unelucidated or unprofitable ques­tions which he would not discuss because he believed that men

4 For information on Carvaka see: Dakshinaranjan Shastri, A Short His­tory of Indian Materialism, Sensationalism and Hedonism (Calcutta, Cal­cutta Book Co., 1930); Dale Riepe, The Naturalistic Tradition in Indian Thought (Seattle, University of Washington Press, 1961), ch. 4.

* The following books on Jainism are recommended: J. Jaini, Outlines of Jainism (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1916); Mohan Lai Mehta, Outlines of Jaina Philosophy (Bangalore, Jain Mission Society, 1954); Mrs. Sinclair T. Stevenson, The Heart of Jainism (London, Oxford University Press, 1915); Nathmal Tatia, Studies in Jaina Philosophy (Banares, Jain Cultural Research Society, 1951). The Sacred Books of the Jainas, edited by Sarat Chandra Ghoshal, is published by The Central Jaina Publishing House of Arrah and Lucknow.

60