
- •Is patently not the case. Many of the rules developed in the 20th century
- •In the light of these observations, it is probably better to regard English
- •Instead.9
- •Invention – if a way out of a tight corner has to be found, then it will be found.
- •Inconvenient, he should recognise the force of these considerations. On the
- •Is precisely how such realist judges will want to decide anyway.
- •Inconvenience, precisely because its market-individualism commits it to a
- •In defending the shopkeeper’s choice of customer), it is the principle of termfreedom
- •Intervention in particular cases.
- •Viewed as competitive transactions, are to be subject to rather more regulation
- •In Schuler V Wickman. We can also see this principle at work in regulating
- •V Hyland).
- •Impose an absolute obligation to work 48 hours’ overtime per week on
- •Irrelevant.4
- •In the cases so far considered, the parties are free to decide whether or not to
- •In his judgment in Trentham V Archital Luxfer,12 Steyn lj appears to position
- •It can be converted into a binding contract by the simple response ‘I accept’.
Intervention in particular cases.
A glance back over the chapters in this part of the book will reveal that the
modern law is littered with examples of the principle of sanctity of contract in
operation. We first encountered its non-interventionist philosophy in Lord
Wilberforce’s powerful dissent in Schuler v Wickman and, not surprisingly, the
same philosophy underpins his speech (and those of the other members of the
House) in Photo Production. However, the principle goes beyond particular
judgments. It is the foundation for such landmarks, as the doctrine that the
courts will not review the adequacy of consideration; the principle that the
basis of implied terms is necessity, not reasonableness (see Liverpool City
Council v Irwin); the hard line towards unilateral collateral mistake (see, for
example, Smith v Hughes); common mistake (see Bell v Lever Brothers Ltd) and
frustration (see Davis v Fareham); the cautious reception of economic duress;
the anxiety to limit the doctrine of inequality of bargaining power; the
resistance to the citation of relatively unimportant uncertainty as a ground for
release from a contract (see, for example, Foley v Classique Coaches Ltd); and the
reluctance to succumb to arguments of economic waste or unreasonableness as
a basis for release from a bargain (see, for example, White & Carter). The
principle of sanctity of contract is a thread which runs through contract from
beginning to end, enjoining the courts to be ever-vigilant in ensuring that
established or new doctrines do not become an easy exit from bad bargains.
(Of course, we are not suggesting that such bargains are necessarily products
in the first place of free bargaining in the literal sense. Especially in those cases
where standard forms are involved they are a product of some rather artificial
rules of incorporation (see, especially, L’Estrange v Graucob). But courts in this
century have tended to regard the contracts resulting from the application of
such rules as exercises in term-freedom.15
Finally, there is a consumer-welfarist approach which adopts an
interventionist stance, particularly with a view to the protection of weaker
parties and the promotion of justice and fairness in contractual dealings.
Consumer-welfarists are likely to be attracted by notions of good faith and fair
dealing and, if a particular rule does not fit with this ideology, a way round it
must be found. Adams and Brownsword conclude as follows:
If the 19th century is usually viewed as the classical period for the doctrines
associated with market-individualism, so the 20th century is for consumerwelfarism
(particularly from 1945 onwards). The recent burgeoning of
consumer-welfarism is, of course, hardly surprising. A policy of consumer
15 Adams and Brownsword, 2000, pp 172–77.
11
Chapter 1: Sourcebook on Contract Law
protection would have to await the development of a consumer society and a
policy of welfarism could be expected to grow as it became accepted that
government had a responsibility to maintain a welfare programme.
Although the consumer-welfarist ideology clearly stands for a policy of
consumer protection and for principles of fairness and reasonableness in
contract, it lacks the unity and coherence of market-individualism. It does not
start with the market-individualist premise that all contracts should be
minimally regulated. Rather, it presupposes that consumer contracts are to be
closely regulated and that commercial contracts, although still ordinarily to be