
- •Is patently not the case. Many of the rules developed in the 20th century
- •In the light of these observations, it is probably better to regard English
- •Instead.9
- •Invention – if a way out of a tight corner has to be found, then it will be found.
- •Inconvenient, he should recognise the force of these considerations. On the
- •Is precisely how such realist judges will want to decide anyway.
- •Inconvenience, precisely because its market-individualism commits it to a
- •In defending the shopkeeper’s choice of customer), it is the principle of termfreedom
- •Intervention in particular cases.
- •Viewed as competitive transactions, are to be subject to rather more regulation
- •In Schuler V Wickman. We can also see this principle at work in regulating
- •V Hyland).
- •Impose an absolute obligation to work 48 hours’ overtime per week on
- •Irrelevant.4
- •In the cases so far considered, the parties are free to decide whether or not to
- •In his judgment in Trentham V Archital Luxfer,12 Steyn lj appears to position
- •It can be converted into a binding contract by the simple response ‘I accept’.
Invention – if a way out of a tight corner has to be found, then it will be found.
Adams and Brownsword continue as follows:
Realism is the antithesis of formalism. It follows that each of the formalist
tendencies is matched by a realist tendency which pushes in the opposite
direction.
First, the rule book is not decisive. The most important aspects of a dispute are
the facts and the decision; rules are a secondary consideration. If formalism is
rule-orientated, realism is result-orientated. In many ways, Lord Devlin’s
observation that ‘The true spirit of the common law is to override theoretical
distinctions when they stand in the way of doing practical justice’ (Ingram v
Little (1961)) enshrines the realist articles of faith.
Secondly, the logic of the rule-book concepts is by no means the be-all and endall.
Immediately, one thinks here of Lord Denning’s criticisms of traditional
offer and acceptance analysis, and of his cavalier exploits with regard to
consideration. But Lord Denning is not alone in such a realist disregard for the
logic of the concepts. For example, the logic of the concepts did not prevent the
majority finding the required contractual connection in The Eurymedon, nor did
it stop the House of Lords finding a remedy for Mrs Beswick.
Thirdly, realists do not regard blotting the rule-book as the ultimate sin. If
practical justice demands some running repairs, then the elegance or
conceptual neatness of the solution hardly matters. What matters is that the
repair job works. Formalists may pour scorn on such realist patch-up jobs as
the device of the collateral contract or the doctrine of the fundamental term,
but realists can take such criticisms without flinching. Realists know a
spatchcock solution when they see one, but a solution is at least a solution.
Fourthly, realism tends towards doctrinal and conceptual innovation. Judges
are not to be discouraged from sowing new doctrinal seeds (for example,
13 Adams and Brownsword, 2000, pp 168–70.
6
What is Contract Law All About?
promissory estoppel, unconscionability, economic duress, the doctrine of the
innominate term) simply because it is not clear how the doctrinal plant will
grow. Nor are judges to be discouraged from cultivating newly born ideas. If a
recent innovation supports a particular decision, then there is no reason to
eschew such support in favour of a traditional ground for the same decision.
Fifthly, for realist judges, ‘sympathy and politics’ do matter. It is all very well
complaining that hard cases make bad law; but if judges ignore the obvious
merits of a case, practical justice goes by the board and the law is rightly
accused of being an ass. Likewise, politics, broadly interpreted, do count.
Where a judge considers a particular rule or its application unfair, or
Inconvenient, he should recognise the force of these considerations. On the
realist view, judges must act as custodians of practical justice and convenience,
not simply as the keepers of the code.
Sixthly, for realists, the mechanical and uncritical adoption and application of
the rule book will not do. Rules are laid down for a purpose, to defend some
principle or to support some policy. When rules no longer serve their intended
purpose, when they become detached from their point, slavish adherence to
the rule book undermines the spirit of their enactment. The drive towards
consumer protection is the outstanding example of a realist recognition that
the world changes and that, in a changing social context, the original intent of
the rules may become perverted by their continued uncritical application. (To
avoid misunderstanding, we should emphasise that realists are not tied to the
purposes underpinning the rule book. In the final analysis, the rule-book,
whether read literally or purposively, is marginal to realism.)
Seventhly, realism is not necessarily inconvenienced by a rule-book which is
riddled with discretions. At least, for realists of a consumer-welfarist
persuasion, if the rules enjoin judges to decide according to the canons of
reasonableness, fairness, conscionability, and the like, this is no problem, for it