Добавил:
Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:

oxford handbook of bioethics

.pdf
Скачиваний:
4
Добавлен:
19.12.2024
Размер:
9.94 Mб
Скачать

42 JA M E S F. C H I L D R E S S

not merely as isolated individuals, who consent or refuse to consent, but also as members of communities. Individuals are embedded, to varying degrees, in their communities with various traditions, beliefs, values, and practices, and respect for cultural values is important. However, it is not possible or justifiable to determine an individual’s wishes and choices by reading them off community traditions, beliefs, values, and practices, and it is not ethically acceptable to subordinate the individual’s autonomy to the community’s will without satisfying stringent justificatory conditions. Similar points can be made about other basic bioethical principles: each one can be interpreted through the lens of relationships and community. For instance, researchers should recognize that some communities can be harmed in genetics research — for example, through stigmatization — in violation of the principles of beneficence and non-maleficence, and that the principle of justice may require involving such communities to participate in the design of genetics research involving their members.

CONCLUSIONS

• • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • •

Significant conflicts remain about which bioethical method, if any, provides the best guidance for decisions and actions in clinical and policy settings. From the standpoint of action guidance, as well as other criteria, each method has significant problems, and yet each method is also helpful in some respects, particularly in identifying relevant features of agents, actions, ends, consequences, contexts, and relationships that merit attention in deciding and acting. Furthermore, several methods overlap with each other, or converge, or supplement each other. It is probably too much to expect consensus about the best possible method(s), all things considered — at most, we can take advantage of the strengths of each method and compensate for its special deficiencies.

REFERENCES

ARRAS, J. D. (1991), ‘Getting Down to Cases: The Revival of Casuistry in Bioethics’, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 16: 29 – 51.

(1994), ‘Principles and Particularity: The Role of Cases in Bioethics’, Indiana Law Journal, 69: 983 – 1014.

(1998), ‘A Case Approach’, in H. Kuhse and P. Singer (eds.), A Companion to Bioethics (Oxford: Blackwell), 106 – 14.

BAIER, A. C. (1985), Postures of the Mind: Essays on Mind and Morals (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press).

(1994), Moral Prejudices: Essays on Ethics (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press).

M E T H O D S I N B I O E T H I C S 43

BEAUCHAMP, T. L. (2000), ‘Response to Strong on Principlism and Casuistry’, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 25: 342 – 7.

and CHILDRESS, J. F. (1979 – 2001), Principles of Biomedical Ethics, (1st – 5th edns. New York: Oxford University Press).

BLUM, L. (2001), ‘Care’, in L. C. Becker and C. B. Becker (eds.), Encyclopedia of Ethics, (2nd edn. New York: Routledge), 185 – 7.

BRANDT, R. B. (1992), ‘Public Policy and Life and Death Decisions Regarding Defective Newborns’, in Brandt, Morality, Utilitarianism, and Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 354 – 69.

BRODY, B. (1988), Life and Death Decision Making (New York: Oxford University Press). (2003), Taking Issue: Pluralism and Casuistry in Bioethics (Washington, DC: Geor-

getown University Press).

CALLAHAN, D. (2003), ‘Principlism and Communitarianism’, Journal of Medical Ethics, 29: 287 – 91.

CARSE, A. L. (1991), ‘The ‘‘Voice of Care’’: Implications for Bioethical Education’, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 16: 5 – 28.

CHAMBERS, T. (1999), The Fiction of Bioethics: Cases as Literary Texts (New York: Routledge). CHILDRESS, J. F. (1982), Who Should Decide? Paternalism in Health Care (New York: Oxford

University Press).

MESLIN, E. M., and SHAPIRO, H. T. (eds.) (2005), Belmont Revisited: Ethical Principles for Research with Human Subjects (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press).

CLOUSER, K. D., and GERT, B. (1990), ‘A Critique of Principlism’, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 15: 219 – 36.

DEGRAZIA, D. (1992), ‘Moving Forward in Bioethical Theory: Theories, Cases, and Specified Principlism’, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 17: 511 – 39.

DUBOSE, E. R., HAMEL, R., and O’CONNELL, L. J. (eds.) (1994), A Matter of Principles? Ferment in U.S. Bioethics (Valley Forge, Pa.: Trinity Press International).

EMANUEL, E. J. (1992), The Ends of Human Life: Medical Ethics in a Liberal Polity (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press).

and WEIJER, C. (2005), ‘Protecting Communities in Research: From a New Principle to Rational Protections’, in Childress et al. (2005: 165 – 83).

ENGELHARDT, H. T. (1986), Foundations of Bioethics (New York: Oxford University Press). FLETCHER, J. (1966), Situation Ethics: The New Morality (Philadelphia: Westminster Press). FOOT, P. (1977), ‘Euthanasia’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 6: 85 – 112.

FRANKENA, W. K. (1973), Ethics, (2nd edn. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall).

GERT, B. (1989), Morality: A New Justification of the Moral Rules (New York: Oxford University Press).

and CULVER, C. (1979), ‘The Justification of Paternalism’, Ethics, 89: 199 – 210. et al. (1996), Morality and the New Genetics (Sudbury, Mass.: Jones and Bartlett).

CLOUSER, K. D., and CULVER, C. (1997), Bioethics: A Return to Fundamentals (New York: Oxford University Press).

GILLIGAN, C. (1982), In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development

(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press).

GILLON, R. (1994), ‘Medical Ethics: Four Principles Plus Attention to Scope’, British Medical Journal, 309: 184 – 8.

(ed.) and LLOYD, A. (asst. ed.) (1994), Principles of Health Care Ethics (Chichester: John Wiley).

44 JA M E S F. C H I L D R E S S

HARE, R. M. (1989), ‘Principles’, in Hare, Essays in Ethical Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press), 49 – 65.

(1996), ‘The Methods of Bioethics: Some Defective Proposals’, in L. W. Sumner and J. Boyle (eds.), Philosophical Perspectives on Bioethics ( Toronto: University of Toronto Press), 18 – 36.

HOOKER, B. (2002), Ideal Code, Real World: A Rule-Consequentialist Theory of Morality

(Oxford: Oxford University Press).

HURSTHOUSE, R. (2001), On Virtue Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

(2003), ‘Virtue Ethics’, in E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2003), <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2003/entries/ethics-virtue/>, accessed 8 Oct. 2005.

JANSEN, L. A. (2003), ‘The Virtues in Their Place: Virtue Ethics in Medicine’, Theoretical Medicine, 21: 261 – 76.

JOHN PAUL II, POPE (1995), Evangelium vitae ( The Vatican).

JONSEN, A. R. (1991), ‘Casuistry as Methodology in Clinical Ethics’, Theoretical Medicine, 12/4: 295 – 307.

and TOULMIN, S. (1988), The Abuse of Casuistry (Berkeley: University of California Press).

JAMA (1988), ‘It’s Over, Debbie’, 259/2: 272.

KAUFERT, J. K., and KOCH, T. (2003), ‘Disability or End-of-Life: Competing Narratives in Bioethics’, Theoretical Medicine, 24: 459 – 69.

KOPELMAN, L. M. (1994), ‘Case Method and Casuistry: The Problem of Bias’, Theoretical Medicine, 15: 21 – 37.

KUCZEWSKI, M. G. (1997), Fragmentation and Consensus: Communitarian and Casuist Bioethics (Washington: Georgetown University Press).

(1998), ‘Casuistry and Principlism: The Convergence of Method in Biomedical Ethics’,

Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 19: 504 – 24.

(2001), ‘The Epistemology of Communitarian Bioethics: Traditions in the Public Debates’, Theoretical Medicine, 22: 135 – 50.

LOUDEN, R. (1984), ‘On Some Vices of Virtue Ethics’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 21: 227 – 36.

MACKENZIE, C., and STOLJAR, N. (eds.) (2000), Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self (New York: Oxford University Press).

MANNING, R. C. (1998), ‘A Care Approach’, in H. Kuhse and P. Singer (eds.), A Companion to Bioethics (Oxford: Blackwell), 98 – 105.

NATIONAL COMMISSION FOR THE PROTECTION OF HUMAN SUBJECTS OF BIOMEDICAL AND

BEHAVIORAL RESEARCH (1978), The Belmont Report: Ethical Guidelines for the Protection of Human Subjects of Research, DHEW publication no. (OS) 78 – 00 (Washington, DC: Department of Health Education and Welfare).

OAKLEY, J. (1998), ‘A Virtue Ethics Approach’, in H. Kuhse and P. Singer (eds.), A Companion to Bioethics (Oxford: Blackwell), 86 – 97.

O’NEILL, O. (2002), Autonomy and Trust in Bioethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

PELLEGRINO, E. D. (1995), ‘Toward a Virtue-Based Normative Ethics for the Health Professions’, Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 5/3: 253 – 77.

M E T H O D S I N B I O E T H I C S 45

(1998), ‘The False Promise of Beneficent Killing in Regulating How We Die’, in L. Emanuel (ed.), Regulating How We Die (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press), 71 – 91.

QUILL, T. (1991), ‘Death and Dignity: A Case of Individualized Decision Making’, New England Journal of Medicine, 324: 691 – 4.

RAMSEY, P. (1968), ‘The Case of the Curious Exception’, in G. Outka and P. Ramsey (eds.),

Norm and Context in Christian Ethics (New York: Charles Scribner’s). (1970), The Patient as Person (New Haven: Yale University Press). (1978), Ethic at the Edges of Life (New Haven: Yale University Press).

RICHARDSON, H. S. (1990), ‘Specifying Norms as a Way to Resolve Concrete Ethical Problems’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 19: 279 – 20.

(2000), ‘Specifying, Balancing, and Interpreting Bioethical Principles’, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 25: 285 – 307.

SHERWIN, S. (1992), No Longer Patient: Feminist Ethics and Health Care (Philadelphia: Temple University Press).

SIDGWICK, H. (1962), The Methods of Ethics (London: Macmillan).

(1998), Practical Ethics: A Collection of Addresses and Essays (New York: Oxford University Press).

SINGER, P. (1993), Practical Ethics, (2nd edn. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). SLOTE, M. (1997), ‘Virtue Ethics’, in M. W. Baron, P. Pettit, and M. Slote, Three Methods of

Ethics (Oxford: Blackwell), 175 – 238.

SOLOMON, W. D. (1978), ‘Rules and Principles’, in W. T. Reich (ed.), Encyclopedia of Bioethics, i (New York: Free Press), 407 – 13.

STRONG, C. (2000), ‘Specified Principlism: What Is It, and Does It Really Resolve Cases Better Than Casuistry?’, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 25: 324 – 41.

SULMASY, D. P. (2001), ‘Research in Medical Ethics: Physician-Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia’, in J. Sugarman and D. P. Sulmasy OFM (eds.), Methods in Medical Ethics (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press), 247 – 66.

SUMNER, L. W., and BOYLE, J. (1996), ‘Introduction’, in Sumner and Boyle (eds.), Philosophical Perspectives on Bioethics ( Toronto: University of Toronto Press), 18 – 36.

TOULMIN, S. (1981), ‘The Tyranny of Principles’, Hastings Center Report, 11/6: 31 – 9. VEATCH, R. M. (1981), A Theory of Medical Ethics (New York: Basic Books).

(1995), ‘Resolving Conflicts Among Principles: Ranking, Balancing, and Specifying’,

Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 5/3: 199 – 218.

(2005), ‘Ranking, Balancing, or Simultaneity’, in Childress et al. (2005: 184 – 204). WARNOCK, G. J. (1971), The Object of Morality (London: Methuen).

WILDES, K. W. (2000), Moral Acquaintances: Methodology in Bioethics (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press).

c h a p t e r 2

• • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • •

T H E WAY W E

R E A S O N N OW:

R E F L E C T I V E

E Q U I L I B R I U M I N

B I O E T H I C S

• • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • •

J O H N D . A R R A S

IN the world of bioethics, the air is abuzz with reflective equilibrium. Not too long ago, this same air echoed the din of clashing moral methodologies. Casuists,1 feminists,2 narrativists,3 and pragmatists4 had been collectively engaged in a tag

This chapter is dedicated to the memory of John Fletcher. Many thanks to Alex London and Bonnie Steinbock for helpful discussion along the way.

1 Casuistry in bioethics has been championed by Albert Jonsen and Stephen Toulmin as an alternative methodology to principlism, one that supposedly works from the ‘bottom up’ by means of analogical case analyses, much like the common law, rather than ‘top down’ by means of moral theories and theoretically derived principles. (See Jonsen and Toulmin 1988; Arras 1991.)

2 Feminist criticism in bioethics has focused primarily on gender-related power imbalances in the health care system. As contributors to the debate over method in bioethics, feminist critics of principlism have lamented the latter’s alleged overemphasis on abstract principle and neglect of personal relations, the emotions, and power in the analysis of moral problems. Many feminists are also moral particularists, and thus have much in common with casuists and narrativists. (See e.g. Wolf 1995.)

3 Narrative ethics, like casuistry, gives pride of place to the particularities of persons and social contexts as these are articulated within personal narratives. The emphasis here is on the trajectory of the ‘patient’s story’, rather than on the abstractions of theory and principles. (See Arras 1997.)

4 Bioethical pragmatists embrace the rejection of epistemological and ethical foundationalism that they find in traditional pragmatists like John Dewey and William James. They view ethical principles as

T H E WAY W E R E A S O N N OW 47

team debunking exercise at the expense of the embattled defenders of principlism, the heretofore dominant method in the field of practical ethics (Beauchamp and Childress 1979 – 2001). These methodological malcontents shared a common core of grievances: Principlism was too abstract, deductive, and ‘top down’; it was insufficiently attentive to particulars, relationships, storytelling, and process. Each claimant to the throne adamantly pressed its case for methodological supremacy in bioethics. In response, the avatars of principlism, Tom Beauchamp and James Childress, politely thanked all their critics for making so many truly helpful suggestions, assuring them that they would each be respectfully subsumed into principlism’s evolving grand synthesis. Each hostile critique would, however, first have to be shorn of its excesses before being assigned its very own section in the next edition of Principles of Biomedical Ethics. Thus, to the casuists, Beauchamp and Childress granted that principles not only ruled over case judgments but were actually derived from particular intuitions in a dialectic between ‘top down’ and ‘bottom up’. To the feminists, they conceded the importance of relationships and the need to address inequality and domination in the relations between the sexes. To the partisans of narrative ethics, they affirmed the importance of narrative detail for the successful deployment and specification of principles. And, finally, to the pragmatists, they admitted the flexible, tool-like nature of principles, and the indispensability of good judgment in their application (Arras 2002).

Central to this project of principlist assimilation was the notion of reflective equilibrium (henceforth, RE), a method of doing moral and political philosophy originally developed by the great political philosopher John Rawls (1971, 1975). According to Rawls, the project of justifying ethical beliefs ideally involves the attempt to bring our most confident ethical judgments, our ethical principles, and our background social, psychological, and philosophical theories into a state of harmony or equilibrium. Our most confident moral judgments or intuitions (e.g. ‘Slavery is wrong’) provide a touchstone for the adequacy of our principles; any moral principle that justified slavery would be either reformulated or rejected. Meanwhile, principles invested with a great deal of confidence could be used to reject some conflicting intuitions while extending our ability to judge confidently in less familiar moral settings. We thus zip back and forth, nipping an intuitive judgment here, tucking a principle there, building up or reformulating a theory in the background, until all the disparate elements of our moral assessments are brought into a more or less steady state of harmonious equilibrium. According to this view, moral justification must be sought, not in secure, incorrigible foundations outside of our processes of reflection, but rather in the coherence of all the flotsam and jetsam of our moral life.

flexible tools that evolve over time in the service of social problem solving, rather than as absolute dos and don’ts; and they tend to emphasize the importance of democratic process as well as the substance of ethical judgments. (See McGee 2003.) It should go without saying that all of these brief vignettes in nn. 1 – 4 are hopelessly oversimplified.

48 J O H N D . A R R A S

Although Rawls limited the deployment of RE to the theoretical construction of his social contract theory, applied ethicists in many fields have more recently taken up this method as a vehicle for solving practical moral problems in their respective disciplines. (See e.g. Benjamin 2002; Nussbaum 1992; Daniels 1996; van der Burg and van Willigenburg 1998.) Although this more practical deployment of RE might raise eyebrows among those philosophers who view ethical theory and practical ethics as existing on two entirely different planes, it has made perfect sense for the growing number of practical ethicists who regard their work as existing on a continuum with that of theorists in normative ethics. It has, in fact, become something of a commonplace for philosophers straddling the theoretical and practical domains to remark that their modes of thinking and justification are pretty much identical in both areas, even if the role of abstraction is obviously greater in the domain of theory construction (Beauchamp 1984; Brock 1995). Although there is no doubt much to be said on behalf of this claimed continuity between practical and theoretical ethics, it remains to be seen whether RE, at least in its most expansive contemporary manifestations, can serve the theorist and practical ethicist equally well. As I explain below, I have my doubts on this score.

One of the many attractions of RE as a method in practical ethics has been its ability to appeal to just about every faction in the method wars. It is agreeably flexible, non-dogmatic, and non-foundationalist in claiming that there are no incorrigible elements of morality on which everything else must be grounded and from which all justification flows. It enforces an appealing egalitarianism with regard to all the various elements of our belief systems, including our beliefs about particular cases, moral principles, and background theories. Within the method of RE, there are no privileged beliefs. Every belief is fair game for pruning in the service of more strongly held beliefs of the same or other kinds. Thus, casuists are happy to hear that intuitive case judgments are crucially important in moral justification; principlists are pleased with the robust role of moral principles; and high-flying philosophers and social theorists are relieved to hear that there’s even a place for background theorizing about the nature of persons and society. It was thus no great surprise, then, when Beauchamp and Childress, confronting that unruly mob of rival methodologists gesticulating from the other side of the moat, hoisted the unifying flag of RE, declaring it to be henceforth the method of principlism in bioethics (4th edn., 1994). All our methodological differences would henceforth merely be matters of emphasis. We would all just be fellow bozos on Neurath’s boat — out at sea, unable to reach dry dock where foundational work could be done, we patch, mend, and stitch our moral bark with the disparate materials at hand.5 As Mark Kuczewski observed at the time, ‘Who could ask for anything more?’ (1997).

5 ‘We are like sailors who on the open sea must reconstruct their ship but are never able to start afresh from the bottom. Where a beam is taken away a new one must at once be put there, and for this the rest of the ship is used as support. In this way, by using the old beams and driftwood the ship can be shaped entirely anew, but only by gradual reconstruction’ (Neurath 1966).

T H E WAY W E R E A S O N N OW 49

Indeed, who could ask for more than this? As a philosopher, however, my job is to make life more difficult for people, so I will proceed to ask some hard questions about the method of RE in practical ethics. I do this not simply to make trouble, but rather because this method raises some very difficult and troubling questions which I shall explore below. I do so with some trepidation, however, because I have previously recommended a modest version of this very method (Arras 2003), and I am hard-pressed to identify a better way of justifying our judgments of right and wrong in practical ethics. I begin, then, with some preliminary remarks about the general features and basic varieties of RE in moral reflection. I shall then consider a couple of preliminary doubts about this method. One claims that the most plausible interpretation of RE is so comprehensive that it risks paralyzing our thinking, while the other claims that this same version of RE is insufficiently determinate in practical contexts and will thus fail to be sufficiently action-guiding. I then proceed to explicate the sense in which RE qualifies as a coherence theory of justification, and I consider several objections to RE that flow from its reliance on the putative connection between coherence and moral justification. I will then bring this chapter to a close with some reflections on the very idea of method in ethics — that is, on what we might realistically expect of methodology as a vehicle to advance justification and truth in the domain of practical ethics.

STA N DA RD FEAT U RE S OF RE E C T I VE

EQUILIBR IUM

• • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • •

Considered Judgments and Principles in RE

In his first paper devoted to a ‘decision procedure’ in ethics, Rawls elaborated an interesting picture of the relationship between moral principles and the intuitive or ‘considered’ judgments out of which they develop (1951). We begin, says Rawls, with a notion of ‘competent moral judges’ — i.e. people who are intelligent, impartial, reasonable, well informed, imaginative, empathetic, and so on. Now, let us assume, first, that these judges are capable of filtering out their less plausible moral judgments. They are on guard against operating under conditions that usually yield bad or untrustworthy decisions — i.e. they are not judging in haste, under a cloud of intense emotions, driven by their own self-interest, and so on. Let us then suppose that these competent judges confront a wide spectrum of moral situations or cases and deliver judgments based not upon some sort of sophisticated theory or set of principles, but rather, assuming there to be such, simply upon their direct, unmediated, most reliable intuitions of right and wrong. Later on, in A Theory of Justice, Rawls calls these responses ‘considered moral judgments’ — i.e. those moral judgments in which we have the most confidence (1971: 47/1999: 42). Although

50 J O H N D . A R R A S

Rawls, as always, is loath to cite concrete examples here, the paradigm cases might be examples of free speech, religious liberty, and racial equality. Putting it mildly, a competent moral judge would look unfavorably upon both the goals and methods of the Spanish Inquisition. Forcing all people to abandon their own visions of the good and the nature of the universe at the altar of Catholic orthodoxy — and to do so by threatening the rack, thumbscrew, or burning pyre — would definitely strike our competent moral judges as being morally out of bounds. So the initial ‘data’ of moral reflection are these intuitive judgments of competent judges directed at various cases. A good bioethical example of this would be our intuitive negative responses to the infamous Tuskegee syphilis study, in which US government researchers charted the doleful effects of untreated syphilis in black sharecroppers over a period of forty years.

The next step in the method is to develop moral principles that ‘match’, ‘explicate’, ‘accord with’, ‘fit’, or ‘account for’ the body of intuitions amassed by competent moral judges. Thus, a principle of religious freedom might explicate the fact that various competent moral judges would intuitively condemn the torture and burning of heretics and similar behaviors. Rawls likens this process to the inductive scientific method, whereby inquirers assemble a set of observation statements or data points, and then attempt to formulate a principle or mathematical function that best makes sense of them. According to this interpretation of RE, moral principles are hypotheses advanced to make sense of the set of considered moral judgments of competent judges. Principles ‘explain’ moral judgments if we could deduce exactly the same judgments just from the principles and relevant facts alone, without the benefit of any moral intuitions or sentiments. In short, moral principles are supposed to yield conclusions in particular cases that would match our considered judgments. If our suggested principles mesh perfectly with our considered judgments, then we are in equilibrium; if they don’t fit, then we have to amend either our particular moral judgments or our principles, depending upon which element of our moral system merits the most confidence.

In addition to their explanatory function sketched above, moral principles also have normative functions within the framework of RE. First, principles that have been forged over time in the crucible of RE can help us recognize and reject mistaken moral judgments; second, Rawls asserts that principles should help us resolve moral perplexities posed by conflicting intuitions in difficult cases. Deploying a set of firmly held principles can assist us in extending the reach of our convictions, even in those situations where we initially lack confidence in our judgments.

A number of questions arise with regard to this initial Rawlsian sketch of RE. First, it is reasonable to ask whether our considered judgments about cases really present themselves in isolation from more ‘theoretical’ considerations in the way that Rawls initially suggested they might (1951). I suspect, with Brian Barry, that most such intuitive judgments about cases already harbor the germ of some sort of larger, quasi-theoretical reflection. For example, our repulsion at the burning of heretics

T H E WAY W E R E A S O N N OW 51

or at the withholding of proven treatment from syphilitic black sharecroppers is not some sort of brute ‘datum’, but is rather most likely a reaction already suffused with the ‘quasi-theoretical’ judgment that the Inquisition and Tuskegee violated, inter alia, important moral norms mandating equality among human beings (Barry 1989: 264; Arras 1991).

Conversely, it is equally problematic to assert that moral principles can be relied upon to yield, exclusively on the basis of the relevant facts, the very same conclusions reached by confidently uttered case judgments. Just as case judgments are infused with quasi-theoretical elements, so principles, in order to actually reach practical conclusions in concrete circumstances, must be supplemented with all sorts of judgments, intuitions, and analogous comparisons with other cases. Although we might be able to ‘derive’ or ‘deduce’ correct practical conclusions from principles in clear-cut cases of moral evil like the Tuskegee experiment, we cannot do so in hard cases involving conflicting principles or difficult problems of interpretation — that is, in precisely those cases that provide the grist for most bioethical reasoning.

A second problem with Rawls’s initial formulation of RE is his claim that moral principles should be understood as hypotheses developed to explain or match whatever deeply felt intuitions we happen to have (Barry 1989: 263). At the least, proponents of RE need to explain how moral intuitions can play the same justificatory role as observation statements in the physical sciences, each one providing its own particular kind of basic ‘datum’ for further theorizing. (I shall say more about this issue later on.) Even some of the most zealous defenders of RE have abandoned this suggested analogy between observation statements in science and considered moral judgments (Daniels 1979). More plausible recent expositions of RE simply acknowledge the existence of most of our commonsensical moral principles — e.g. keep promises, respect autonomous choices — and then attempt to show what is valuable and important about the norms they articulate and to state the best reasons why it is wrong to violate them (Scanlon 1992). In other words, instead of deploying RE to discover new principles, these theorists harness RE for the more modest but still crucially important task of becoming more reflective about the meaning, functions, and justifications of whatever moral principles we happen to endorse. Sometimes the process of RE will reveal that we have misunderstood the values protected by a principle, and this will have implications for what the principle is now taken to sanction. More rarely, this process may reveal that we have simply given up entirely on the reasons behind a principle (‘Shield your patients from troubling diagnoses’), and at that point we jettison the principle.

Finally, and most importantly, it is unclear how RE, as explicated so far, has any serious normative bite. At best, such a bouncing-back-and-forth between considered judgments and derivative principles will yield a fully rounded inventory of our collected moral intuitions, but the justification of those very intuitions remains unsettled. It is a commonplace that people often feel supremely confident in their most basic moral judgments, but it is unsettling, to say the least, to acknowledge

Соседние файлы в предмете [НЕСОРТИРОВАННОЕ]