- •Lesson 1
- •Lesson 2
- •Lesson 3
- •Lesson 4
- •Lesson 5
- •Lesson 6- colloquium Text 1- Case law
- •Text 2- How do judges really decide cases?
- •Text 3- Equity
- •Plan for Text 3
- •Lesson 7
- •Lesson 8
- •Lesson 9 Summary of Text 3 (Unit 2)
- •Task 1 (c), Task 2, Task 4 Article
- •Lesson 10
- •Lesson 11
- •Lesson 12
- •Task 1 b
- •The cases mentioned in the text (there are 2 cases)
- •Montesquieu and his work of separation of powers
Text 2- How do judges really decide cases?
The independence of the judiciary was ensured by the Act of Settlement 1700, which transferred the power to sack judges from the Crown to Parliament. Consequently, judges should theoretically make their decisions based purely on the logical deductions of precedent, uninfluenced by political or career considerations.
William Blackstone introduced the declaratory theory of law, stating that judges do not make law, but merely, by the rules of precedent, discover and declare the law that has always been.
Blackstone does not accept that precedent ever offers a choice between two or more interpretations of the law. His view presupposes that there is always one right answer, to be deduced from an objective study of precedent.
Today, however, this position is considered somewhat unrealistic. If the operation of precedent is the precise science a large majority of cases in the higher courts would never come to court at all. Если бы действие прецедента было точной наукой, подавляющее большинство дел в высших судах вообще никогда бы не дошло до суда. The lawyers concerned could simply look up the relevant case law and predict what the decision would be, then advise whichever of the clients would be bound to lose not to bother bringing or fighting the case. Заинтересованные юристы могли просто просмотреть соответствующее прецедентное право и предсказать, каким будет решение, а затем посоветовать тому из клиентов, который обречен на проигрыш, не беспокоить возбуждение дела или борьбу с ним.
Further evidence of this is provided by the fact that one can read a judgment of the Court of Appeal, argued as though it were the only possible decision in the light of the cases that had gone before, and then discover that this apparently inevitable decision has promptly been reversed by the House of Lords. Дополнительным свидетельством этого является тот факт, что можно прочитать решение апелляционного суда, аргументированное так, как будто это единственно возможное решение в свете предыдущих дел, а затем обнаружить, что это очевидно неизбежное решение было принято. был немедленно отменен Палатой лордов.
In practice, then, judges’ decisions may not be as neutral as Blackstone’s declaratory theory suggests: they have to make choices which are by no means spelt out by precedents.
Judges themselves still cling to the image of themselves as neutral decision-makers, even though they admit that there are choices to be made. In a 1972 lecture Lord Reid agreed that the declaratory theory was something of a ‘fairytale’, but argued that ‘everyone agrees that impartiality is the first essential in any judge. And that means not only that he must not appear to favour either party. It also means that he must not take sides on political issues. Judges must play safe. They must decide the case on the preponderance of existing authority’.
Judges should have regard to common sense, legal principle and public policy in that order’. But common sense may be as much a value judgment as public interest.