
ИГПЗС учебный год 2023 / Прецедент в 18-19 веках (статья)
.odtonly shew the opinions of the writers, yet all precedents which
are brought into argument are of the same authority. Their
weight depends much upon the age in which they were written, and
the character of the writers."233
Arguments of counsel reproduced in state reporters also
give evidence that practitioners considered the maxim stare
decisis not as a fixed and unyielding rule, but as a maxim that
had to be weighed with other maxims and principles in order to
reach a just outcome in a particular case. Thus we see counsel
in Connecticut arguing: "The precedent, however, will have its
due weight, in proportion to the soundness of the reasons, on
231 Wood v. Bullock, 10 N.C. 298, 299 (N.C., 1824).
232 Means v. Trout, 16 Serg. & Rawle 349, 350 (1827). Cf.
Hobbs v. Middleton, 24 Ky. 176, 185 (1829): "[W]e shall not be
much embarrassed by the maxim, 'stare decisis et non quieta
movere.' For, we do not consider it as applicable to such a
question as that now under consideration, and to such decisions as
those which have been rendered upon it." Id.
233 State v. Owen, 5 N.C. 452, 463 (Taylor, J., dissenting).
89
which it was founded, and the number and respectability of the
judges, who acted upon it."234 Counsel in Virginia in 1807
asserted: "Stare decisis is a rule which I hold in as much
respect as any man in the Commonwealth; but there are cases in
which it may be necessary to depart from it."235
These cases demonstrate that stare decisis, termed
variously a maxim, or a principle, or a rule of law, was not
understood as a doctrine that exerted binding authority on the
courts. Courts, rather, engaged in a process of weighing and
balancing competing considerations. The vocabulary the courts
employed was not one of strict obligation, or absolute adherence;
rather, the vocabulary is one of proportionality, due weight,
measuring and balancing. Again, the explanation for this
vocabulary is to be sought in the jurisprudential foundations of
the time. The early American Republic came of age at a time
before the ascendancy of the strict positivism, the
instrumentalism, and the utilitarian doctrines of a later age.
As we have made clear throughout this Article, what mattered more
at this stage in American history was fidelity to theories of
234 Fitch v. Brainerd, 2 Day 163 (Ct. 1805) [page reference to
be supplied].
235 Eldridge v. Fisher, 11 Va. 559 (1807) [page reference to
be supplied]. One might compare this form of argument with the
following: "The maxim stare decisis is of peculiar weight in
commercial questions, in which, perhaps more than in any others,
it is more important that the law be settled, than in how it is
settled." Oliver v. Newburyport Insurance Company, 3 Mass. 37
(Mass., 1837) [full reference to be supplied].
90
natural justice and natural law.
III. Conclusion:
This Article can now be fitted within the scholarship
on the history of stare decisis and precedent. It differs from
the early scholarship on the subject by taking seriously the
first premises of this older conception of precedent and stare
decisis. Thus Frederick Kempin takes as normative a strict
doctrine of precedent and searches for its origins in early
American judicial opinions.236 Using the strict doctrine as his
model, Kempin concluded: "One can summarize by saying that
American cases, up to the year 1800, had no firm doctrine of
stare decisis."237 In proceeding on these premises and claiming
these historical objectives, Kempin's work might even be called
by that indelicate term "Whig history."238 As this Article makes
clear, however, English and American courts most certainly had a
conception of stare decisis; it was not, however, the strict
doctrine that would come to prevail at a later time in American
history. And, indeed, it is hoped that this Article's review of
the jurisprudential foundations of this older way of viewing
stare decisis establishes the extent to which this now vanished
236 Supra note --.
237 Id., at 50.
238 See generally, HERBERT BUTTERFIELD, THE WHIG
INTERPRETATION OF HISTORY (1931).
91
thought-world was a rich and coherent one on its own terms.
In some respects, this Article may serve as a
complement to the studies of Gerald Postema239 and Jim Evans.240
Postema, like Kempin, takes as normative a strict doctrine of
precedent and traces its roots back into the philosophical
speculations of Thomas Hobbes and Jeremy Bentham.241 Postema
labels the older school of thought that we have been examining
the "traditionary doctrine of precedent," and associates it with
English common lawyers like the seventeenth-century Sir Matthew
Hale.242 While I have eschewed the label traditionary doctrine of
precedent, my investigation complements Postema's in that it
studies the main premises of this doctrine. Unlike Kempin,
Postema takes the "traditionary doctrine" seriously although he
does relatively little with it. This Article in a sense remedies
this deficiency in the literature. This Article,
similarly, has some affinities with Jim Evans' study of precedent
in the nineteenth century. Evans uses some of the English cases
we examined in the course of this Article as background to his
239 Gerald J. Postema, "Roots of Our Notion of Precedent," in
PRECEDENT IN LAW 9 (Laurence Goldstein, ed., 1991).
240 Jim Evans, "Change in the Doctrine of Precedent During the
Nineteenth Century," in PRECEDENT IN LAW, supra --, at 35-72.
241 Postema, supra note --, at 11-15 (reviewing Hobbes in the
context of examining the "positive conception of precedent"); and
at 13-16 (examining Bentham).
242 Id., at 15-23.
92
investigation of the emergence of a positivist account of
precedent.243 In my own case, once again, rather than use this
material merely as a starting-point for the investigation of
recent developments, I have chosen to consider the older
materials on their own terms.
This Article also has affinities with the historical
sections of Caleb Nelson's important article, "Stare Decisis and
Demonstrably Erroneous Precedents."244 Unlike the other studies
of precedent and stare decisis that I have mentioned, Nelson
recognizes the significance of what he calls "the external
sources of the common law" -- by which means reason and natural
law -- to the story he wishes to tell.245 This Article builds on
Nelson's insight by exploring, in much greater detail than he
does, the role these "external sources" played in judicial
reasoning at the time of the Founding.
Having a proper appreciation of the history of stare
decisis and precedent is not a merely academic concern but in
fact matters greatly to the outcome of cases today. I might thus
close by considering the very different treatments of stare
decisis found in the reasoning of two recent -- and highly
243 Evans, supra note --, at 35-47 (reviewing the older
English materials).
244 Caleb Nelson, "Stare Decisis and Demonstrably Erroneous
Precedents," 87 VA. L. REV. 1, 21-45 (2001).
245 Id., at 28.
93
controversial -- cases, Anastasoff v. United States246 and Hart v.
Massanari.247 The Court in Anastasoff concluded that not only
published opinions of the Court but also every unpublished
opinion must, as a matter of originalist constitutional
interpretation, be considered as creating binding precedent.248
This much, the Anastasoff Court asserted, was the implicit
understanding of the conferral of "judicial power" upon Article
III judges at the time of the Founding.249 In support of this
contention, the Anastasoff Court cited some of the authorities
discussed in the body of this Article, including especially
William Blackstone,250 James Wilson,251 and even Chancellor Kent.252
The Anastasoff Court can be criticized for reaching the
conclusion it did. It can fairly be said that the Anastasoff
Court adopted what might be called a "presentist" reading of
246 Anastasoff v. United States, 223 F. 3d 898 (8th Cir.,
2000).
247 Hart v. Massanari, 266 F. 3d. 1155 (9th Cir., 2001).
248 Id., at 899-900 ("Inherent in every judicial decision is a
declaration and interpretation of a general principle or rule of
law. . . . This declaration of law is authoritative to the extent
necessary for the decision, and must be applied in subsequent
cases to similarly situated parties"). Id.
249 Id., at 900 ("The Framers of the Constitution considered
these principles to derive from the nature of judicial power").
Id.
250 Id., at 900-902.
251 Id., at 902, notes 10 and 11.
252 Id., at 902, note 12.
94
precedent and stare decisis; in essence, it read back into
eighteenth- and nineteenth-century discussions of precedent and
stare decisis understandings of those terms that would not, in
fact, cohere until the middle and later 1800s. Along these
lines, perhaps the largest error in Anastasoff was the adoption
of a positivist reading of precedent and stare decisis which
precluded the possibility of appreciating the jurisprudential
framework of the founding period.253 As this Article repeatedly
establishes, the historical foundations of these two basic
principles of Anglo-American law can only be understood through
the prism of eighteenth-century theories of natural law and
natural justice.
Hart v. Massanari, for its part, rejected Anastasoff's
analysis. It did so by focusing on the meaning of the term
"judicial power" as used in Article III of the United States
Constitution, and reading into it the modern presupposition that
courts not merely found the law but that they "made" it.254 The
253 The Anastasoff Court at several points mentions what it
calls "the law-declaring nature of the judicial power," id., at
901; the Anastasoff Court, however, fails to appreciate the
consequences that extend from this limitation on judicial power.
254 Id., at 1159-1160. The Hart Court reveals not only its
own but also Anastasoff's essentially modernist understanding of
precedent and stare decisis: "According to Anastasoff, exercise
of the 'Judicial Power' precludes federal courts from making
rulings that are not binding in future cases. Or, to put it
differently, federal judges are not merely required to follow the
law, they are also required to make law in every case." Id. The
assertion that federal judges "made the law" would be profoundly
repulsive to most lawyers and judges in the Founding period and
for several decades thereafter.
95
Hart Court was comfortable with the anachronism implicit in this
assertion. "[W]e should exercise considerable caution," the Hart
Court declared, "lest we freeze the law into the mold cast in the
eighteenth century."255 But even though the Hart Court accepted
the evolving character of legal concepts, it wished to engage in
historical exploration. It did so as a way of confronting
Anasatasoff's reading of precedent and stare decisis. "To accept
Anastasoff's argument," the Hart Court explained, "we would have
to conclude that the generation of the Framers had a much
stronger view of percedent than we do. In fact . . . our concept
of precedent today is far stricter than that which prevailed at
the time of the Founding."256
In the course of explaining, in a few pages, the
common-law understanding of precedent, Hart touched on some of
the themes explored in this Article. At footnote eight, for
instance, we find recited Sir Matthew Hale's assertion that
"judicial decisions 'do not make a Law properly so-called,' . .
." but constitute evidence of what the law should be;257 in the
same footnote, we also encounter Lord Mansfield's declaration
255 Id., at 1162. The Hart Court returned to this theme one
page later: "One danger of giving constitutional status to
practices that existed at common law, but have changed over time,
is that it tends to freeze certain aspects of the law into place,
even as other aspects change significantly." Id., at 1163.
256 Id., at 1163.
257 Id., at 1164, note 8 (quoting Sir Matthew Hale, The
History of the Common Law of England).
96
that "'the reason and spirit of cases make law; not the letter of
particular precedent.'"258 After reviewing this history, the Hart
Court reasserted the proposition with which it commenced its
analysis:
"A survey of the legal landscape as it might have
been viewed by the generation of the Framers casts
serious doubts on the proposition -- so readily
accepted by Anastasoff -- that the Framers viewed
precedent in the rigid form that we view it today.
Indeed, it is unclear that the Framers would have
considered our view of precedent desirable. The
common law, at its core, was a reflection of
custom, and custom had a built-in flexibility that
allowed it to change with circumstance."259
To address the normative question left unasked by Hart
-- why should we accept the modernist understanding of precedent
and stare decisis rather than return to the older understanding
embodied in the work of the jurists of the later eighteenth and
nineteenth century? -- would be a large and daunting task,
especially for the conclusion of an already overly-long
historical study of the subject. It is best, perhaps, to close
with an observation: stare decisis, at the time of the Founding,
258 Id. (quoting Fisher v. Prince, 97 Eng. Rep. 876, 876
(K.B., 1762).
259 Id., at 1167.
was a very different concept from what it has become today. How
we respond to this background is very much up to us.