
- •1 The concept of promise
- •1. What is a promise?
- •(a) A definition of promise
- •(b) Promise: objectively existing phenomenon or human construction?
- •(c) Testing component elements of the definition of promise
- •(i) A promise is more than merely an internal mental process: promises as speech acts demonstrating commitment
- •(ii) A promise is a commitment to a performance of the promisor
- •(iv) A promise must relate to the future
- •(v) A promise must state a commitment in favour of another party
- •(vi) Things which are not components of the definition
- •2. Three crucial qualities of relevance to promises: gratuitousness, conditionality, unilaterality
- •(a) Gratuitousness
- •(b) Conditionality
- •(c) Unilaterality
- •3. Acts having some similarity to, but which are distinct from, promises
- •(a) Vows
- •(b) Oaths
- •(c) Threats
- •(d) Donation (gift)
- •(e) Warranties (guarantees)
- •(f) Agreement
- •4. Promise as a culturally universal and significant idea
- •5. Preliminary conclusions
- •2 Promises as obligations: morality and law
- •1. Introduction: promise as a type of obligation
- •2. Taxonomies of obligations in morality and law
- •3. Promises as moral obligations: the practice of promising
- •(a) Promising as moral, immoral, or amoral?
- •(b) Source of the morality of the practice of promising
- •(i) Promising as a virtuous act; the natural law tradition
- •Scripture
- •The canon law
- •Objections to the morality of promising as having a natural law/virtue basis
- •(ii) Promising as an act of the will: respect for personal autonomy
- •(iii) The ‘contract theory’ of promising
- •(iv) Consequentialism (utilitarianism)
- •(v) Reliance theory
- •A more limited role for reliance
- •(vi) Conclusion on the competing theories of the moral value of promises
- •4. Powers and sanctions relevant to breach of morally binding promises
- •3 The historical development of promissory ideas in the law
- •1. Roman law
- •(a) Formal contracts: the stipulatio
- •(b) Informal contracts
- •(c) Conclusion on Roman law
- •2. Medieval contract law
- •(a) Continental legal thought
- •(b) English law
- •(i) Debt
- •(ii) Covenant
- •(iii) Unilaterality and bilaterality in early English contract law
- •(iv) Assumpsit
- •(v) The doctrine of consideration
- •3. The Northern natural law school
- •(a) Hugo Grotius
- •(b) Samuel von Pufendorf
- •(c) James Dalrymple (Viscount Stair)
- •4. Eighteenth and nineteenth centuries
- •(a) English law
- •(b) Scots law
- •(c) Civilian systems
- •(i) German law
- •(ii) Robert Pothier
- •5. Contract theory and practice in the twentieth century
- •6. A revitalised will theory
- •4 Formation of contract
- •1. Wasted pre-contractual expenditure following termination of contract negotiations
- •(a) A Common law solution to the problem of pre-contractual expenditure: promissory and proprietary estoppel
- •(i) Promissory estoppel: promissory or reliance-based principle?
- •(ii) Promissory estoppel and failed contractual negotiations
- •(iii) Proprietary estoppel and failed contractual negotiations
- •(iv) Conclusion on estoppel and pre-contractual expenditure
- •(b) A civilian solution to wasted pre-contractual expenditure: culpa in contrahendo and bad faith termination of contractual negotiations
- •(c) A mixed legal system solution to wasted pre-contractual expenditure: liability from an implied assurance that a valid contract exists
- •(d) Other solutions to the problem of pre-contractual liability
- •(e) Conclusion on pre-contractual liability
- •2. Pre-contractual duties of disclosure
- •3. Offer and acceptance
- •(a) Offer and acceptance as conditional promise
- •(b) The traditional offer and acceptance model as a unilateral dictation of terms
- •(c) Distinguishing offer from conditional promise
- •(d) Problem cases for a promissory analysis of offer and acceptance
- •(e) Conceiving of offers as binding
- •4. Enforcement of auction/tender conditions
- •5. The firm or irrevocable offer
- •(a) Characterising the firm offer
- •(b) Promises of reward
- •6. Options
- •7. Letters of intent and preliminary contracts
- •(a) An intent to contract
- •(b) A preliminary contract, envisaging a further contract
- •(c) An expectation of a formal contract
- •(d) An expression of intention to do something other than contract
- •(e) A genuine unilateral promissory intention
- •8. Error in formation of contract
- •(a) Choosing the policies which inform the rules on error
- •(b) Constructing workable classifications which implement the policies chosen
- •(i) Roman Law
- •(ii) The Common law
- •(iii) The mixed legal systems
- •(iv) German law
- •(v) An ideal approach to promissory error?
- •9. Extortion in the formation of contract
- •(a) English law
- •(b) The mixed legal systems
- •(c) German law
- •(d) Conclusion on extortion
- •10. Implied terms
- •11. Consideration
- •(a) The Common law
- •(b) The mixed legal systems
- •(c) German law
- •(d) Model law
- •12. Requirements of form: unwarranted restrictions on promising?
- •5 Third party rights
- •1. The challenge to third party rights in contract
- •2. The historical legal background
- •3. Third party rights in modern contract law
- •(a) The Common law
- •(b) The mixed legal systems
- •(c) German law
- •(d) Model law
- •(e) Conclusion on third party rights under contract
- •4. Assignment
- •(a) English law
- •(b) The mixed legal systems
- •(c) German law
- •(d) Model law
- •5. The problem of transferred loss
- •(a) English law
- •(b) The mixed legal systems
- •(c) German law
- •6. Conclusion on third parties
- •6 Contractual remedies
- •1. The ‘interests’ protected by remedies
- •2. Mutuality of promises and withholding of performance
- •(a) The Common law
- •(b) Mixed legal systems
- •(c) German law
- •(d) Model law
- •3. Specific performance
- •(a) English law
- •(b) Mixed legal systems
- •(c) German law
- •(d) Model law
- •4. Perfect or substantial performance of contractual promises
- •(a) Contracts for services
- •(b) Sales of goods
- •5. Injunction (interdict)
- •6. Damages
- •(a) Contractual damages and interests other than the performance interest
- •(b) Damages for mere breach of contract, or for fault?
- •(c) English law
- •(d) Mixed legal systems
- •(e) German law
- •(f) Model law
- •7. Liquidated damages: penalty clauses
- •(a) English law
- •(b) Mixed legal systems
- •(c) German law
- •(d) Model law
- •8. Termination of contract for non-performance
- •(a) Historical origins of the right to terminate
- •(b) English law
- •(c) Mixed legal systems
- •(d) German law
- •(e) Model law
- •9. Restitution following termination for non-performance
- •(a) English law
- •(b) Mixed legal systems
- •(c) German law
- •(d) Model law
- •10. Good faith and contractual remedies
- •7 The renunciation of contractual rights
- •1. Terminology
- •2. Bilateral or unilateral renunciations
- •3. Characterising undertakings not to enforce contractual rights
- •4. Express contractual or promissory renunciation of rights
- •(a) The Common law
- •(b) Mixed legal systems
- •(c) German law
- •5. Forbearance, promissory estoppel and personal bar
- •(a) The Common law
- •(i) Forbearance at common law
- •(ii) Forbearance in equity: promissory estoppel in English law
- •(iii) Promissory estoppel in American Common law
- •(iv) Conclusion on promissory estoppel in the Common law
- •(b) Mixed legal systems
- •(i) South Africa
- •(ii) Louisiana
- •(iii) Scotland
- •(c) German law
- •6. Model Law and renunciations of rights
- •8 The future of promise in contract law
- •1. The restricted role of promise in the modern law
- •2. Future possible development of the law
- •(a) General remarks
- •(b) The Common law
- •(c) The mixed legal systems
- •(d) German law
- •(e) The development of supranational model law
- •3. Conclusion on the future of promise
86 |
Promises and Contract Law |
effect they have upon surrounding society, particularly, for instance, in the happiness they produce, or in the utility that they offer to the functioning of that society or of more specific interests such as commerce. For positivists, the moral quality to behaviour is thus relative. A frequent criticism of such positivists is that, bearing in mind that all theories of law have to accept the reality that not all promises are held to be binding, natural law’s explanation for not upholding all promises – based upon the idea of implied conditions deemed to affect promises – is unconvincing.86 This, however, is not a wholly accurate criticism, as the natural law tradition does not rely solely upon the idea of implied conditions to explain invalid promises: in addition, natural lawyers have used the concept of the just or appropriate causa required to support promises and contracts, they have considered whether consent has truly been given in specific circumstances, and have had regard as well to external considerations of justice (for instance in relation to the just price of a contract).
A third line of attack on the virtue/natural law foundations of the morality of promising focuses on theistic conceptions of natural law: it is thus an attack on the religious basis of the moral worth of promises. The criticism is that canonical and scriptural texts cannot prove the inherent morality of promising, given that they presuppose but cannot demonstrate a specific theistic belief, a belief which is rejected as unjustifiable.87 There is little that can be said of this criticism, save that one either accepts its sceptical, humanist premise, or rejects it and, in so rejecting it, affirms the value and place of the insights about human nature and the moral quality of human actions such as promising which is provided by canonical and scriptural sources. Admittedly, however, even those who do accept these insights are often slow at advocating them in an avowedly secular age.
(ii) Promising as an act of the will: respect for personal autonomy
One of the great themes of obligations theory in the western legal tradition, both from a moral and legal standpoint, has been the view that promises (and thus the contracts formed by an exchange of promises) are acts of the human will.88 Such a conception opens up a second approach
86This attack is advanced by Atiyah in Promises, Morals and Law, pp. 22–4.
87An interesting recent philosophical study of whether it is justifiable to commit oneself ‘by faith’ to a religious claim when its truth appears to lack adequate evidentiary support is Bishop, Believing by Faith.
88On the will in the law, see Pound, ‘The Role of the Will in Law’.
Promises as Obligations: Morality and Law |
87 |
to viewing the act of promising as moral, by positing that, as a function of the human will, promising is moral because it is the free choice of an autonomous moral being, worthy of respect as such, to create or subject himself to an obligation.89 A promise can thus be said to embody a moral principle forged by such a moral being about what it is right to do. As Raz put it:
What one ought to do depends in part on oneself, and this is not just because the behaviour, needs, tastes, and desires of the agent count just as much as those of any other person, but because the agent has the power intentionally to shape the form of his moral world, to obligate himself to follow certain goals, or to create bonds and alliances with certain people and not others.90
The rise to prominence of the will theory as a means of explaining the force of promises, and hence of contract, is often ascribed to nineteenthcentury legal and moral thought.91 This development, it is said, took the idea of the will, which had already been a feature of contract law prior to this point, and gave to it the pre-eminent position in the philosophical and moral explanation of the force of promises and contracts.92 As will be seen when considering the other theories of promise discussed later in this chapter, the counter-attacks on the idea of the will as the explanatory moral force behind promise and contract has left the theory somewhat battered but not, it will be suggested, dethroned from its position as the standard modern explanation for the moral and legal force of promises.
It should be noted that there are different strands of will theory. One view posits the will itself as the source of the obligation created, whether it be of promise or of some other type, and so conceives of the moral agent as endued with normative power. By that agent’s willing to make a promise, the agent thereby wills a moral obligation in to being. On such a view, the promissory obligation is seen as having both its source and force (moral
89‘According to the classical view, the law of contract gives expression to and protects the will of the parties, for the will is something inherently worthy of respect’ (Cohen, ‘The Basis of Contract’, 575).
90 Raz, ‘Promises and Obligations’, p. 228. |
91 See Gordley, Philosophical Origins, Ch. 9. |
92‘Logically central to Will Theory was the idea that contractual liability depended on the voluntary, intentional, act of the parties. There was nothing new in this; it was an idea that had been familiar to Common lawyers for at least half a millennium. What was new was the greater depth given to the idea, and the greater weight placed on it’ (Ibbetson, Historical Introduction, p. 232). The nineteenth-century timescale suggested is doubtless true of the Common law, though arguably the will had already played a more prominent position in the legal theory of some non-Common law systems before this point, a matter explored in more detail in the next chapter.
88 |
Promises and Contract Law |
as well as legal) in the act of the human will. A slightly different strain of will theory sees the promisor as merely, in making the promise, expressing a consent to be bound in law to an obligation, the difference being that, while on this view the consent of the promisor remains an act of the will, the source and the force of the promissory duty is found not in that act of will but in the law’s imposition of the duty in response to the freely given consent of the promisor.93 On this view, the promisor wills undertaking a legal obligation, but the obligation has its source in the normative power of the legal system. This may seem a neat distinction, depending on the moot point of whether it is better to see the law as allowing individuals to create obligations by their actions or whether the law permits them voluntarily to submit themselves to externally imposed obligations, but it is a distinction which often makes a difference to the question of whether or not objections to will theory strike home (as the discussion of Hume’s views below will indicate). Both of these strands of will theory suggest that the act of promising is moral, though in the case of the latter strand the moral nature of the promise need not simply rest on the idea that it is the free choice of a moral being, but can further be said to lie in the fact that, as the law will only ever impose moral and not immoral duties upon a promisor, any promise which has legal effect through such imposition must necessarily be a moral one.94
The will theory of the moral force of promises is the foundation of a number of more specialised theories of contract law. Theories of contract based upon the idea of an agreement95 or the idea of a bargain96 are both
93Coote’s theory of contract as assumption might be classified in these terms. He sees contract as stemming from an expression of the parties’ will, made manifest in their promises, to submit to the imposition of contractual duties upon them (an assumption of contractual duty). His theory thus contains elements of promise, will and intention to contract, but it ultimately rests upon the basis that the law permits voluntary assumption of duty in some cases: see further Coote, Contract as Assumption, Ch. 2.
94This, of course, presupposes a belief in the view that obligations imposed by a sovereign normative power upon a promisor will necessarily be moral, a view which would not be universally accepted given that sovereign normative powers appear not to be universally morally good.
95Thus Peel, Treitel on Contract, has contract as ‘an agreement giving rise to obligations which are enforceable or recognised by law’ (para. 1–001), this definition being almost verbatim the definition adopted in early editions of Chitty (the newest editions of Chitty discuss definitions both in terms of promise and agreement, without definitively settling for either).
96The bargain theory has, as an essential component, not just the idea of the will but of exchange, and is thus a theory peculiarly designed to explain the Common law idea of quid pro quo or consideration, as it later became. Furmston, Cheshire, Fifoot and
Promises as Obligations: Morality and Law |
89 |
dependent upon will theory, given that the will, as the faculty of human decision-making, is self-evidently the seat of the ability of human beings to agree or to bargain with others. If the concept of the will is attacked as unable to explain why promises are enforced, then logically agreement or bargain theories of contract must necessarily fall with it.
There are a number of common criticisms of the will theory of the moral force of promises. First, given that human beings can choose freely to do that which is immoral, a promise might conceivably be used as a vehicle for implementing just such an immoral choice. Such a promise would seem logically to be as immoral as the choice prompting it. This problem can be argued, however, to relate only to specific promises, and not promising as an institution. Despite individual bad choices and thus bad promises, promising as an institution remains moral because, taken as a whole, the practice of promising is supportive of the autonomy of moral beings capable of undertaking moral choices. Even were this defence not to be accepted, then it might yet be conceded that at least those individual promises reflecting good choices must be recognised as moral
More fundamentally, one might choose to challenge the idea that there is such a thing as free will, and thus the idea that promise is based upon an exercise of such free will. Scientific views about the nature of causality since the Enlightenment have led some to adopt a sceptical view of free will for the reason that, it is said, science has shown the universe to be essentially deterministic.97 What appears to be a freely made choice, whether it be a promise or some other human act, is in reality determined by the factors preceding it and not the human will. On such a view, a promise is neither moral nor immoral, for human beings are no longer seen as moral agents capable of making moral decisions. However, adherence to such a view depends crucially on a belief in an entirely deterministic universe, a controversial belief within the scientific community.
A slightly less sceptical view of free will, though one which nonetheless rejects any relationship between the will and promising, is represented in David Hume’s view that the human will can only have a causal effect
Furmston, refers (p. 37) to ‘the idea of bargain, fundamental to the English conception of contract’, noting that, because this idea is absent in obligations undertaken by way of deed, such obligations should not properly be considered as contract. Such a view seems entirely logical if the essence of contract is located in bargain or agreement: the contract by way of deed is essentially a unilateral promise (much like the Scots unilateral promise), put into a required form, rather than such a bargain or agreement.
97Views differ on this point, however. The apparent unpredictability of the decay of uran ium-238 atoms, for instance, would appear to indicate that at least some things are not determinable (at least from a human perspective).
90 |
Promises and Contract Law |
on present actions. A promise, by contrast, relates to the future, and any binding effect said presently to be produced by a promise can thus only result from human convention and not from an act of the will.98 Morality, including the morality of adhering to promises, is, on this view, mere sentiment, the idea of promise-keeping being said to be virtuous resulting merely from the fact that honouring promises creates pleasing results. Hume asserts that anyone unacquainted with society’s conventions would not even grasp the idea of a promise; on the contrary, it would be unintelligible to him.99
Hume’s points require to be broken down. Firstly, one must consider his objection that the will alone cannot give rise to binding obligations. This is essentially an objection to the idea of the will as a normative power. This criticism only raises any serious problems for that strand of will theory which posits that obligations arise directly from the will of the parties, but, as noted above, that is but one strand of will theory. The alternative is to say that what a promisor is doing is simply consenting to the law’s imposition of a duty upon him. On that view, the will merely triggers the assumption of a binding duty which finds its force and origin in the law and not the human will itself. If that view is taken, then Hume’s objection to seeing the human will as the source of an obligation is irrelevant. The human will has apparent normative capacity only because it is exercising a discretionary power to bind itself delegated to it by the sovereign normative power. On such a view, Hume’s objection that the will can only have a causal effect on present actions is also irrelevant, as a consent to be bound at law can be said to be just such a present action of the will, the duty being imposed by the law as soon as the consent to it is given. At least one strand of will theory can thus offer a powerful riposte to Hume’s insistence that the use of free will to explain promises necessarily involves seeing the force of promise as deriving from the human will.100
98
99
‘… promises are human inventions, founded on the necessities and interest of society’ (Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, III.ii.5).
Ibid.
100A different response to Hume’s concern would be to take the idea of an intention to act, formed by the human will, and add to it some other element, such further element being the source of the obligatory force of the promise rather than the act of will alone. The philosopher Michael Robins, for instance, has suggested that pure will or intention alone does not furnish a moral content to promises, but requires the additional element of ‘commitment’, a ‘relation that binds together the very concept of intention with that of volition’ and is ‘irreducibly normative’ (Robbins, Promising, Intending and Moral Authority, p. 12). The moral imperative here derives from the moral agent’s committing himself to an intended course of conduct in favour of another, a commitment which Robbins believes is by its nature normative.
Promises as Obligations: Morality and Law |
91 |
A second comment on Hume’s position is that, in order to reject the view that promising is an essential feature of human nature, he somewhat unsettlingly rejects the social nature of human beings, portraying them as essentially isolated and self-concerned beings (humans are ‘naturally selfish’ in Hume’s conception)101 rather than as naturally cooperative creatures. Yet it is this latter conception of the human species which many would say represents a more accurate anthropological critique of human nature. And, if we are indeed cooperative and not isolated by nature, it is not hard to see a promise-making disposition as an inherent part of that cooperative nature: as Hume’s contemporary Lord Kames put it when considering promises, ‘[a]s man is framed for society, mutual trust and confidence, without which there can be no useful society, enter into the character of the human species’.102
Thirdly, a substantial concern for Hume is that the theory that the human will can give rise to binding obligations would seem, Hume asserts, to allow people to turn that which is immoral (or indeed amoral) into a moral action simply by promising to do the act, which forces Hume to question whether morality can really be so subjective as to allow this.103 Such a concern can be refuted through rejecting Hume’s premise: promissory theorists do not assert, as Hume suggests, that promising can turn what was an immoral into a moral act. All that the promising does is to turn an act which was not the object of a moral duty into such an object, thereby creating a moral imperative or duty where there was none before. So Hume’s objection is based on a false premise; promises do not undermine the objective moral or immoral nature of acts. A cruel father who neglects the care of his child by binding himself to give all his money away to a stranger would still be acting immorally in spite of his promise, and the fact that he has bound himself to give his wealth to another merely creates a duty to that party without affecting the nature of his conduct towards his child.
As a final comment on Hume’s position, from a legal realist perspective Hume’s view that human beings cannot bind themselves to an obligation by an act of the will suffers from comparison with the reality of what actually occurs in moral and legal systems, which do conceive of the human will as exercising normative power (whether primary or devolved) and
101 Hume, Treatise of Human Nature, III.ii.5. 102 Kames, Essays on Morality, II.vi.
103Hume asserts that we cannot ‘by a single act of our will, that is, by a promise, render any action agreeable or disagreeable, moral or immoral; which, without that act, wou’d have produc’d contrary impressions, or have been endow’d with different qualities’ (Treatise of Human Nature, III.ii.5).
92 |
Promises and Contract Law |
do assert that obligations may be constituted simply by a voluntary act of such will.104 That being the reality, it seems somewhat futile to argue that this is inconsistent with legal philosophy.
A further and significant attack on the moral nature of promises as acts of the human will has been said to lie in the fact that it is not, in fact, the actual, subjective intentions of promisors which are usually (if ever) given effect to, but rather the objectively manifested indication of such intentions, the words or behaviour of the promisor as manifested to the reasonable promisee or to the reasonable third party observer.105 If therefore, it is said, it is not the actual will of the promisor which creates a promise, then such act of will cannot be the source of the moral (or indeed legal) authority of the promise. Such ‘objectivist’ objections have been raised both in the Common law106 as well as civilian jurisprudence.107 The subjective/objective debate is one of the hardest fought in the law but, at least in the field of promise and contract, middle ground is possible. Such middle ground may be found in a number of ways. First, as discussed in Chapter 1, if one accepts the practical reality that internal thought processes, such as acts of the will, can only ever (short of the invention of mind reading technology) be judged objectively,108 then it seems reasonable to assert that, in general, the human will is best defined and characterised in its objective, external form. Second, however, one can concede, as some will theorists have done (and as seems reasonable), that while a subjective intention to make a promise at all should be considered necessary (even if, in the absence of an error-based challenge, such intention is usually
104As Cohen put it, on the question of taking account of the moral realities of the world around us: ‘If, then, we find ourselves in a state of society in which men are, as a matter of fact, repelled by the breaking of promises and feel that such practice should be discouraged or minimized, that is a primary fact which the law must not ignore’ (Cohen, ‘The Basis of Contract’, 572; Law and Social Order, p. 90).
105There has been a lively debate in many legal systems as to whether taking an objective perspective of a party’s conduct means the perspective of an entirely detached, disinterested, third party observer (what can figuratively be called ‘fly-on-the-wall objectivity’) or whether it means the perspective of a reasonable party in the shoes of the other party to the transaction (what can be called ‘objective subjectivity’, given that it is an attempt to bring a reasonable perspective to the other subject of the contract): for some interesting discussion in the Common law tradition, see Howarth, ‘Objectivity in Contract’; Vorster, ‘A Comment on the Meaning of Objectivity in Contract’. The DCFR takes the ‘objective subjective’ approach that it is how words or conduct were ‘reasonably understood by the person to whom [they are] addressed’ which counts: see Art. II.-4:302.
106In the USA, in the writings of Holmes and Williston, for instance.
107In Germany, in the writings of Schlossmann and Kohler, for instance.
108A practical approach which essentially constitutes the view of Pollock.