
- •Contents
- •Acknowledgements
- •Table of cases
- •Abbreviations
- •Introduction to the second edition
- •1 The roots of corporate insolvency law
- •Development and structure
- •Corporate insolvency procedures
- •Administrative receivership
- •Administration
- •Winding up/liquidation
- •Formal arrangements with creditors
- •The players
- •Administrators
- •Administrative receivers
- •Receivers
- •Liquidators
- •Company voluntary arrangement (CVA) supervisors
- •The tasks of corporate insolvency law
- •Conclusions
- •2 Aims, objectives and benchmarks
- •Cork on principles
- •Visions of corporate insolvency law
- •Creditor wealth maximisation and the creditors’ bargain
- •A broad-based contractarian approach
- •The communitarian vision
- •The forum vision
- •The ethical vision
- •The multiple values/eclectic approach
- •The nature of measuring
- •An ‘explicit values’ approach to insolvency law
- •Conclusions
- •3 Insolvency and corporate borrowing
- •Creditors, borrowing and debtors
- •How to borrow
- •Security
- •Unsecured loans
- •Quasi-security
- •Third-party guarantees
- •Debtors and patterns of borrowing
- •Equity and security
- •Equity shares
- •Floating charges
- •Improving on security and full priority
- •The ‘new capitalism’ and the credit crisis
- •Conclusions
- •4 Corporate failure
- •What is failure?
- •Why companies fail
- •Internal factors
- •Mismanagement
- •External factors
- •Late payment of debts
- •Conclusions: failures and corporate insolvency law
- •5 Insolvency practitioners and turnaround professionals
- •Insolvency practitioners
- •The evolution of the administrative structure
- •Evaluating the structure
- •Expertise
- •Fairness
- •Accountability
- •Reforming IP regulation
- •Insolvency as a discrete profession
- •An independent regulatory agency
- •Departmental regulation
- •Fine-tuning profession-led regulation
- •Conclusions on insolvency practitioners
- •Turnaround professionals
- •Turnaround professionals and fairness
- •Expertise
- •Conclusions
- •6 Rescue
- •What is rescue?
- •Why rescue?
- •Informal and formal routes to rescue
- •The new focus on rescue
- •The philosophical change
- •Recasting the actors
- •Comparing approaches to rescue
- •Conclusions
- •7 Informal rescue
- •Who rescues?
- •The stages of informal rescue
- •Assessing the prospects
- •The alarm stage
- •The evaluation stage
- •Agreeing recovery plans
- •Implementing the rescue
- •Managerial and organisational reforms
- •Asset reductions
- •Cost reductions
- •Debt restructuring
- •Debt/equity conversions
- •Conclusions
- •8 Receivers and their role
- •The development of receivership
- •Processes, powers and duties: the Insolvency Act 1986 onwards
- •Expertise
- •Accountability and fairness
- •Revising receivership
- •Conclusions
- •9 Administration
- •The rise of administration
- •From the Insolvency Act 1986 to the Enterprise Act 2002
- •The Enterprise Act reforms and the new administration
- •Financial collateral arrangements
- •Preferential creditors, the prescribed part and the banks
- •Exiting from administration
- •Evaluating administration
- •Use, cost-effectiveness and returns to creditors
- •Responsiveness
- •Super-priority funding
- •Rethinking charges on book debts
- •Administrators’ expenses and rescue
- •The case for cram-down and supervised restructuring
- •Equity conversions
- •Expertise
- •Fairness and accountability
- •Conclusions
- •10 Pre-packaged administrations
- •The rise of the pre-pack
- •Advantages and concerns
- •Fairness and expertise
- •Accountability and transparency
- •Controlling the pre-pack
- •The ‘managerial’ solution: a matter of expertise
- •The professional ethics solution: expertise and fairness combined
- •The regulatory answer
- •Evaluating control strategies
- •Conclusions
- •11 Company arrangements
- •Schemes of arrangement under the Companies Act 2006 sections 895–901
- •Company Voluntary Arrangements
- •The small companies’ moratorium
- •Crown creditors and CVAs
- •The nominee’s scrutiny role
- •Rescue funding
- •Landlords, lessors of tools and utilities suppliers
- •Expertise
- •Accountability and fairness
- •Unfair prejudice
- •The approval majority for creditors’ meetings
- •The shareholders’ power to approve the CVA
- •Conclusions
- •12 Rethinking rescue
- •13 Gathering the assets: the role of liquidation
- •The voluntary liquidation process
- •Compulsory liquidation
- •Public interest liquidation
- •The concept of liquidation
- •Expertise
- •Accountability
- •Fairness
- •Avoidance of transactions
- •Preferences
- •Transactions at undervalue and transactions defrauding creditors
- •Fairness to group creditors
- •Conclusions
- •14 The pari passu principle
- •Exceptions to pari passu
- •Liquidation expenses and post-liquidation creditors
- •Preferential debts
- •Subordination
- •Deferred claims
- •Conclusions: rethinking exceptions to pari passu
- •15 Bypassing pari passu
- •Security
- •Retention of title and quasi-security
- •Trusts
- •The recognition of trusts
- •Advances for particular purposes
- •Consumer prepayments
- •Fairness
- •Alternatives to pari passu
- •Debts ranked chronologically
- •Debts ranked ethically
- •Debts ranked on size
- •Debts paid on policy grounds
- •Conclusions
- •16 Directors in troubled times
- •Accountability
- •Common law duties
- •When does the duty arise?
- •Statutory duties and liabilities
- •General duties
- •Fraudulent trading
- •Wrongful trading
- •‘Phoenix’ provisions
- •Transactions at undervalue, preferences and transactions defrauding creditors
- •Enforcement
- •Public interest liquidation
- •Expertise
- •Fairness
- •Conclusions
- •17 Employees in distress
- •Protections under the law
- •Expertise
- •Accountability
- •Fairness
- •Conclusions
- •18 Conclusion
- •Bibliography
- •Index
48 |
agendas and objectives |
precision, appeals can be made to an open-ended menu82 of purposes and it is difficult to decide when to rule out appeals on the basis that they invoke irrelevant values or aims. (Cork, it should be conceded, does offer a list, as we have seen.) Eclecticism runs the danger of seeing all arguments as valid and, as a result, guidance for practical decision-making is lacking and confusion results. If an identification of the objectives of insolvency law is desired so as to provide a framework within which judges and legislators can act, then the multi-value/eclectic, even more than the communitarian, approach is guilty of settling untrammelled discretions on such individuals and allowing them freely to choose from and combine an indeterminately long list of vaguely stated ingredients.
The nature of measuring
The above visions or approaches to insolvency emphasise different facets of corporate insolvency law’s role. What fails to emerge from the review undertaken, however, is any complete view of the appropriate measures of insolvency law. Creditor wealth maximisation was narrow in its exclusive concerns with creditors’ interests and pre-insolvency rights and in its conception of the insolvent company as a pool of assets. The broad-based contractarian approach begged questions concerning the nature of persons behind the veil of ignorance and failed to explain tradeoffs of fairness or justice versus efficiency or between different kinds of interests worthy of protection. The communitarian vision escaped the narrowness of creditor wealth maximisation but encountered problems of indeterminacy. The forum vision made much of procedural concerns but shed little light on the substantive ends to be pursued by insolvency law or processes. The ethical vision gave rise to difficulties concerning the possibility of locating agreement as to ethical content and to establishing the boundaries of relevant ethical concerns. How ethical aspects of decisions on insolvency interacted with other, say legal, principles remained in doubt. Finally, the eclectic approach, again, gave rise to problems of indeterminacy and of contradictions and tensions between different ends.
82For a view that insolvency law should offer a ‘menu of options’ and allow firms to choose the optimal rules for their own, perhaps idiosyncratic, requirements, see Rasmussen, ‘Debtor’s Choice’ and Rasmussen, ‘The Ex Ante Effects of Bankruptcy Reform on Investment Incentives’ (1994) 72 Wash. ULQ 1159.
aims, objectives and benchmarks |
49 |
To advance the search for measures in the light of such competing, yet contestable, visions, it is necessary to examine further the purpose of a quest for benchmarks and in doing so to answer two questions. What precisely is being measured? Is it possible to justify insolvency law or processes given present approaches? A response to these issues can be made by examining a well-known treatment of justification in company law and by suggesting that it can be built upon to develop an approach that has relevance for the insolvency arena.
A framework for analysing the fundamental rules of company law has been offered by focusing on the question of how corporate managerial power is legitimated. This issue is said to be a ‘unifying theme of company law’.83 Mary Stokes’ argument, in brief, is as follows. If economic power, derived from private property, is to be legitimated within the framework of a liberal society, it is necessary to show that there are restraints preventing it from becoming a threat to liberty or a challenge to state power. Two strategies are contained within the fabric of the law to attempt this demonstration: first, it is posited that the economic power at issue is not sufficiently concentrated to be a threat; second, such economic power is seen as subject to constraints imposed by the competitive market. Unfortunately both strands of argument are afflicted with deficiencies. The growth of the corporate enterprise has allowed concentrations of economic power; and the separation of ownership from control has produced managers’ powers that are unrestrained by the market (much economic power indeed has come to be exercised not within markets but within corporate bureaucracies).
Company law can be said to have offered a response to the problem of corporate managerial power by explaining why discretion was conferred on corporate managers and by demonstrating that such discretionary power was subject to checks and controls. The justification for discretion was based by some on a contractual view of the company.84 Thus, the owners might legitimately contract with managers to establish the latter
83Stokes, ‘Company Law and Legal Theory’, p. 155.
84On the contractual view see J. E. Parkinson, Corporate Power and Responsibility: Issues in the Theory of Company Law (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1993) pp. 25–32 and Parkinson, ‘The Contractual Theory of the Company and the Protection of Non-Shareholder Interests’ in D. Feldman and F. Meisel (eds.), Corporate and Commercial Law: Modern Developments (Lloyd’s of London Press, London, 1996); W. W. Bratton, ‘The “Nexus of Contracts Corporation”: A Critical Appraisal’ (1989) 74 Cornell L Rev. 408 at 415–23;
M. C. Jensen and W. H. Meckling, ‘Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behaviour, Agency Costs and Ownership Structure’ (1976) 3 Journal of Financial Economics 305; F. H. Easterbrook and D. R. Fischel, ‘The Corporate Contract’ (1989) 89 Colum. L Rev.
50 |
agendas and objectives |
as agents. As companies grew, though, the artificiality of a contractarian analysis became apparent. A ‘natural entity’ view of the corporation was seen by others to be more appropriate.85 This saw the company as a living organism with the managers as the brain and the shareholders as passive suppliers of capital. The natural entity view gave rise to a further way of justifying the vesting of discretionary power in managers: it was the expertise and competence of managers that legitimated their discretion. The boundaries of such expertise and appropriate deference to it were nevertheless difficult to delineate.
As for legitimation through checks on arbitrariness, the traditional legal model offered two mechanisms: accountability to shareholders through internal company controls and directorial duties to act in the best interest of shareholders. (The latter duties legitimated discretions by compelling directors to aim at profit maximisation.) Both mechanisms proved flawed and the law’s quest to legitimate the power of corporate management failed.86
In response to this failure two strategies might be advocated within the traditional approach: either managers could be made more responsible to the market or new legal steps could be taken to ensure management in the interest of shareholders. Both of these strategies would constitute tinkering. It would be better, argued Stokes, to recognise the misguided nature of attempts to control through markets or the ordering of power in the company and to adopt a new perspective on legitimating managerial power.87 This new approach would accept the separation of ownership and control and break free from the contractual conception of the company. It might build on a corporatist model of the company and see
1416; E. F. Fama, ‘Agency Problems and the Theory of the Firm’ (1980) 88(1) Journal of Political Economy 288; Symposium, ‘Contractual Freedoms in Corporate Law’ (1988) 89 Colum. L Rev. 1385; H. Butler, ‘The Contractual Theory of the Corporation’ (1989) 11 Geo. Mason UL Rev. 99.
85 See Stokes, ‘Company Law and Legal Theory’, p. 164. See also further discussion in S. W. Mayson, D. French and C. L. Ryan, Mayson, French and Ryan on Company Law
(24th edn, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2007) ch. 5. Another problem of using a contractual conception to legitimate managerial power was that this view conflicted with the case-law theory of the company as a body distinct and separate from its shareholders.
86Notably because in large public companies the dispersion of shareholding undermined shareholder control and managers, in reality, wielded power free from either shareholder constraint or the courts, who displayed deference to managerial expertise. (Dispersed shareholding produced a lack of control over managers because of low information levels and low incentives to enforce duties against directors: see V. Finch, ‘Company Directors: Who Cares About Skill and Care?’ (1992) 55 MLR 179.)
87Stokes, ‘Company Law and Legal Theory’, pp. 173–7.
aims, objectives and benchmarks |
51 |
its interests not merely as those of shareholders but as involving both public and private dimensions; see directors as expert public servants balancing a variety of claims by various groups in the community and doing so with reference to public policy not private cupidity; and see the company as an organic body unifying the interests of participants in harmonious purpose. Managerial power would be legitimated as giving expression to the common purposes of shareholders, creditors, employees and the community.
Stokes’ argument, in short, is thus that current strategies for legitimating managerial power should be seen as unnecessarily tied to traditional contractarian views of the company and as inadequate; and that the values involved in the corporatist and democratic ideals of the company should be embraced in rethinking rationales for legitimation.
The importance of the argument outlined lies in its critique of the assumptions that underpin traditionalist approaches to the legitimation of managerial power and in its stressing that the public dimension of corporate power demands measures reflecting community and democratic rather than simply private values. Against Stokes it can be countered, however, that reservations about narrow contractarianism and endorsement of the communitarian/democratic approach do not necessarily mean that arguments for legitimation based on contractarian assumptions lack all validity. Here the question is whether traditionalist arguments for legitimation are ‘fundamentally misguided’88 in the sense that they are positive deceptions or whether they are criticisable as telling only part of the story. The communitarian/democratic vision may be completely at odds with the contractarian vision but it may be that legitimating arguments from both camps may cumulate: that adding a communitarian perspective means that corporate managerial power is capable of legitimation to some degree with reference both to controls exercised over managers by the market and to controls operating through representative arrangements corresponding to the democratic ideal. Legitimating arguments such as those based on expertise and accountability can thus be seen as having cumulative force in spite of being flawed in various ways. Indeed, arguments derived from the communitarian/democratic vision are themselves not problem free. (How much representation of which interests is appropriate? How should such representation best be achieved?)
88 Ibid., p. 174.