
- •CONTENTS
- •CONTRIBUTORS
- •PREFACE
- •Introduction
- •I. A Positive Account
- •II. Normative and Historical Accounts
- •III. Explaining Legal Doctrine
- •A. Willful Breach
- •B. Comparative Fault
- •Conclusion
- •ACKNOWLEDGMENT
- •Introduction
- •C. Summary
- •Conclusion
- •Introduction
- •B. Some Striking Nuances in Common Law Systems
- •II. A Market Function Approach
- •A. Ethics or Economics – The Wrong Question
- •B. Party and Market Expectation as Guidelines
- •D. Fault, Foreseeability, and Other “Softeners” of Strict Liability
- •Conclusion
- •I. Fault and Uncertain Contractual Intent
- •II. An Expanded Law and Economics Approach to Fault
- •III. A Fault-Based Approach to Contract Damages
- •Conclusion
- •Introduction
- •A. A Model
- •B. Fault
- •C. A Comparison: Strict Liability Versus Negligence
- •II. Doctrine
- •A. Impossibility/Impracticability
- •B. Reasonable or Substantial Performance
- •C. Good Faith and Best Efforts
- •D. Interpretation/Implied Terms
- •E. Conditions
- •F. Damages
- •Introduction
- •I. Unconscionability
- •A. Markets
- •B. Moral Fault
- •II. Unexpected Circumstances
- •III. Interpretation
- •IV. Mistake
- •C. Cases in Which the Nonmistaken Party Neither Knew nor Had Reason to Know of the Mechanical Error
- •V. Nonperformance
- •Conclusion
- •Introduction
- •I. Modernizing Tort and Contract Around Fault
- •II. Explaining the Fault Swap
- •Conclusion
- •Introduction: From Fault to Negligence – and Back
- •I. Tort Law
- •III. Gratuitous Transactions: Bailment and Agency
- •A. Coggs v. Bernard
- •C. Siegel v. Spear and Comfort v. McGorkle
- •D. Medical Malpractice, Occupier’s Liability, and Guest Statutes
- •IV. Frustration and Impossibility
- •Conclusion
- •Conclusion
- •A. Analogies in Criminal Law
- •B. Lay Assessments of Culpability
- •C. Two Ways of Defining “Willful”
- •B. “Willful” as a Test for Inefficiency?
- •B. Optimal Damages Under Strict Liability
- •Conclusion
- •II. Cost of Correction Versus Diminution in Value
- •B. Treatment by the Courts
- •Conclusion
- •Introduction
- •C. An Information-Based Explanation
- •B. Informal Lessons from the Example
- •D. From Moral Hazard to Adverse Selection
- •II. Willful Breach Doctrine
- •A. Overcompensatory Expectation Damages
- •B. Tort Damages for Bad-Faith Breach
- •C. Restitution
- •Conclusion
- •Introduction
- •I. Expectation Damages and Willful Breach
- •II. Willfulness, Material Breach, and Damages
- •Conclusion
- •Introduction
- •A. Noncooperation
- •B. Overreliance
- •A. Setting the Stage
- •B. Noncooperation
- •1. When Should Avoiding Overreliance be the Default Rule?
- •Conclusion
- •Introduction
- •I. Stipulation, Fault, and Mitigation
- •II. Encouraging Stipulation
- •A. How Courts Encourage Parties to Stipulate
- •B. Two Advantages of Stipulation: Knowledge and Mitigation
- •Conclusion
- •Introduction
- •II. Comparative Negligence
- •III. Mitigation
- •IV. Reasonable Reliance
- •V. Causation
- •VI. Foreseeability
- •Conclusion
- •I. Summary of the Argument that Breach May Not Be Immoral Given the Incompleteness of Contracts
- •F. When Is Breach Immoral and When Is It Moral in Practice?
- •II. Criticism and Discussion of the Foregoing Argument
- •Conclusion
- •Introduction
- •I. Promise De-moralized, Contract Moralized
- •II. Contract and Promise: More on the Relationship
- •IV. Harm, Fault, and Remedies for Breach
- •V. Fault and Institutional Harm
- •Conclusion: Toward a Moral Law of Contract
- •I. Breach as Moral Harm
- •III. Moral Norms as Default Rules
- •Conclusion
- •CASE INDEX
- •SUBJECT INDEX
How Fault Shapes Contract Law • 61
than esthetic purposes. The contractor was in a vulnerable position, having incurred substantial sunk costs. Even though the contractor had protected itself to some degree against owner opportunism by insisting on progress payments, the amount owing was still a significant sum. The costs of “mitigating” the breach and replacing the pipe were high because the defective pipe was encased rather than “in shape to be returned.” One could add to Cardozo’s list the fact that owner was a one-shot contractor who might not be concerned about any reputation for opportunistic behavior among other builders, and so might be insufficiently deterred from “holding up” the builder for more money in the absence of court action.
My point is that contract disputes often present questions not only about which party is the best precaution taker, but also about which party is the best mitigator and the most likely opportunist. The case for strict liability is strongest when the promisor is all three. In my view, however, the likelihood that the promisee is more at fault on one or more of these criteria is high enough in litigated cases that courts should not presume that strict liability generally best represents contractual intent.
III. A Fault-Based Approach to Contract Damages
Having addressed the main arguments for strict liability in contract law, based on mutual intent and economic theory, I turn fi nally to the question of the role of fault in contract doctrine. In my view, the language and architecture of contract doctrine strongly reflect the pervasive influence of fault, though not always in obvious ways. In this fi nal section, I focus on a particular area of contract doctrine – contract damages – to show how a seemingly strict liability doctrine in fact leaves ample room for fault considerations.
Th e law of contract damages purports to follow the strict liability paradigm because it claims to focus on the goal of “compensation” for the promisee’s loss. If compensation is the goal, then the reason for the breach must be irrelevant. Contract law then claims expectation damages as the primary compensatory damage measure. The problem is that the apparent dominance of expectation damages as “the” unifying compensatory damages measure is an illusion. Contract law recognizes other compensatory interests, namely, reliance and restitution. Moreover, contract law recognizes a number of “limitations” on expectation damages, including mitigation, foreseeability, and certainty. Courts even have two different ways of measuring expectation damages: cost of completion and diminution in value. What explains the dizzying array of contract damage measures?
62 • George M. Cohen
In my view, the law of contract damages as courts actually apply it is best understood as a fault-based system.15 Courts apply different damage measures depending on the reason the contract fails and the relative fault of the parties. By adjusting the level of damages awarded, courts try to give optimal incentives to both parties. In general, higher damage measures, such as expectation damages and the disgorgement version of restitution, reflect a greater concern with promisor fault. Lower damages measures, such as reliance damages and the reimbursement version of restitution, reflect a greater concern with promisee fault. Contract damages are often undercompensatory relative to the expectation interest because they are as much about deterrence and incentives as about compensation.
More specifically, courts tend to use expectation damages when they believe that the promisor has acted opportunistically, the promisor is the superior mitigator, or the contract otherwise should be performed because it remains jointly profitable. The primary purpose of expectation damages is to deter opportunistic breaches. Expectation damages generally deter opportunistic breaches by depriving the promisor of gain that he has illegitimately expropriated in violation of the parties’ intentions or some broader social norm. This justification for expectation damages is broader than the traditional economic justification for expectation damages, based on the theory of efficient breach, which holds that expectation damages optimally deter inefficient breaches. Inefficient breaches are generally considered breaches involving situations in which circumstances unexpectedly change after the formation of the contract, making the contract sufficiently more costly or less desirable to the promisor that it is no longer profitable for him, although the contract remains jointly profitable. Opportunistic breaches, by contrast, include cases in which no such change occurs. The stated primacy of the expectation damage remedy, of course, makes these extreme cases of opportunism relatively rare; if reliance damages were the predominant contract damage remedy, however, these cases would be more common.
To make this point more concrete, consider four paradigmatic cases of pure opportunistic breach.16 In the first case, the half-completed exchange, one party provides a service to another for an agreed price, but the other party then simply refuses to pay. If the service provider (the promisee) were limited to reliance damages, and these damages are less than the contract
15For a more detailed discussion of the points in the next two paragraphs, see Cohen, NegligenceOpportunism Tradeoff, at 1245–316.
16I discuss these cases in more detail in Cohen, Finding Fault, at 140–54. The examples themselves come from Christopher T. Wonnell, Expectation, Reliance, and the Two Contractual Wrongs, 38 San Diego L. Rev. 53 (2001).
How Fault Shapes Contract Law • 63
price, the paying party (promisor) would always have an incentive to breach because he would, in effect, get the service for less than the contract price. In the second case, one party makes a relationship-specific investment and the other tries to exploit that vulnerability to extort a modification of contract terms. If the extortionist promisor expects that some percentage of vulnerable promisees will agree to the modification and not have the resources to sue later, the promisor will not be deterred from repeatedly attempting extortion if the promisees who do sue are limited to recovering reliance damages. Expectation damages are more likely to deter the repeated extortion attempts. In the third case, an insurer refuses to pay out on insurance after the insured contingency occurs. Reliance damages in this case, if they are defined as simply a refund of the premium, could lead to the collapse of the insurance market, because no insurers would have an incentive to pay out. They would simply keep the premiums of all who suffered no loss and refund the premiums for promisees who suffered losses. The same argument would apply to other contracts with a risk allocation component, such as those with warranty provisions. In the final case, a party with valuable private information contracts with another party. When the less-informed party discovers the information, that party may breach the contract but try to exploit the information in other transactions. Again, if the better-informed promisee is limited to recovering reliance damages, the promisor will not be deterred from the opportunistic expropriation. By contrast, to the extent it captures the value of the promisee’s information to the promisee, the expectation damage measure will deter such opportunistic breaches.
Th e idea that the main purpose of expectation damages is to deprive a promisor of illegitimate gain will strike some as more like the restitutionary goal of avoiding unjust enrichment than the goal of compensation. That depends on how restitution is defined. Sometimes, the restitution remedy is conceived of as a kind of reimbursement. In a half-completed exchange involving goods, rather than services, this version of restitution would simply involve returning the goods, or the money paid. The reimbursement restitution remedy is not sufficient to deter opportunistic breaches. In other cases, however, restitution is conceived of as a disgorgement remedy. That is analogous to the function I see expectation damages as playing. In fact, in some cases, courts will use the disgorgement version of restitution instead of expectation damages where they believe that expectation will not sufficiently deter opportunistic breach.
Courts tend to use reliance damages when breach is nonopportunistic; that is, the promisor breaches not to expropriate some illegitimate gain, but to avoid an unanticipated loss. There are two main examples of nonopportunistic
64 • George M. Cohen
breach, which differ mainly in whether the contract was a bad deal from the outset or became a bad deal only after it was made.17 In the first case, the contract itself is an “accident” or a “mistake,” a contract that should not have been made because it never was jointly profitable, or simply would not have been made if both parties had known all the relevant facts existing at the time. Accidental contracts are distinguishable from contracts in which one party fraudulently induces the other party to enter into the contract by withholding information or providing false information; those contracts that should not have been made are opportunistic breach cases. In the second case, an unanticipated contingency (as opposed to an opportunistically manipulated or exaggerated one) renders the contract not jointly profitable and therefore one that should not be performed. In the absence of promisor opportunism, the failed contract in both cases becomes more like a tort accident; reliance damages are then appropriate, because they aim not at encouraging performance, but rather at encouraging efficient precaution taking to avoid reliance losses. Expectation damages applied in cases of nonopportunistic breach would overdeter promisors; promisors would take too many precautions, including not promising. The real difficulty in these cases is deciding whether opportunism is truly absent, that is, whether the contract really was an unintentional mistake or the regret contingency really was unanticipated. This problem is just another variation of uncertain contractual intent.
Finally, courts use various doctrines that limit damage recoveries, such as foreseeability, mitigation, and certainty, to give promisees incentives to take precautions and mitigate and to deter promisee opportunism. Reliance damages generally have the same effect. In fact, the limitations on expectation damages often leave the promisee with reliance damages or something close to it. To the extent that the reliance damage measure may itself lead promisees to make excessive reliance investments, take insufficient precautions, or engage in opportunism, courts can apply the damage limitations to a reliance damage recovery, or alternatively use the lower reimbursement version of restitution, to restrict the promisee’s recovery.
A fault-based theory of contract damages explains the variety of damage doctrines courts actually use in a unified way that does not depend on ad hoc principles or a resort to measurement difficulties. The theory also explains the predominance of the expectation damage measure. Many litigated cases involve opportunistic behavior by promisors or situations in which the contract remains jointly profitable and the promisor is the superior mitigator. Yet courts and scholars continue to resist the “intrusion” of fault in contract
17 See Cohen, Finding Fault, at 154–63.
How Fault Shapes Contract Law • 65
damages. In the remainder of this section, I consider three important ways that economically oriented scholars have manifested this resistance to a faultbased theory of damages, which is comfortably grounded in economic theory. These paths of resistance are the theory of efficient breach, the critique of the penalty clause doctrine, and the importance of market damages.
Economic theorists have used the theory of efficient breach to justify and explain the privileged position of expectation damages. The theory says that only expectation damages optimally deter inefficient breaches and encourage efficient breaches. To the extent these are important goals of contract law, expectation damages should thus be the dominant damage measure. The problem I have always had with the efficient breach theory is that it takes a reasonable economic concept – efficient nonperformance – and combines it with a controversial commitment to limited court involvement in contract damage determination, that is, strict liability. T he theoretical attraction of the efficient breach theory is that a uniformly applied expectation damage measure avoids costly court determinations of the reason for a particular breach – that is, fault. All a court has to do in a contract dispute is decide whether a contract has been made, whether a breach has occurred, and what the expectation damages are.
In reality, however, the net benefits of this “pricing mechanism” are, at best, far from clear and, at worst, illusory.18 Th e theory assumes that it is generally easier for courts to measure the expectation interest accurately than it is to determine accurately whether a particular breach is efficient. That may not be the case. Some argue that courts can save on the costs of gathering information about fault under a strict liability regime. But contract law has many doctrines that allow introduction of evidence that would be useful for making a fault determination: excuse, promissory estoppel, and good faith, as well as the damage rules already discussed, to name a few. If one of these doctrines is potentially applicable in a particular case, contract law does very little to cut off information relevant to distinguishing among breach types when the parties think it is worth the effort to produce such information. Moreover, a strictly applied expectation damage rule would insufficiently deter some promisor and promisee opportunism as well as insufficiently encourage promisee precaution taking and mitigation. Unsurprisingly, then, contract law has never implemented anything close to the regime the efficient breach theory contemplates. If anything, the law of contract damages is closer to the idea that courts tend to award expectation damages for inefficient breaches and reliance damages for efficient breaches.
18 See Cohen, Finding Fault, at 159–63.
66 • George M. Cohen
Although the efficient breach theory of expectation damages does not describe the contract damage regime we have, it at least has a patina of plausibility to the extent that expectation damages are the predominant remedy. The continuing objection of law and economics scholars to the rule against enforcing penalty clauses19 more directly challenges existing law. T he critique, however, is similarly grounded in the strict liability paradigm and the argument that strict liability best comports with contractual intent. In many contracts, parties do not express their views on damages or other remedies. A seldom acknowledged corollary to this observation is that no court, to my knowledge, has ever held a contract unenforceable on the grounds of uncertainty for lack of a remedy term. In these cases, the contracting parties must expect courts to set reasonable damage default rules, and as I have already discussed, there is reason to think parties expect courts to use fault concepts to determine the appropriate measure of damages, as well as to interpret contracts generally.
But if the parties contract for a liquidated damage clause, then why does the law not always enforce these clauses? One concern is that parties may not have intended the clause to act as a penalty at all; the fact that it has become a penalty may be an “accident.” In addition, the parties may not have intended that a promisee be able to use a penalty clause opportunistically by looking for ways to assert breach, no matter how trivial.20 (A similar concern helps explain contract law’s avoidance of punitive damages, as well as the concern that such damages would too greatly deter promise making.) To critics of the penalty doctrine, however, the doctrine appears anomalous because it seems to single out a particular kind of contract term for special scrutiny and possible nonenforcement. From the perspective of a fault theory of contract, by contrast, strict enforcement of liquidated damage clauses would be the anomaly. Strict enforcement of liquidated damage clauses is a form of strict liability. If strict liability does not make sense generally in contract law, why should we impose it on this one term? Put another way, by not strictly enforcing liquidated damage clauses when they act as penalties, courts treat those clauses the same way that they treat other contract clauses, which are also not strictly enforced regardless of the circumstances and the fault of the parties.
Th e one pocket of contract damage doctrine where strict liability makes sense is market damages, which are based on the difference between the contract price and the market price of a substitute performance at the time of
19See, e.g., Posner, Economic Analysis of Law, at 127–30.
20See Kenneth W. Clarkson, Roger LeRoy Miller, & Timothy J. Muris, Liquidated Damages v. Penalties: Sense or Nonsense?, 1978 Wis. L. Rev. 351, 368–72.