
- •Preface
- •The Self and the Absolute
- •References
- •Introduction
- •The Self and the Absolute
- •References
- •Introduction
- •Nature of the Self
- •References
- •Introduction
- •Nature of the Self
- •References
- •Introduction
- •Introduction
- •Nature of the Self
- •Self-luminosity of the Self
- •Multiplicity of the Self
- •References
- •Introduction
- •Nature of the Self
- •References
- •Introduction
- •Introduction
- •Nature of the Self
- •Introduction
- •The Empirical self
- •References
- •Introduction
- •References
- •Introduction
- •Introduction
- •Nature of the Self
- •References
- •Introduction
- •Nature of the Self
- •Introduction
- •Introduction
- •Nature of the Self
- •References
- •Introduction
- •The Self and s'iva
- •Introduction.
- •Nature of the Self
- •Introduction
References
ksity-rp-tejo marud-vyorna-kala-dig-dehinau mana'i dravyani— Karikavall, 3.
sa dvividhah. jivatma paramfitmi ceti, tatra i.ivarah sarvajnah paramatma eka eva, jivastu prati-sanraih bhinnah—Tarka-samgraha. Ch. I.
jnanadhikaranam atma—Tarka-samgraha. p. 19 ; K. P. Sinha, Nyaya- darsana-vimarsah, PP. 29-30.
sa dvividha'i jivatma paramatma ceti—Tarka-samgraha. p. 19.
vibhur nityas ca ibid p. 20 ; paramanurnpatve tad-gata-jnanadi-pra- tyaksanupapatteh, apakrstaparimanatve .-.aditvena—Vakya-vrtli on Tarka-samgraha. p. 20 ; see Tatparyatika. 1.1.10 and NSB. 3.1.14.
ayaugapadyaj jnananarh tasya nutvam ihesyate—Karikavall, 85.
See Karikavall. 23-24.
buJdhi-sukha-duhkheccha-dvesa-prayatna-dharmfi dharmasamskara- rTirh nirmulocchedo'pavargah— Nya^o-raaJ/ya/-;, Apavarga-prakarara.
NV, 1.1.22 ; see also NSB. 4.1.58.
B. K. Banerji, Bharatlya-dzrSane Muktirad, pp. 95-96.
G. Bhattacb.arya, Studies in Nyaya-vaiseiika Theism, p. 151. :
See 8 above.
IP, vol. II, p. 153.
NV, 3.1.1. '
Va sesika-sutra, 3.2.4—13 ; Ip, Vol. II. pp. 189-190.
samanadhikaranyam ca smaranar.ubhavadi.su anusandhiyamiinain yad drsyate tat katharh bhavet—Nyaya-matijari. II, p. 7.
sanrasya na caitanyarh mriesu vyabhicaratah—Karikavall, 48 ; see Muktavall on ibid and NSB, 3.1.4.
tathatvarh ced indrijanam upaghale kathEm smrtih—Karikavall, 48 ; see N)aya-manjarl, vol. II, p. 13 and NSB. 3.1.1., 3.2.18. ;
mano'pi na tatha jndnadyanadhyak$arii tada bhavet—Karikavall. 49 ; sse Muktavall on ibid, and NSB. 3.2.19.
See NsB. 2.1.1-5 and IP, Vol. II, p. 147.
jivas tu prati sarlrarh bhinnah-Tc;ka-scriigraha. pp. 19-20 ; See Sinha. op dt, pp. 33-34.
Nyaya-kusumanjali, p. 270 ; see IP, Vol. II, p. 159.
CHAPTER
8
THE SELF IN SAMKHYA
Introduction
According to the Old Sgmkhya found in the Bhdgavata-the Visnu-Puraya etc., the purusa or self and prakrti, the material of the world, are not the ultimate realities ; they are nothing but the manifestations of Bhagavat, the Absolute— otherwise called Vi§nu or Narayana—or of his power, and are therefore dependent upon him1. In the Classical Sarhkhya, however, the world has been explained only with reference to purusa and prakrti described as two distinct and independent principles. No mention has here been made to. any other reality higher than these two principles. Accordingly, it is generally held that according to the Classical Sgmkhya, purusa and prakrti are the fundamental realities. Of them, puru$a means the self, while prakrti is the ultimate material out of which the world evolves.
Nature of the Self
According to Sarhkhya, the purusa or self is a pure spirit entirely different from prakrti and its evolutes. The self is, thus, beyond the three qualities—sattva, rajas and tamas— belonging to prakrti, and is, consequently, pure and free from merits, demerits, pleasures, pains, delusion, attachment, aversion desire etc. According to the Naiyayikas, qualities like pleasure, pain, etc. belong to the self. The Sarhkhyists, on the other hand, hold that these are the qualities of antah-karana,
The Self in SUmkhya 51
but are falsely ascribed to the self2. The self in its real nature is beyond all empirical attributes. It is simple or uncom-pounded, and is neither the cause nor the effect of anything. The self is unchangeable and immutable. It is eternal in the sense that it is not affected by the change of time, and that it is an uncaused ultimate principle. It is independent and is not supported by anything else. The self is of the nature of consciousness. The fundamental point regarding the nature of the self is that it is always the subject of knowledge, and never an object of it3. The self possesses the power of discrimination, and witnesses the modifications of prakjti. Consciousness, however, is not a mode or attribute of the self, as some philosophers like the Naiyayikas opine, but is the very essence of it. The self should not be regarded as blissful consciousness also, because bliss and consciousness, being different entities, cannot be the essence of the same reality. Further, bliss is but another name of pleasure which belongs to prakrti and, as such, cannot be the essence of the purusa4. Thus, the puru?a is devoid of any and every characteristic of the empirical world ; its nature is absolute and pure consciousness. And, as it is of the nature of pure consciousness, it is sada-prakasa-svarupa or always self-manifesled. The self is not anything of the world of objects : it is differents from matter or the material body, the senses, the mind and the intellect. The self is different from matter, because the latter is the known, the former is the knower. It is different from the senses, since the latter are the instruments of knowing, while the former is the subject thereof. It is different from the manas, because the latter is active and composed of gunas, while the former is inactive and devoid cf guffas. It is different from the buddhi, since the latter is unconscious, while the former is conscious. Though the purusa is thus different from all these elements, it lies behind them all: it holds together all the different stages of an individual and illuminates the whole sphere of thought and feeling5.
Hiiiiliiliininw iiini llllllll||[|iii(|fj|!!||||||||||||||||||||pj||||||||
52 The Self in Indian Philosophy
The purusa is not of limited magnitude or madhyama-parimana. If it were so, it would be made up of parts and would, consequently, be destructible. Neither can it be atomic in magnitude , because an atomic serf cannot account for the fact of our cognition throughout the whole body. Thus, by the method of residue, the self should be regarded as of unlimited size or vibhu-parimana i.e. all-pervasive6.
The puru$a is not kartSt or agent, because it is entirely passive or devoid of activity, all activities belonging to prakfti and its products. Actions or movements that seem to pertain to the purusa are only aupadhika or conditional. The self being related to the body, the movement of the latter is ascribed to the former, just as the movement of a pitcher is ascribed to ghatakaSa or the akaSa confined by a jar7. Thus, kartftva or agency is not natural to the self. But though not karta or agent, the self is bhoktft or enjoyer. Actually, however, enjoyment is also not natural to the self; it is ascribed to the empirical self because of abhimana or the egoistic sense which, on its part, is born of aviveka or non-discrimination8. When true knowledge arises, all the qualities like pleasure, pain, agency, enjoyment etc. wither away, while only pure consciousness remains. In its real nature, the self is eternally free and perfect. Bondage and liberation, birth and death, pleasure and pain—all belong to prakfti, and not to the self9.
A world-creator Igvara having been denied by the Sgmkhyists, the purusa cannot be said to have any relation to Isvara, either as his part or as identical with him. Vijnana Bhiksu, however, regards Brahman, the universal consciousness,, as the Absolute, and advocates a relation of difference-cum-identity between the self and Brahman. In his view, in the state of bondage, the self is different from Brahman, but in liberation, the former realises its identity with the latter10.
According to the Sarhkhyists, the self is not one, but many ;. it is different in different organisms. The manifoldness of the self is established by the Samkbyists on the ground of the
53
difference of empirical facts like birth, death etc. It is thus said, ''As birth, death and sense-organs are different in different individuals, as all are not simultaneously engaged in actions, and as the three qualities are found to exist in different individuals in different grades, the self should be accepted as many"11. It is, however, to be noted that the arguments put forward by the Samkhyists prove the multiplicity of the empirical self, and not of the transcendental self. The Mgdhvists have led this position to its logical conclusion to. show the multiplicity of the transcendental selves also.
REFERENCES
cf. etad bhagavato rupam brahmapah paratnatmanah param pradha- narhpurusam—BP, 3.29.36 ; Isvareccha-vasalj so'pi jivatma katbyate budhaih—Matsya Parana, 3.27.
para-dharmatve'pi tat-siddhira-vivekat—SS, 6. 11 ; see Aniruddh^-vrtt and Bhasya on SS, 6.2.10, and S/fand STK, 11.
SK, STKanl Yukti-dlpika, 11.
naikasyananda-cid-rnpatve dvayor bhedat—SS, 5.66 ; see SK and STK,
19.
SS. 6.2, 2.29 ; SK, STK and Yukti-dlpika. 17.
SS. 1.50 ; IP. Vol. II, p. 281.
SK, 19: niskriyasya tad-asambhavat—SS, 1.49. See SK, 20, 22 and SS, 1.51, 1.162 and 1.163.
STK, 21 ; SS, 105.
9. SS, 1.107 and 6.28 ; SK, and STK, 62 ; IP, Vol. II, p. 286. .10. SS, 5.116.
11. SK, 18.
Illllliliillllllllllilllllllllililllillllllllllllllllillllllllllllllllll IIIIIHIIIIIIIH
liij"'1' III "Wv
CHAPTER
9
THE SELF IN YOGA ( pATANJALA-YOGA )