
- •Introduction. XI
- •Introduction. XlH
- •14. Exclusive and Jealous Spirit. ВЂ” Some reservation
- •19. Greek Pedagogy. ВЂ” Upon that privileged soil of
- •21. The Schools of Athens. ВЂ” The Athenian legislator,
- •In the final passage of this cutting dialogue, observe the
- •Infirm constitution, — Plato does not go so far as ordering
- •In the Laws, Plato explains his conception of religion. He
- •Is above all an education in art. The soul rises to the good
- •Very skilful discipline which, by way of amusement, 2 leads the
- •41. Faults in the Pedagogy of Aristotle, and in
- •In a disinterested pursuit of a perfect physical and intellectual
- •Inspires respect. Coriolanus, who took up arms against his
- •45. Rome at School in Greece. ВЂ” The primitive state of
- •Is the fatal law of mysticism, is that Saint Jerome, after
- •Ing to the rules of our holy religion, but, in addition, to teach
- •1 The following quotation illustrates this servile dependence on authority:
- •83. Abelard (1079-1142). ВЂ” a genuine professor of
- •94. The Theory and the Practice of Education in
- •Ing the Bible, to reading, and writing. They proscribed, as
- •105. Intellectual Education. ВЂ” For the mind, as for
- •109. Religious Education. ВЂ” In respect of religion as of
- •Violence ! away with this compulsion ! than which, I certainly
- •127. Double Utility op Instruction. ВЂ” a remarkable
- •129. Criticism of the Schools of the Period. ВЂ” But
- •130. Organization of the New Schools. ВЂ” So Luther
- •128 The history of pedagogy.
- •143. Sense Intuitions. ВЂ” If Comenius has traced with a
- •It secured a footing in Paris, notwithstanding the resistance
- •Vigilance in order to keep guard over young souls, and there
- •Vigilance, patience, mildness, — these are the instruments
- •170. Faults in the Discipline oe Port Royal. ВЂ” The
- •183. All Activity must be Pleasurable. ВЂ” One of the
- •Important tone : " How dare you jeer the son of Jupiter?"
- •It must certainly be acknowledged that, notwithstanding
- •201. The Discourse of Method (1637). ВЂ” Every system
- •In other terms, Descartes ascertained that his studies,
- •190 The history of pedagogy.
- •203. Great Principles of Modern Pedagogy. ВЂ” With-
- •In a word, if I may be allowed the expression, some affect
- •205. Malebranche (1638-1715). ВЂ” We must not expect
- •209. Some Thoughts on Education (1693). ВЂ” The book
- •Is, in fact, but another name for duty, and the ordinary
- •It fluently, but if not, through the reading of authors. As
- •V themselves into that which others are whipped for."
- •Is like repose and a delicious unbending to the spirit to go
- •227. Education in the Convents. ВЂ” It is almost exclu-
- •1 Greard, Memoire sin- V ' enseiynement secondaire desfilles, p. 55.
- •254. Different Opinions. ВЂ” Rollin has always had warm
- •255. Division of the Treatise on Studies. ВЂ” Before
- •It may be thought that Rollin puts a little too much into
- •242 The history of pedagogy.
- •259. The Study of French. ВЂ” Rollin is chiefly preoccu-
- •1 Rollin does cot require it, however, of young men.
- •It is in the Treatise on Studies that we find for the first
- •261. Rollin the Historian. ВЂ” Rollin has made a reputa-
- •If the scholar is not ready, he shall return to his desk with-
- •Is it possible to have a higher misconception of human
- •Ideal, — from the pleasant, active, animated school, such as
- •302. The Pedagogy of the Eighteenth Century. ВЂ”
- •288 The history of pedagogy.
- •In its successive requirements to the progress of the faculties.
- •309. Romantic Character of the вЈmile. ВЂ” a final ob-
- •Institutions."
- •317. Proscription of Intellectual Exercises. ВЂ” Rous-
- •318. Education of the Senses. ВЂ” The grand preoccupa-
- •324. Excellent Precepts on Method. ВЂ” At least in the
- •300 The history of pedagogy.
- •333. The Savoyard Vicar's Profession of Faith. ВЂ”
- •334. Sophie and the Education of "Women. ВЂ” The weak-
- •342. Preliminary Lessons. ВЂ” We shall quote, without
- •Value of certain portions of them. The general characteris-
- •344. Othek Parts of the Course of Study. ВЂ” It
- •345. Personal Reflection. ВЂ” What we have said of Con-
- •346. Excessive Devotion Criticised. ВЂ” What beautiful
- •375. Expulsion of the Jesuits (1764). ВЂ” The causes of
- •It would be interesting to pursue this study, and to collect
- •380. Secularization of Education. ВЂ” As a matter of
- •1708, " That fathers who feel an emotion that an ecclesiastic
- •Inevitable, while it shall be entrusted to persons who have
- •382. Intuitive and Natural Instruction. ВЂ” a pupil of
- •395. Aristocratic Prejudices. ВЂ” That which we would
- •Ital?" And he adds that " the only means for attaining an
- •414. Mirabeau (1749-1791). ВЂ” From the first days of
- •430. The Legislative Assembly and Condorcet. ВЂ” Of
- •It is necessary that women should be instructed : 1 . In order
- •467. Pedagogical Methods. ВЂ” Lakanal had given much
- •Versational lessons.
- •498. How Gertrude teaches her Children. ВЂ” It is
- •509. The Institute at Yverdun (1805-1825).ВЂ” In 1803
Is, in fact, but another name for duty, and the ordinary
synonym of virtue, — honor may assuredly be the guide of
an adult and already trained conscience ; but is it not chi-
merical to hope that the child, from his earliest years, will be
sensible to the esteem or the contempt of those who surround
him? If it were possible to inspire a child with a regard for
his reputation, I grant with Locke that we might henceforth
" make of him whatever we will, and teach him to love all
the forms of virtue " ; but the question is to know whether
we can succeed in this, and I doubt it, notwithstanding the
assurances of Locke.
Kant has very justly said : —
" It is labor lost to speak of duty to children. They com-
prehend it only as a thing whose transgression is followed by
the ferule. ... So one ought not to try to call into play with
children the feeling of shame, but to wait for this till the
PHILOSOPHERS OF THE SEVENTEENTH CENTUET, 201
period of youth comes. In fact, it cannot be developed in
them till the idea of honor has already taken root there."
Locke is the dupe of the same illusion, both when he
expects of the child enough moral power so that the sense of
honor suffices to govern him, and when he counts enough on
his intellectual forces to desire to reason with him from the
moment he knows how to speak. For forming good habits
in the child, and preparing him for a life of virtue, there is
full need of all the resources that nature and art put at the
disposal of the educator, — sensibility under all its forms,
the calculations of self-interest, the lights of the intelligence.
It is only little by little, and with the progress of age, that
an exalted principle, like the sentiment of honor or the senti-
ment of duty, will be able to emerge from out the mobile
humors of the child, and dominate his actions like a sovereign
law. The moral pedagogy of Locke is certainly faulty in that
it is not sufficiently addressed to the heart, and to the
potency of loving, which is already so great in the child. I
add, that in his haste to emancipate the child, to treat him as
a reasonable creature, and to develop in him the principles
of self-government, Locke was wrong in proscribing almost
absolutely the fear of punishment. It is good to respect the
liberty and the dignity of the man that is in the child, but it
is not necessary that this respect degenerate into supersti-
tion ; and it is not sure that to train firm and robust wills, it
is necessary to have them early affranchised from all fear
and all constraint.
214. Condemnation of Corporal Punishment. — It is
undeniable that Locke has not sufficiently enlarged the liases
of his theory of moral discipline ; but if he has rested incom-
plete in the positive part of his task, if he has not advised
all that should be done, he has been more successful in the
202 THE HISTORY OF PEDAGOGY.
negative part, that which consists in eliminating all that
ought not to be done. The chapters devoted to punishments
in general, and in particular to corporal punishments, count
among the best in the Thoughts. Rollin and Rousseau have
often copied from them. It is true that Locke himself has
borrowed the suggestion of them from Montaigne. The
"severe mildness" which is the pedagogical rule of the
author of the Essays, is also the rule of Locke. It is in
accordance with this that Locke has brought to bear on the
rod the final judgment of good sense : " The rod is a slavish
discipline, which makes a slavish temper." He has yielded
to the ideas of his time on only one point, when he admits
one exception to the absolute interdiction of the rod, and
tolerates its use in extreme cases to overcome the obstinate
and rebellious resistance of the child. This is going too far
without any doubt ; but to do justice to the boldness of
Locke's views, we must consider how powerful the custom
then was, and still is, in England, in a country where the
heads of institutions think themselves obliged to notify the
public, in the advertisements published in the journals, that
the interdiction of corporal punishment counts among the
advantages of their schools. "It is difficult to conceive
the perseverance with which English teachers cling to the old
and degrading customs of corrections by the rod. ... A
more astonishing thing is that the scholars seem to hold to it
as much as the teachers." "In 1818," relates one of the
former pupils of Charterhouse, " our head master, Doctor
Russell, who had ideas of his own, resolved to abolish
corporal punishment and substitute for it a fine. Everybody
resisted the innovation. The rod seemed to us perfectly
consistent with the dignity of a gentleman ; but a fine, for
shame ! The school rose to the cry : ' Down with the fine !
Long live the rod ! ' The revolt triumphed, and the rod was
PHILOSOPHERS OF THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY. 203
solemnly restored. Then we were glad-hearted over the
affair. On the next day after the fine was abolished, we
found, on entering the class-room, a superb forest of birches,
and the two hours of the session were conscientiously em-
ployed in making use of them." 1 ' 2
215. Intellectual Education. — In what concerns intel-
lectual education, Locke manifestly belongs to the school,
small in his time, but more and more numerous to-day, of
utilitarian teachers. He would train, not men of letters, or
of science, but practical men, armed for the battle of life, pro-
vided with all the knowledge they will need in order to keep
their accounts, administer their fortune, satisf\' the require-
ments of their profession, and, finally, to fulfill their duties as
men and citizens. In a word, he wrote for a nation of trades-
men and citizens.
216. Utilitarian Studies. — An undeniable merit of
Locke is that of having reacted against a purely formal in-
struction, which substitutes for the acquisition of positive
and real knowledge a superfluous culture, so to speak, a
training in a superficial rhetoric and au elegant verbiage.
Locke disdains and condemns studies that do not contribute
directly to a preparation for life. Doubtless he goes a little
1 Demogeot et Montucci, de l'Kneeigneme?it secondaire en Angleterr< .
p. 41.
2 On the question of corporal punishment in school, is not M. Compayre
too absolute in his assumptions? On what principle does he base his
absolute condemnation of the rod ? What is to be done in those cases of
revolt against order and decency that occur from time to time in most
schools? There is no doubt that the very best teachers can govern without
resorting to this hateful expedient ; but what shall be done in extreme rases
by the multitude who are not, and never can be, teachers of this ideal
type? Nor does this question stand alone. Below, it is related to family
discipline; and above, to civil administration. If corporal punishment is
interdicted in the school, should it not be interdicted in the State ? (P.)
204 THE HISTOBY OF PEDAGOGY.
too far in his reaction against the current formalism and in
his predilection for realism. He is too forgetful of the fact
that the old classical studies, if not useful in the positive
sense of the term, and not satisfying the ordinary needs of
existence, have yet a higher utility, in the sense that they
may become, in skillful and discreet hands, an excellent
instrument for intellectual discipline and the education of the
judgment. But Locke spoke to fanatics and pedants, for
whom Latin and Greek were the whole of instruction, and
who, turning letters from their true purpose, wrongly made
a knowledge of the dead languages the sole end, and not, as
should be the case, one of the means of instruction. Locke
is by no means a blind utilitarian, a coarse positivist, who
dreams of absolutely abolishing disinterested studies. He
wishes merely to put them in their place, and to guard against
investing them with a sort of exclusive privilege, and against
sacrificing to them other branches of instruction that are
more essential and more immediately useful.
217. Programme of Studies. — As soon as the child
knows how to read and write, he should be taught to draw.
Very disdainful of painting and of the fine arts in general,
whose benign and profound influence on the souls of children
his colder nature has not sufficiently recognized, Locke, by
way of compensation, recommends drawing, because drawing-
may be practically useful, and he puts it on almost the same
footing as reading and writing.
These elements once acquired, the child should be drilled
in the mother tongue, first in reading, and afterwards in
exercises in composition, in brief narratives, in familiar
letters, etc. The study of a living language (Locke recom-
mends French to his countrymen) should immediately follow ;
and it is only after this has been acquired that the child shall
be put to the study of Latin. Save the omission of the
PHILOSOPHERS OF THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY. 205
sciences, Locke's plan is singularly like that which for ten
years has been in use in the French lycВЈes.
As to Latin, which follows the living language, Locke
requires that it shall be learned above all through use,
through conversation if a master can be found who speaks