Добавил:
Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:

coons_c_weber_m_eds_paternalism_theory_and_practice

.pdf
Скачиваний:
0
Добавлен:
29.10.2019
Размер:
3.32 Mб
Скачать

Paternalism and the principle of fairness

151

The arguments I have pressed would not support coercive imposition of the scheme on those who would prefer not to cooperate with it. The legitimate choices the cooperators have in this scenario are to limit the scope of the scheme and exclude the non-cooperators from the benets or to include the non-cooperators in the scheme and tolerate their free riding.

Suppose instead that exclusion is impossible or unfeasible but No Choice fails to hold. For simplicity, just take the case in which the public-good-provision scheme provides all in the group the opportunity to consume a good but each beneciary may choose either to consume the good or decline consumption. For example, suppose the public-good scheme provides an unguardable well for a village, which gives each village member the opportunity to get water from the well if she chooses. Now suppose there are some in the village who do not value the good provided and do not avail themselves of it. Intuitively, it seems these noncooperators are not gaining benets from the scheme, are not free riders, and hence may not legitimately be coerced into paying their share of the costs of the scheme. Suppose the non-cooperators are making a mistake here: They are foregoing water consumption, but they would be advantaged if they did take advantage of the scheme and did drink the water. Here at last we have a case in which anyone opposed to paternalistic restriction of liberty will see strong moral reasons not to block the mistaken non-cooperators from acting on their own judgment about their own good and to force them to contribute to a scheme they reject. But this is a deviant case, not the standard case where both No Choice and No Exclusion obtain. Rejecting coercion to force unwilling beneciaries to benet and pay when No Exclusion obtains but No Choice does not and consumption is optional for each individual potential consumer is not rejecting the amended principle of fairness, just forcing a small clarication of it, which I provide in a footnote.16

In considering such cases, we need to be careful in describing the goods provided. Providing the opportunity for someone to have water if

16The nal amended version of the HartRawls principle: When a number of persons engage in a just, mutually advantageous cooperative venture according to rules and thus restrain their liberty in ways necessary to generate non-excludable and non-optional benets for all, those who have submitted to these restrictions have a right to similar acquiescence on the part of those who have beneted from their submission, at least when failure to acquiesce in this way will impose costs on the cooperators. If the goods provided are non-excludable but optional, those who do not exercise the option of taking the goods provided do not acquire obligations under this principle. (On paternalist grounds it might be urged that in some cases in which people by mistake would choose not to take the optional provided goods, they should nonetheless be forced to take and pay for their own good. This further argument would not appeal to the principle of fairness.)

152

richard arneson

she wants it is itself a good, which may be valuable to a person who never has occasion to take the water. In the cases described above, someone who does not actually take water from the public well provided by a cooperative scheme may still benet from having the back-up option to use the well if her other sources of water should dry up. In the previous paragraph, we are supposing the non-cooperators do not avail themselves of the opportunity to take water and also are not, or do not judge themselves to be, better o by having the No Choice opportunity provided.

To this point I have challenged Wellmans claim that forcing people to contribute to public-good-provision schemes they do not voluntarily embrace would necessarily be paternalistic. (The forcing would be paternalistic only in the special case just discussed, and there is a natural interpretation of the amended principle of fairness that disallows the forcing in this special case.) Wellman is focusing on the particular case of the imposition by a state of a coercive scheme requiring all within its jurisdiction to obey the laws and contribute to the cooperation needed to sustain the rule of law; I simply assert that my arguments about the general case apply to this particular example.

no hard paternalism?

So far my claim has been that enforcing the principle of fairness is not paternalistic, so cannot be objectionably paternalistic. Just suppose that claim is false, and that enforcement of the principle of fairness in some standard cases would be either paternalistic or close to paternalistic. What would follow? Let us consider cases in which enforcement would qualify as hard paternalism, restriction of a competent adult persons voluntary choices against her will for her own good. Would such paternalism be morally unacceptable? The topic that opens up here is too broad for this essay. I limit myself to three remarks.

If enforcement of the principle of fairness does not squarely fall into the category of paternalism but only lies somewhere near it, we should note that the moral reasons against paternalism, whatever they may be, may fade away or become diluted as we move from core instances to more marginal cases. On this ground alone we might judge the anti-paternalism case against the principle of fairness to be weak.

A second comment is that even if we uphold a strong moral presumption against paternalism, when paternalism is necessary to provide a person a decent minimum of real freedom in her life, the presumption

Paternalism and the principle of fairness

153

may be overridden. If what is at issue is the claimed obligation of the individual to support a state that provides the essential public goods of law and order and basic physical security, the goods being provided are very large. Anarchy along with a general breakdown of peoples willingness to respect one anothers moral rights is a disastrous condition. Anyones e ective or real freedom to decide on any of a broad array of worthy courses of action and carry out the chosen course of action with a reasonable prospect of success will be very low under anarchy. If there is a moral obligation to bring it about that so far as is feasible, everyone has at least a minimal good enoughlevel of real freedom, this obligation arguably will override whatever moral presumption stands against paternalism.

A third comment is that at the level of fundamental moral principle, there may be no presumption at all against paternalistic restriction, at least when paternalism enhances the prospect that the restricted individual will live autonomously and well. Morality may include a strong benecence requirement, and the requirement to promote the good may encompass a duty to promote peoples real freedom especially when their real freedom would sink to disastrous levels absent our aid. The sensible version of anti-paternalism is perhaps not in play at the level of fundamental moral requirements but only shows up at the level of practical policy guidance, the lore needed to fulll fundamental principles as well as we can.17

is paternalism morally objectionable?

The discussion so far does not lay to rest the suspicion that there is something deeply wrong with paternalism per se, such that if an action or policy is correctly classied as paternalistic, that automatically renders it the case that the action or policy is morally impermissible unless there are overwhelming countervailing considerations in play. Is this so? Here is an argument to that conclusion:

Each person has the moral right to do whatever she chooses with whatever she legitimately owns (provided she does not thereby wrongfully cause harm to others). Having such a right entails that one is at liberty to act and others have a moral duty not to interfere. Now add the premise that each person is the full, rightful owner of herself. So, each

17 This is how J. S. Mill argues in On Liberty. For criticism of Mills anti-paternalism from a prioritarian perspective, see Arneson, Paternalism, Utility, and Fairness.

154

richard arneson

person has the moral right to destroy herself, to inict any lesser harm on herself, and to act in ways that court or risk bringing about harm to herself. From these premises it follows that paternalism (restricting someones liberty, against her will, for her own good) is morally impermissible. If the right in question is absolute, exceptionless, then paternalism is never permissible.

The aws in this argument against paternalism reveal considerations that weigh in favor of paternalism.18 The crucial aw is that the claim that each person is the full, rightful owner of herself, at least as interpreted here, is implausible. This idea of self-ownership is that each person has full sovereignty and control over herself (unless she has ceded some sovereignty and control by her voluntary consent), and is permitted to act at will in any way that a ects her body or future life, and also has the moral power to transfer this extensive bundle of rights over herself, in whole or in part, to another person. One sign that this conception of self-ownership rights is inated is that common sense denies that one has the moral power to sell oneself into slavery or to make oneself the slave of another person.

There is no conceptual oddity in attributing property rights in oneself to each person, but it makes more sense to hold that such rights are limited. Any duties one has to help others can be construed as limited property rights that other people in need have in ones body. These limit self-ownership. But my moral liberty to act as I choose is also limited by duties to myself. Just as one who holds property in land is not best regarded as having the moral right to destroy it at will but instead as having stewardship duties to preserve the land as well as various rights to use and consume it, so too one has, so to speak, stewardship duties along with rights of self-ownership.

One source of such duty is ones rational agency capacity; being a (partly) rational agent, one has duties to seek out the reasons that bear on ones choices of action and to act for reasons. Another source of duty is that each person has the opportunity to live a life, and barring tragic circumstances, this is a tremendous opportunity to do good for self and others, which one is not morally at liberty to squander. Each person is under a vague, loose, but signicant duty to make something worthwhile of the opportunity he or she has to live a life and is bound not to waste or squander this opportunity. Although an act-consequentialist principle interprets this duty strictly, on most accounts of morality the duty to

18 For further argument, see Arneson, Joel Feinberg and the Justication of Hard Paternalism.

Paternalism and the principle of fairness

155

make something useful of ones life goes with great discretion to do this in any of a great variety of ways. A duty to do something worthwhile with ones life is not equivalent to a maximizing duty to do the most good one can with the opportunities one has. This is a duty owed to oneself, but not a duty one can waive on ones own behalf, and though limited in its demands, when severely neglected it opens the doors to enforcement. If I am wasting my life, I am violating social norms and this triggers informal penalties as appropriate. Using certain mind-deadening drugs that tend to degrade ones rational faculties while o ering too little enjoyment and other benets in return can render me appropriately subject to criminal law penalties. Suicide on a whim, for no good reason, is banned in morality as well as in law.

Duties to make something worthwhile of ones life interact with duties of benecence that we owe to one another (and so are owed by others towards oneself) to draw boundary lines setting limits to ones autonomy and allowing, and in extreme cases mandating, paternalistic interference. If I am making bad decisions and ruining my life, at some threshold of badness I am violating the duty to make something worthwhile of my life. From the side of other persons who are in a position to act to make my life go better, one should note that they have a duty to respect my autonomy, my authority to decide for myself how to conduct my own life, which includes the right to make mistakes and learn from them (or not), up to some point. But again there is some threshold of badness, some point beyond which ones life is becoming a mess of spoiled fruit, and others become morally permitted, and then at some further point perhaps mandated, to prevent further rot if there are available ways to do that that are morally cost-e ective. (How these thresholds interact and where they might be located are topics for another occasion.)

In these brief remarks I intend to do no more than indicate a plausible and promising pathway along which one might proceed, to mount a convincing defense of the commonsense ideas that paternalism is sometimes morally permissible and sometimes morally required. I make no attempt to show how a plausible moral principle regulating permissible paternalism would treat the issue of the moral permissibility of enforcement of the principle of fairness, because I deny that such enforcement would trigger the application of such anti-paternalism norms as there are. But if you believe that enforcing the principle of fairness would be paternalistic or exhibit features that are very like paternalism, this belief should be no bar to holding that enforcing the principle of fairness can be entirely morally appropriate.

156

richard arneson

conclusion

This chapter has defended the HartRawls principles of fairness as justifying the duty to obey the law, in a broad range of cases. The defense has proceeded mainly by clarifying what the principle a rms and by introducing minor amendments to enable the principle to avoid objections that do not go to the heart of the matter. Even if successful, this chapter does not advance a knockdown argument for the principle; it simply knocks down some bad inuential objections.

chapter 8

Paternalism in economics

Daniel M. Haybron and Anna Alexandrova

introduction

Economists are notoriously averse to paternalism. Yet the reigning methods of policy analysis in normative economics frequently counsel profoundly paternalistic policies. Or so we shall argue.

We take our cue from the current debate over the use of happiness and other psychological measures of well-being in economics. The debate concerns those who take happiness to be a relevant policy consideration, employing the methods of psychology to study the impact of economic policies on well-being, and those who dont. We will call the former approach happiness-driven economics (HDE) and the most important variety of the latter minimalism.1 Minimalists argue that economics should minimize its normative commitments by adopting a preference-satisfaction theory of well-being and a decision procedure based solely on optimizing preference satisfaction; and, crucially, minimizing its use of psychological notions, relying instead on an austere methodology of revealed preference – “choice,in a loose manner of speaking.2 Happiness-driven economics need not take happiness to be the sole, or even a central, focus of normative economics; it may see it only as one signicant concern among others. But it does trade freely in psychological notions like happiness, asserting that economic policy analysis must go beyond a narrow focus on choice behavior. For convenience, our discussion centers on happiness,using that term

For their helpful discussion and feedback on earlier versions of this paper, we wish to thank audiences at the Freedom, Paternalism, and Moralityworkshop at Bowling Green State University and the Law and Happinessworkshop at Saint Louis University, as well as John Helliwell, Neil Thin, Richard Arneson, Douglas Husak, Bonnie Wilson, and Matthew Cashen.

1One need not be a minimalist to oppose HDE, but minimalism exemplies the main strand of opposition within economics. As well, our chief target in this paper is the minimalist exclusion of psychological phenomena generally from economics, not just happiness.

2Loose, because revealed preference does not distinguish between choices and other forms of behavior, including involuntary behavior; indeed, thermostats make choicesin this sense.

157

158 daniel m. haybron and anna alexandrova

loosely to refer to mental states like subjective well-being, life satisfaction, or emotional well-being, which have dominated recent discussion of well-being policy. However, the argument more broadly concerns the use of well-being indicators for policy, and the points made about happiness will generally apply to well-being regardless of which of the major theories of well-being is adopted.

Happiness-driven economics has been widely accused of paternalism, particularly by friends of minimalism. Such critiques, we will argue, are well founded in relation to some forms of HDE; but the objections fail regarding other varieties of HDE: There is nothing inherently paternalistic about happiness-driven economics.

The question of paternalism in HDE raises broader questions, however, about the potential for paternalism in economic policy analysis. We do not deny that paternalism is sometimes justied to help people achieve what they value. And avoiding paternalism, even where it isnt warranted, can be surprisingly di cult. But one approach that especially lends itself to deeply objectionable forms of paternalism, ironically, is minimalism. This claim will occupy the lions share of the paper. Doubling the irony is the fact that HDE can be an important tool for avoiding paternalism. In short, the minimalist critics of HDE have gotten things almost exactly backwards when it comes to the avoidance of paternalism. Even where HDE genuinely o ends anti-paternalist sensibilities, few of the measures actually proposed for HDE even approach the extent to which minimalist policies can disregard the highest priorities of their supposed beneciaries, indeed amounting to hard paternalism.

We want to stress at the outset that our target is by no means the whole of mainstream economics. To a great degree our criticisms aim not at economists but at policy-makers and agencies who have taken up principles inspired by minimalism in setting policies. Nor are we calling for a revolution in economics. For all we shall argue, introductory economics classes might proceed largely as before. Indeed, minimalist principles might remain appropriate for substantial parts of economics; we do not claim that the entire eld needs to engage with psychological research. Note that plenty of economists have already abandoned minimalism, and might regard our discussion as congenial to their e orts. Yet our target, minimalism, nonetheless constitutes a huge strain of economic thought, inuencing even many of those who do not fully accept it.

We begin with a characterization of minimalism. Then, using a broad denition of paternalism, we examine the anti-paternalist credentials of minimalism and nd them wanting. Finally, we consider how policy-makers

Paternalism in economics

159

might avoid, or at least minimize, paternalism, arguing that HDE should be part of a less paternalistic approach to policy analysis.3

what is minimalism?

In standard economics minimalism takes the form of two commitments: epistemological and normative. In this paper we focus on the latter, but it will help to briey characterize epistemological minimalism. It stresses observability, precision, and parsimony.4 Observability is a requirement that applies to economistscharacterization of preferences. According to the Revealed Preference Methodology (hereafter RPM), unobservable psychological quantities, such as happiness, commitments, or other mental states, should not be part of economic theory or economic explanations. Heres a recent endorsement of RPM:

Economic phenomena consist of individual choices and their aggregates and do not include hedonic values of utilities or feelings. Therefore, it is not relevant for an economic model to explore the feelings associated with economic choices. The point of revealed preference theory is to separate the theory of decision making from the analysis of emotional consequences of decisions.5

And more strikingly:

Populating economic models with “flesh-and-blood human beings,was never the objective of economists.6

Gul and Pesendorfer provocatively embrace the term mindless economicsfor this minimalist view of their eld: Minimalist economics is, literally, mindless economics.

Normative minimalism is a set of implicit principles of welfare economics. It purports to keep value commitments to a minimum, if not to avoid them altogether, notably by orienting normative economics solely towards the satisfaction of preferences, and thus (ostensibly) deferring to individualsown value judgments. Normative minimalists usually adopt an actual preference satisfaction theory of well-being and welfarism, the view that only well-being is morally signicant. These assumptions are not an explicit part of economic theory and there are certainly economists who do not endorse them. But

3A couple of caveats: For convenience, we will sometimes speak loosely of policy analyses as being paternalistic, even if paternalism only emerges in their application. Second, our discussion of HDE sets aside concerns unrelated to paternalism such as the reliability of happiness measures (see Haybron, The Pursuit of Unhappiness), and does not try to mount a general defense of HDE.

4See Alexandrova and Haybron, High-Fidelity Economics,for more on epistemological minimalism.

5 Gul and Pesendorfer, The Case for Mindless Economics,40.

6 Ibid., 43.

160 daniel m. haybron and anna alexandrova

they are so common as to be denitive of standard welfare economics; or, as Edward Glaeser recently put it, they constitute the moral heart of economics:

Improvements in welfare occur when there are improvements in utility, and those occur only when an individual gets an option that wasnt previously available. We typically prove that someones welfare has increased when the person has an increased set of choices. When we make that assumption (which is hotly contested by some people, especially psychologists), we essentially assume that the fundamental objective of public policy is to increase freedom of choice.7

Of course, providing policy recommendations requires more than the preference theory of well-being and welfarism. We also need principles for aggregating individual preferences at a societal level. Here, normative minimalists have two procedures to o er: the Pareto Principle and CostBenet Analysis (hereafter CBA). Since the Pareto Principle has a very narrow range of application (that is, only to cases where there are no losers from a proposed policy), we shall concentrate on CBA.

In its classic form, CBA is a minimalist procedure par excellence. It requires only one extra step beyond Pareto e ciency: An outcome favored by CBA is a potential Pareto improvement if the losers under the proposed policy could be compensated by the winners, a condition known as Kaldor-Hicks e - ciency. CBA attempts to provide a decision criterion without relying on any interpersonal comparisons of psychological states, without incorporating moral and political values, without engaging in any deliberation about the relative merits of the policy proposals in question, and often without even actually talking to or otherwise communicating with the a ected parties. Instead, CBA proposes that we canvass actual raw preferences for a policy, often using nothing more than past choices in similar situations as the indicators of preferences. Once the preferences of all a ected parties are represented by the present monetary value and aggregated (without consideration of their comparative wealth or any other morally relevant factors), the benets of adopting a project must be compared to its costs.

This standard form of CBA has elicited much criticism and many proposed xes for its shortcomings.8 Nevertheless, in its classic formulation CBA retains

7Glaeser, The Moral Heart of Economics.

8See Hausman and McPherson, Economic Analysis, Moral Philosophy, and Public Policy for a summary of the criticisms, and papers from a 2000 issue of the Journal of Legal Studies, collected in Adler and Posner, eds., Cost–Benefit Analysis, for proposed xes to classic CBA (Sunstein, Cognition and CostBenet Analysis) or the impossibility of such xes (Nussbaum, Costs of Tragedy; Richardson, The Stupidity of the CostBenet Standard). Adler and Posner, New Foundations of Cost–Benefit Analysis; Orr, Values, Preferences, and the CitizenConsumer Distinction in CostBenet Analysis; and Schmidtz, A Place for CostBenet Analysis,provide qualied defenses of CBA.