Добавил:
Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:

учебный год 2023 / A secret paradox of common law

.pdf
Скачиваний:
1
Добавлен:
19.12.2022
Размер:
1.27 Mб
Скачать

A Secret Paradox of the Common Law

Author(s): Richard Bronaugh

Source: Law and Philosophy, Vol. 2, No. 2 (Aug., 1983), pp. 193-232

Published by: Springer

Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3504794

Accessed: 06/10/2008 14:30

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=springer.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Law and Philosophy.

http://www.jstor.org

Copyright ?1983
0167-5249/83/0022-0193
193-232.
$04.00.

RICHARD BRONAUGH

A SECRET PARADOX OF THE COMMON LAW*

ABSTRACT. This essay recounts a fascinating if complicated piece of AngloAmerican debate. My aim is to reach a conclusion about the importance of the notion of changing one's normative position as part of the act of "giving sufficient consideration" for a legal contract. In several journals and textbooks between 1894 and 1918 the major contract scholars of the time, e.g., Langdell, Anson, Pollock, Williston, Ames, and Corbin, discussed a special example which was thought to reveal a paradox in the common law of consideration. The problem had shown itself in the textbooks of Pollock in England and Langdell in the United States. The example is of two contracts made by three persons in which one contract with the third party repeats the content of an existing contract with the second party. It would appear that the party at the pivot experiences no new detriment in merely performing, or promising to perform, his pre-existing duty. If so, such oblique contracts with third parties must fail for want of consideration extended from the first party. About this difficulty the experts were anything but agreed. The cases were not consistent. At the root of this uncertainty is an ambivalence about

the concept of consideration itself. Should it be conceived in terms of normative relations and changes of moral position or should it be conceived

in valuative terms, as harms and benefits? The differences of opinion about

the legal validity of oblique contracts is explained by this ambiguity, one which the common lawyer has not yet resolved.

In his 1880 Summary of the Law of Contracts, Harvard's first Law

Dean, Christopher Columbus Langdell, presented an analysis of consideration which turned out to be logically circular. The defini-

tion itself was simple: "The consideration of a promise is the thing

given or done by the promisee in exchange for the promise."l Consideration, of course, is essential to a common-law contract.

Langdell, in explaining his definition, made clear that "the thing

* This paper was written while holding a Social Science and Humanities Research Council of Canada Leave Fellowship, for which I express my

gratitude.

1 Summary of the Law of Contract (1880), Section 45, p. 58.

Law and Philosophy 2 (1983)

by D. Reidel Publishing Co., Dordrecht, Holland, and Boston, U.S.A.

If the detriment

194

RichardBronaugh

given or done" must be a legal detriment to the giver or doer. He wrote, for instance,

a person does not in legal contemplation, incur any detriment by doing a thing which he was previously [legally] bound to do, but he does incur a detrimentby givinganother person the right to compel him to do it, or the right to recoverdamagesagainsthim for not doing it. One [legal] obligation is a less burdenthan two (i.e. one to each of two persons), though each has to do the samething.2

"To Professor Williston," wrote Henry W. Ballantine, "belongs

the credit of having pointed out the question-begging fallacy in Langdell's theory."3 Indeed, in 1894 Samuel Williston, Harvard's great contracts lawyer, noticed about bilateral contract considera-

tion that "[u]nless a promise imposes [a legal] obligation no promise whatever can be considered a detriment. It is therefore

assuming the point at issue to say a promise is a detriment because

it is binding."4

Fifteen years before Williston's discovery, Sir William Anson had noticed the same difficulty in SirFrederickPollock's Contracts published in 1876.5 One can find observations in O. W. Holmes's The Common Law, of 1881, which contain or suggest the same circularity. He wrote, imagining two people wagering over a past fact: "It is ... a detriment to undertake to be ready to pay if the event turns out not to have been as expected."6

both creates and results from the contract, there is circularity of reasoning. Because the problem can be extended to all agreements,

2Langdell, Section 84, p. 105. Note that unilateraland bilateralcontracts, for Langdell,are treated differently; only the bilateralone with the external personwill havevalidconsideration.

3Henry Winthrop Ballantine, 'Mutualityand Consideration,'HarvardL.R.

28(1914): 123.

4SamuelWilliston,'SuccessivePromisesof the SamePerformance,'Harvard

L.R. 8 (1894): 35.

5See WilliamAnson, Principlesof the English Law of Contract (Oxford: ClarendonPress,1878), p. 80.

6The CommonLaw (1881), pp. 304-5.

The Common Law

195

Pollock came to speak of a secret paradox in the common law.7 Langdell's claim, and the three-person, two-contract frame in which it was set ("one to each of two persons"), became the focus of a remarkable controversy in the pages of the Harvard Law

Review.

 

1. A PARALLEL

TO THE SOCIAL CONTRACT

This logical problem in the

analysis of the theory of common-law

consideration

is

parallel

to

one noticed about some theories of

social

contract. It might

be said that there are no obligations

except

insofar

as

there is a

social contract to ground them. The

obligation in

the

exchange

of promises itself may then be said

either to derive from the resultant contract (in which case there is

circularity

of reasoning)

or

to be

independent

of the

contract

entirely

(in

which case

the

social

contract

does

not

explain all

obligations).

This dilemma is, for example,

suggested

by

Hume in

his essay Of the Original Contract.9

Let me anticipate

the con-

clusion

of

the argument

of this essay.

It is my purpose to recount

a fascinating

piece of Anglo-American

intellectual

history

with the

ulterior

aim of reaching

a conclusion

about

the importance of the

7 Sir Frederick Pollock in an unsigned review in L.Q.R. 30

(1914): 129,

describedit as "one of the secret paradoxesof the CommonLaw."Pollock

was led to addin the eighthedition of hisPrinciplesof Contracts,p. 191, "In fact there is no conclusivereasonother than convenienceof so holding, for the rule that promise and counter promisewill make one anotherbinding; for neither of them, before it is known to be bindingin law, is in itself any benefit to the promiseeor burdento the promisor."

8 The discussionwas initiated by Willistonin 1894 and effectively endedin the journalwith anotherarticlein 1914 by Williston.Corbin,in my opinion, hadthe lastword in 1918 in the YaleLawJournal.The whole debateengaged the best legal minds of the time. Holmes,Pollock, and Anson are enduring figures;Langdell,Ames, Ashley, and Ballantinewere or would be prominent Deans; Willistonand Corbinwere the two greatestcontractslawyersNorth Americahasproduced.

9 See Hume's Essays Moral and Political (1748).

196

RichardBronaugh

idea of changingone's independentnormativepositionas partof the act of "giving sufficient consideration"to bring a legal contract into existence. One of the subplots of this story is the reluctanceof lawyersto recognizethis dimensionof common-law contractformation.The moralof the tale is that classicalcontract

formation, especially of the bilateral kind (i.e., in which only promises are exchanged), cannot explain considerationmerely from within the force of the contractitself and must - however

little appreciated- depend upon independentnotions of obliga-

tion derivedfromthe ideaof

 

as a moralact.

 

promising

2. THE PRECISE QUESTIONS

AND SOME TERMINOLOGY

Early in the Harvarddebate one writer raised the question of considerationas "benefitto the promisor"and set it in the same

two-contractframe -

a test case for the

theory

of

three-person,

 

in his

 

of

considerationused

 

 

 

 

previouslyby Langdell

explanation

how legal detrimentis created. Assume that B and C have an existingbilateralcontractandB hasnot yet performedA,. a third party, has a strong interest in seeing B perform. PerhapsB is hesitatingand may breach.A approacheshim andoffersa second contract for the same performancealreadyowed to C. Edmund Bennittasked:

What supports a promise by A to pay B for doing exactly what B was already bound to do by a prior contract with C? Whatnew consideration,loss, or detriment to B exists in such cases?Is not the promisebindingon A solely from the supposedgain, advantage,or satisfaction ensuing to him from performanceof the promise,and without any increasedamage,loss or cost to B than havealreadybeen paidfor by C?10

had denied-

see the

quotation

-

that a unilateralcon-

Langdell

 

 

 

10 Edmund H. Bennitt, 'Is Mere Gain to a Promisora Good Consideration

for his Promise?'HarvardL.R. 10 (1896): 261. Bennitt could support his view well by citing Englishcases, not U.S., notably Shadwellv. Shadwell (1860), 9 C.B.N.S.159 and Scotsonv. Pegg(1861), 6 H. & N. 295.

The Common Law

197

tract11 could be createdobliquely, even by the beneficialvalue

experiencedby

the

A from the

of the B

 

promisor

performance

party. A new detrimentto B is required.So a repeatedpromise would be consideration,creatingthe addedlegaldetrimentin the bilateral context. The above test case raises two issues: Does

benefit to the

count as considerationin

any context,

but

 

promisor

 

especiallyin the unilateral?Whatis the natureof detrimentalconsiderationin bilateralcontractformation?

To save

I shall

adopt

the

 

repeatinglong descriptiveexpressions,

 

following terminology for use hereafter,which I hope will be perspicuousin itself. In the above test case for consideration,I shallsay that the B-placeparty is in a pivotal position.I shallsay that B's originalcontractwith C is for a designatedperformance.

B's new

with the external

A for the

designated

 

arrangement

party

performanceis an oblique contract, whether it is unilateralor bilateral.For the questionof pre-existingdutyto beraisedproperly the two contracts,originaland oblique, must be over the same designated performance,whether promised or executed. If an original contract called for drivingin the GrandPrix while the oblique one is for winningthe race, there is not one designated performance;if the oblique were bilateral then failure to win wouldbe a breachwhereasit wouldnot be on theoriginalcontract,

whichcalled

for

the race.

only

 

driving

In the circumstancesof the test case,when the obliquecontract

is proposed,the designatedperformancemust be executory (i.e.

on the pivotal(B) party'sside.The originalcontract unperformed)

(B to C) is probablybilateral,while an oblique contract(withA)

can be eitherbilateralor

 

but is

 

 

the latter.For

B has

 

unilateral,

probably

 

 

 

C to drivein the GrandPrix

(the original

example,

promised

B to

 

 

bilateral

andA has

pay

himif he does

(an

contract)

 

promised

 

 

 

oblique unilateralcontract). When there is an oblique bilateral

contractovera

then the

will

 

designatedperformance,

pivotalparty

promiseto the externalpartythat which he had promisedto do

11 A contract in which one side gives an action other than a promise as considerationfor the promiseof the other side.

198

Richard Bronaugh

under the

original. The precise question, then, is this: Can the

same promise once given originally in the formation of a contract, if repeated to another party before the designated action is per- formed, be new consideration in the formation of a second or oblique contract with an external party?

Turning to B's action respecting an oblique unilateral contract, there is one self-identical action susceptible to several operative descriptions, e.g., acceptance of a unilateral contract offer from A, formation of a unilateral contract, execution or.discharge by performance of two contracts (one unilateral with A and the other

with C probably bilateral) or giving consideration to A in the uni- lateral contract.12 Being a conceptually plural act, a description must be chosen which counts for the question at stake. When there is an oblique unilateral contract, B's pivotal action discharges by performance his original contract with C and, in the same stroke, aims to form a contract with the external party A. So this is the precise question: Can the same action designatedandgiven in execution of an original contract be consideration in the forma- tion of an oblique contract with an external party?13

Recast in terms of benefit and detriment, one asks, does the pivotal party suffer some detriment for the sake of contract formation with an external party in executing, or in promising to execute, an originally designated duty? One may ask of the exter-

12 I am assuming that

the oblique unilateral contract is executed on the

pivotal side. It could be

executed on the external side. That

is a situation

to which I shall return in discussing Corbin's view below.

 

13 The action designated in the original contract is of course

an action per-

formed in satisfaction

of the obligation of the original contract. However,

the external

party will

usually be interested in the designated performance

as the

action

itself rather than as an action in

satisfaction of the other con-

tract.

(The distinction

is not always possible,

e.g., where there is an original

contract to marry.) I have stated the precise questions in terms of the action itself; restatement would be required when the external party requests the performance of the original contract and would not otherwise be interested in the action itself. An example would be where someone wants another to "keep his word" and bargains for that as such.

The Common Law

199

nal party whether it should count that he receives some benefit

from the execution, or from the promise of execution, by the pivotal party of a designated duty. If one denies validity to all oblique unilateral contracts, as Langdell did, then one must also disallow valuable benefit to the promisor. If one denies validity to all oblique bilateral contracts, then one must find no added detriment in repeating a promise to a new party and count no benefit to a new party in receiving it. This position has been taken, as shall be seen.

3. TWO POSSIBLE SOLUTIONS

The Promise Itself

James BarrAmes, Langdell's.successoras Harvard'sDean, suggested that "the consideration in bilateral contracts is the promise and

not the legal obligation

of each party. ..

14 He wrote:

 

 

Is not

the

 

...

...

Everyone

will

 

 

alleged question-begging purely imaginary?

 

concede that the considerationfor every promise must be some act or forbearancegiven in exchange for the promise.The act of eachpromiseein the case of mutual promisesis obviously the giving of his own promiseanimo contrahendiin exchangefor the similarpromise of the other. ... This, then, mustbe the considerationfor each promise..... s

About the particular problem of oblique contracts, Ames's answer was as generous as his overall theory was seemingly simple. All such contracts have consideration in the detriment experienced by

the party who performs, or promises to perform, the pre-existing duty.16 If there is consideration, the only bar to contract would be some matter of public policy. And there is no public policy

14James BarrAmes, 'Two Theories of ConsiderationII,' HarvardL.R. 13 (1899): p. 34.

15Ibid.,pp. 31-32.

16Ames's conclusion was against the tide in America at the time. "It must be conceded," he wrote, "that in this country a majority of the decisions and dicta are opposed to the [English] doctrine...", 'Two Theoriesof ConsiderationI,' HarvardL.R. 12 (1899): 520.

200

Richard Bronaugh

objection per se to oblique contracts. Although there will probably be benefit to the promisor - something judges often mention, especially in unilateral contract contexts - it is never relevant, for the necessary and sufficient test of consideration is detriment to the promisee from the making of a promise, or from the performance of an action.

Ames's theory of bilateral contract consideration and so his

solution to the paradox, it is sad to say, was not well understood. Mr. Justice Holmes, for example, in a letter to Pollock, said that Ames's notion of consideration as "the act of speaking(utterance)" was "absurd."17 Ballantine was to declare, repeating what several others had said before: "But it seems fanciful to suggest that mere words, movements of the lips, vibrations of the vocal chords, the

act of signing one's name, are the consideration requested."18

Lawyers at this stage were in some difficulty, especially with respect to the bilateral contract. The promise one gives in accept- ing an offer unfortunately cannot be the giving of something that

is a legal detriment; it was brought home in most quarters that that kind of detriment only comes as a result of a contract's

successful formation. It cannot be consideration. To avoid circu-

larity of reasoning must the parties then be thought to trade onerous noises? The very idea of a bilateral binding exchange certainly had something paradoxical to it. Of course Ames, for his part, did not mean that the utterance qua physical movement or oral effort was the detriment given in making a bilateralagreement. He had said that one gives one's promise and so there is "a change

of position on his part."19 But missing is a development of that idea by Ames, so it is perhaps not strange that others took him

wrongly.

17 The Pollock-Holmes Letters, Volume I, ed. Mark DeWolfe Howe (Cam-

bridge, 1942), p. 177.

18 Henry Winthrop Ballantine, 'Is the Doctrine of Consideration Senseless

and Illogical?' Michigan L.R. 11 (1913): 427. 19 Ames, 'Two Theories I,' p. 515.

The Common Law

201

Moving in Legal Circles

 

Clarence D. Ashley, Dean of the New York University

Law School,

did look closely at the notion of a promise. Ashley declared,

we should look at each supposed promise with a view to its legal requirements, and we then conclude that each is a promise if it meets our profes-

sionalconception.... Thereis no beggingthe question in sucha process.20

The layman's use, the one which Ames apparently had meant, seems nothing but "mere words of promise to which no legal con-

sequence

can attach

..."21

But

Ashley says,

speaking as a profes-

sional lawyer, "promise and contract do not

differ as terms, for a

promise

is

a

contract."22

This

solution attacks

the problem of

circularity

in

bilateral contexts

by

declaring

it to be a technical

feature

of the law and so to be virtuous, not vicious.

The

question

is how professional

training

enables one to spot

the "promise

in law." The answer is, "We must

employ our legal

acumen."23

 

Yet on his view the

ordinary

person must possess

some

of

that

kind

of acumen,

for contract's

self-containment

20ClarenceD. Ashley, 'Whatis a Promisein Law?'HarvardL.R. 16 (1903):

21Ibid., p. 322.

22Ibid., p. 321. As a claim about what is true by definition within the

standard discourse of the guild, counterexamples suggest themselves.The expression "gratuitouspromise,"a commonplacein legal literature,must be

to

legal circles,

or else it is a contradictionin

a lay expressioninappropriate

 

terms. Languagelike "a promise that is not binding is of no value" (from

Williston)is either tautologous or nonprofessional.Morecasually,one lawyer says to another, "Thatpromiseyour client made, it will neverbe enforced; the plaintiffwill fail." Suchtalk does not fit Ashley's strictures.

23 Ashley, 'Whatis a Promisein Law?' p. 321. In so far as most laws are addressed to nonprofessionals,not just lawyers, purely technical conceptions cannot be a desideratumof all law. Thereis, one mustsuspect, a certain despair in the appeal to acumen. In another essay, a decade later, Ashley concluded that "consideration"cannotbe defined. But he did not add that it

is therefore the subject of professionalintuition. Instead, he said it should be legislatedout of the law. See his 'The Doctrine of Consideration,'Harvard

L.R. 26 (1913): 429-36.

Соседние файлы в папке учебный год 2023